Two concepts of equality Paul Dumouchel Ritsumeikan University 56-1 Toji-in, Kitamachi, Kita-ku, Kyoto JAPAN

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Two concepts of equality Paul Dumouchel Ritsumeikan University 56-1 Toji-in, Kitamachi, Kita-ku, Kyoto JAPAN"

Transcription

1 Two concepts of equality Paul Dumouchel Ritsumeikan University 56-1 Toji-in, Kitamachi, Kita-ku, Kyoto JAPAN 1

2 When reading current literature on equality and justice it is possible to recognise that it resorts to at least two different concepts of equality that we generally confuse or at least fail to distinguish. Concepts of equality, it is important to note are different from practical goals and political issues such as political or economic equality or equal opportunity or which inequalities, if any, are just, or legitimate, or should be allowed? Concepts of equality are cognitive tools, they are ideas concerning the nature of equality as such that underlie the way in which be think about these issues and that guide us in the decisions we reach concerning them. They should not be identified with the issues themselves. Failure to distinguish the two concepts of equality has lead, I believe, to confusion concerning the relationship between these different practical and theoretical issues. In particular it has been one cause of the priority often given to economic equality over political equality, or to social rights over political rights. It has been a cause of the common belief that political equality is merely formal while economic equality is real. In this paper I want to challenge this common prejudice in the following way. I will argue that the political concept of equality constitutes a much better tool for thinking about issues of inequality even and perhaps especially issues of economic inequality. Even in Rawls, who has done so much to limit the priority of economic equality over political equality, the different concepts of equality remain indistinct. This may explain some of the difficulties in the interpretation of his work. However, my goal is not exegetical but methodological: it is to show that there are two different concepts of equality between which authors often go back and forth and that we should distinguish between them. We should distinguish between them because one of them is a much better tool to think about issues of justice and equality, leaving them indistinct leads to confusions and misunderstandings. In fact, I will argue that one of these two concepts is incoherent, but that incoherence does not appear until the two concepts of equality are clearly distinguished. I propose to call the first of these two concepts of equality the political concept of equality 1 and the other the concept of complete equality. In the first part of this paper, I start from three conceptions of equal opportunity and work my way back to the concept of equality that underlies them. In the second part I analyse this concept and show that it is essentially political. Part three introduces the concept of complete equality and traces its evolution through various recent texts and authors. In part four, I analyse complete equality and distinguish it from the concept of political equality. Finally part five argues that the concept of complete equality is incoherent. 2

3 1. Equality and three conceptions of equal opportunity Allen Buchanan, Dan W. Brock, Norman Daniels, & Daniel Wikler in Chapter 3 of From Chance to Choice. Genetics & Justice (Cambridge 2000), their book on justice in relation to present and foreseeable future developments of genetic technologies distinguish three conceptions of equal opportunity which they view as alternative interpretations over which authors disagree. The first they name Formal Equality of Opportunity. It requires, they say, the removal of formal and legal barriers that limit equal access to careers, professions, government offices and to all desirable social roles and functions. Characterised in this way, formal equality of opportunity is, as they note, closely related to what historically has been understood by the slogan careers open to talents. 2 The second conception of equal opportunity that they identify retains the prerequisites of formal equality of opportunity to which it adds the central requirement of removing or compensating the different types of informal social discrimination that prevent equal access to different roles and functions. This can be called material equality of opportunity. Under a natural interpretation, the aim of material equality of opportunity can be seen as fulfilling the conditions necessary in order for careers to be really opened to talents. Clearly, even when equality of opportunity is legally entrenched, discrimination or prejudices can prevent members of various groups from having access to many positions, occupations and benefits. Material equality of opportunity is necessary if equality of opportunity is not to remain a purely formal provision that masks real inequality of opportunity. Under this interpretation, material equality of opportunity does not send back to a concept of equality that is different from that which underlies formal equality of opportunity. Contrary to what our authors suggest when they talk of alternative interpretations, material equality of opportunity simply corresponds to a greater awareness of the conditions necessary in order for equal opportunity, understood as careers open to talents, to be realised. However, according to Buchanan et al., material equal opportunity remains insufficient if careers really are to be open to talents. Equality of opportunity requires even more they argue. This third conception of equal opportunity, which we can characterise as real equality of opportunity, they name following John Roemer (1996), the level playing field concept of equal opportunity. 3 Real equality of opportunity, they tell us, requires not only the elimination of legal and informal barriers of discrimination, but also efforts to eliminate the effects of bad luck in the social lottery on the opportunities of those with similar talents and abilities. 4 In other words, real equal opportunity demands not only the elimination of legal and formal barriers, plus measures to combat discrimination and the effect of prejudices, but it also requires policies that compensate for the effects of existing social inequalities on the life prospects of various individuals, i.e. bad luck in the social lottery. 3

4 These three conceptions of equal opportunity can be viewed as deriving from one and the same concept of equality, one that is expressed or at least suggested by the slogan careers open to talents. Central to this idea of equality is the requirement that a person s access to different roles or positions should be limited only by his or her abilities. Each of the three conceptions of equal opportunity corresponds to a different social extension of the concept and to a growing understanding of what is necessary in order for the requirements implied in the core idea to be implemented. Formal, material and real equal opportunity are like three concentric circles, representing the shock wave of this idea of equality as it gradually invades the social fabric. First, it is assumed that removing legal and formal obstacles to equal opportunity is enough in order to open careers to talents. When that is revealed insufficient, steps are taken to prevent discrimination and to reduce other informal barriers that defeat the goal of equal opportunity. This corresponds to material equality of opportunity. Finally, real equality of opportunity sets out to level the playing field, to even out differences in the starting point that result from existing inequalities. 5 In all these cases the goal remains the same: that a person s access to different positions and benefits should only be limited by his or her abilities. What changes is the importance of the measures that we believe are necessary in order to reach that goal. As we move from formal to real equality of opportunity the requirements necessary to implement the goal defined by careers open to talents become stronger and the social consequences of doing so more important. Formal, material, and real equal opportunity correspond to practical issues, to real states of affair which have been or which we want to realise in the world. All three of them, from the weakest to the strongest conception of equal opportunity can be viewed as rooted in the same concept of equality. A concept that, I will argue, is essentially political. 2. Careers open to talents and the political concept of equality Which idea of equality, if any, motivates the call that career should be open to talents? Rawls in paragraph 12 of A Theory of Justice (1971) criticises the conception of equality as career open to talents and it may be useful before carrying on to review his criticism. Rawls central objection is that this conception of equality permits distributive shares to be improperly influenced by factors so arbitrary from a moral point of view. (p. 72) What Rawls has in mind, is that the slogan careers open to talents is compatible with considering natural differences in talents as a sufficient justification of social inequalities. It is true that career open to talents can be viewed as leading to a form of moral meritocracy in at least two ways. Under a strong interpretation, agents deserve the more important positions and higher benefits they obtain only if their 4

5 capacities are superior. In other words, given that social competition is fair, unequal capacities justify unequal benefits. On a weaker interpretation, agents only deserve what they get, whatever that is, if it results from the unfettered autonomous use of their abilities. That is to say, social inequalities can only be justified if social competition is fair. In the first case, under the strong interpretation, differences in ability directly justify social inequalities. They constitute a sufficient condition of legitimate inequalities. Under the second, weaker interpretation, social inequalities can be justified only if the process through which they arise is such that they can reflect natural differences in talents. In this case careers open to talents, rather than differences in talents themselves, constitutes a necessary, but not sufficient condition of legitimate inequalities. Rawls also claims that careers opens to talents leads to a basic structure of society, the system of natural liberty, which he judges inferior to the basic structure recommended by his two principles of justice. One of the reasons why Rawls reaches that conclusion is because he considers that careers open to talents does not imply any provision concerning the passage of time. As a consequence the results of past fair competitions accumulate and create between agents important inequalities that trump the very ideal of equality that gives rise to them. But since there is no effort to preserve an equality, or similarity, of social conditions, except insofar as it is necessary to preserve background institutions, the initial distribution of assets in any period of time is strongly influenced by natural and social contingencies. The existing distribution of income and wealth, say, is the cumulative effect of prior distribution of natural assets that is, natural talents and abilities as these have been developed or left unrealized, and their use favored or disfavored over time by social circumstances and such chance contingencies as accident and good fortune. 6 However, as we have just seen, this need not be the case. Rigorously applied careers open to talents requires not only formal, but also material and real equality of opportunity. In itself it is sufficient to justify the requirement that we compensate for the effects of bad luck in social lottery. Or to put this in a slightly different way efforts to preserve equality insofar as it is necessary to preserve background institutions may have consequences that are much more important that what Rawls suggests. This said, there are two criticisms here on the part of Rawls and they should be distinguished. The first one is that careers open to talents leads to the system of natural liberty. This I have argued is not the case. Rawls accusation rests on an unjustified premises, that careers open to talents does not imply anything concerning the cumulative effect of prior distribution of natural assets and perhaps on an insufficient distinction between the idea itself and the way in which, historically, it was implemented. 7 The second one is that it allows inequalities that are arbitrary from a moral point of view. I have not yet responded to this criticism. 5

6 Why should careers be open to talents? What is wrong with a social arrangement that forbids or limits this? In political and social situations where careers are not open to talents certain groups or individuals are excluded from some professions, roles or social benefits. Who excludes them? It may be the laws or customs or religion, but in a sense it is always other groups or individuals that exclude them, other individuals and groups that profit from and uphold the laws or customs that limit the opportunities open to women, to foreigners or to members of various religious, ethic or social minorities. Such situations imply the existence of privileges in the classical sense of the word, of private laws that allow certain individuals or groups to impose their private will upon other individuals or groups. In other words, these situations imply political inequality in the sense of some being subjected to the private will of others. By the private will of others I mean that when careers are not open to talents there are rules of exclusion to which agents who are morally equal would not agree. Such rules of exclusion are arbitrary. To the opposite morally equal agents can agree to a rule that limits access to various positions on the basis of the agents competence. Political equality it will be said is equivalent to equality before the law. Not quite, political equality implies equality before the law but it is not implied by it. Equality before the law is not in itself a sufficient guaranty of political equality. Equality before the law alone fails to prevent that some agents, for example in virtue of their wealth or of their social standing, may exert disproportionate influence upon the political decision process in consequence excluding others from participating. In order to protect the integrity of the political decision process, political equality will therefore recommend in such cases special rules that limit the influence of these factors. Political equality cannot be reduced to equality before the law because, as our discussion of equal opportunity has shown, not only laws can constitute barriers or exclude agents and subject them to rules to which morally equal agents would not agree. Careers open to talents is a direct expression, a requirement of the ideal of political equality. Rawls was afraid that it could tolerate the existence of inequalities that are arbitrary from a moral point of view. It is likely that he is right. The political concept of equality suggests that morally arbitrary inequalities should only be limited if they lead to political inequality. Contrary to what Rawls suggest at time and to a common belief, political inequality properly understood can exercise very strong constraints upon permissible economic and other social inequalities. From the point of view of political equality such inequalities are in themselves neither legitimate, nor illegitimate as long as they do not lead to political inequality. As Rawls once said: The natural distribution is neither just nor unjust; nor is it unjust that persons are born into society at some particular position. These are simply natural facts. What is just or unjust is 6

7 the way that institutions deal with these facts. 8 Why then did Rawls also write that the most obvious injustice of system of natural liberty is that it permits the distributive shares to be improperly influenced by these factors so arbitrary from a moral point of view? Why is that such an obvious injustice? Why can t distributive shares be influenced by factors that are morally arbitrary? How is improperly influenced to be construed if it is not equivalent to leading to political inequality? 3. Brute luck and equality. Having distinguished the three conceptions of equal opportunity that I presented in part 1, Buchanan, Brock, Daniels & Wilker (2000) go on to argue that there are two variants of the third conception of equal opportunity, what I have called real equality of opportunity, and that, following Roemer (1996), they name the level playing field conception of equal opportunity. It is in this second variant that we will discover at work a different concept of equality. The main difference between these two variants, they tell us, lies in the reasons that justify why we should compensate agents who have experienced bad luck in the social lottery. According to the first variant, which they call the social structural view, that reason is because how someone fares in the social lottery is significantly influenced by the ongoing effects of past injustice. 9 In other words, according to this first variant the reason why we should compensate an agent born into an underprivileged group is because the disadvantage from which he or she suffers in terms of equal opportunity is to some extent the result of past injustice. If we did not compensate this disadvantage we would actually perpetuate the injustice and in consequence give undue advantage to some other individual or group. 10 The second variant, they argue, is based on a different assumption: the moral intuition or considered judgement that persons should not have lesser opportunities as a result of factors that are beyond their control, in the sense of being unchosen. 11 In other words, according to this view it is not because they suffer from the cumulative result of past injustice that we should compensate those who have lost out in the social lottery but because their disadvantage is no fault of their own. According to them, even if Rawls is one of the primary advocates of the social structural conception, this alternative view can also be found in his work. For example, in A Theory of Justice (1971) though he affirms the superiority of the liberal interpretation of the two principles of justice over the system of natural liberty, Rawls nonetheless rejects the liberal interpretation because it still permits the distribution of wealth and income to be determined by the natural distribution of abilities and talents. Within the limits allowed by the background arrangements, distributive shares are decided by the natural lottery; and this outcome is arbitrary 7

8 from a moral perspective. 12 Later on he adds: There is no more reason to permit the distribution of income and wealth to be settled by the distribution of natural assets than by historical and social fortune. 13 In a just society, our access to different roles and positions should not be determined by our success in the social, any more than in the natural lottery. Buchanan, Brock, Daniels & Wilker interpret these and similar passages from Rawls as indicating that, according to him, benefits and inequalities that result from factors over which a person has no control have no moral basis. The underlying idea, they suggest, is that it seems unfair that an agent should be at a disadvantage because of something that is no fault of his or her own. Following T. Scanlon (1989), our authors call this the brute luck view of the level playing field conception of equal opportunity. Buchanan, Brock, Daniels & Wilker s main interest is with respect to justice issues raised by the capacity of genetic technologies to transform the results of the natural lottery. The appeal of the brute luck view is to them evident, as it seems to extend very naturally and simply from questions of justice concerning the social lottery to justice with regard to the natural lottery. However, before directly addressing these issues they also provide a short genealogy of the brute luck view. From Rawls, they trace the history of this conception to two famous articles published by Richard Dworkin in 1981: What is Equality? Part I Equality of Welfare and What is Equality? Part II Equality of Resources. In those articles Dworkin argues in favour of equality of resources over equality of welfare. According to him, one of the reasons why equality of resources is preferable to equality of welfare is because equality of resources takes into account the natural distribution of talents while equality of welfare does not. That is to say, in the unfortunately now received jargon, equality of resources factors in the original distribution of non-transferable productive assets among a population. If it is true, as Rawls (1971) argued, that an individual s life prospects should not be determined by the morally arbitrary natural distribution of talents, then we should, according to Dworkin, compensate agents who have received fewer talents. He then considers two schemes of compensation. Without entering into the technical details of these methods of compensation, the point that is important to our discussion is that in these two articles Dworkin postulates a type of equivalence between natural assets and social benefits. He considers that natural assets should also be taken into consideration by theories of distributive justice and he proposes mechanisms to even out differences among agents of nontransferable personal goods, that is to say talents. Rawls had argued that the difference principle represents, in effect, an agreement to regard the distribution of natural talent as a common asset and to share in the benefits of this distribution whatever it turns out to be. 14 But he also claimed that the distribution of natural assets is a fact of nature and no attempt is made to change or even 8

9 to take it into account. 15 Dworkin for his part believes that we should take this fact into account and, if we cannot change the unequal distribution of natural assets, we should at least compensate in some way those who have been unlucky. However, Dworkin did not carry to its logical conclusion the transformation of personal assets into objects of distributive justice. He refrained from doing so for a moral reason directly related to the intuition that, according to the authors of From Chance to Choice, is at the hearth of the conception of justice underlying the brute luck view: a person should not have lesser opportunities as a result of factors that are beyond his or her control. Dworkin maintained that while agents should be compensated for their lack of talent or poor abilities, they should also be held responsible for their expensive tastes or preferences. That is to say, if talents and natural abilities are morally indifferent, tastes and preferences are not. Contrary to natural endowments, they reflect personality characteristics for which an agent can be held responsible. Unlike talents, tastes and preferences are not simply things that happen to us, original assets that are given to us at birth, but the result of past decisions and actions. In consequence, if our preferences are expensive and difficult to satisfy, it cannot be said that it is no fault of our own and therefore we cannot claim to be compensated for them. Like talents, preferences and tastes are personal resources or liabilities. They also make it harder or easier for a person to achieve certain goals or to attain a given welfare. Nonetheless Dworkin maintained a clear moral difference between talents and preferences. The first, because they are morally arbitrary factors should be compensated and their consequences evened out among agents. The second should not. Because they are under the agent s responsibility they can ground no claim of inequality. However John Roemer in The Equality of Talents (1985) questioned the stability of this distinction between talents and preferences. While the main thrust of his article is to reject Dworkin s claim that equality of resources is preferable to equality of welfare, in the process he also undermines the sharp distinction between talents and preferences. His argument to this effect rests a large extent on the fact that mathematically we can always portray agents who have different preferences as agents who have similar preferences but over an extended list of goods. As George J. Stigler and Gary S. Becker had already demonstrated a long time ago, differences in preferences among agents can always be represented as differences between prices of objects, production cost or information available to agents who have similar preferences. 16 It follows that there is no fundamental difference between preferences and talents, nothing to ground the moral distinction Dworkin sought to establish. Since different preferences, Roemer argued, can always be expressed as differences in talents, in the information available to agents or in production cost there is no reason to maintain a strong moral distinction between talents and preferences. From a 9

10 less technical point of view we can ask: Is it really plausible to maintain that there is a radical difference between our talents for which we are not responsible, as if we did not need to cultivate them and discipline to make them fructify, and our tastes for which we are held responsible, as if they were not the result of contingent encounters and of the social lottery? Buchanan, Brock, Daniels & Wilker argue for their part that the radical form of resource equalitarianism that results from the abandon of the moral difference between talents and preferences yields a profoundly expanded conception of the domain of distributive justice. 17 The most obvious difference between the political concept of equality and the concept of equality that underlies the brute luck view is that the first one considers the unequal natural distribution of talents as neither good nor bad, but as morally indifferent. The brute luck view for its part aims at removing this original inequality of natural assets either indirectly through a compensation scheme, as Dworkin suggests, or directly through eugenic intervention, as the authors of From Chance to Choice recommend. That is because under that concept of equality any inequality that is morally arbitrary, in the sense that it does not have any moral foundation, is morally objectionable. As Larry Temkin says of the equalitarian position that he adopts in his book Inequality on this view, undeserved inequality is always objectionable; whether or not it is unavoidable, any one is responsible for it, there is anyone for whom it is worse, or it involves different people, societies, places or times. 18 This last quotation brings out into the open a distinction that is implicit in the difference Dworkin makes between talents and preferences. Relative to this concept of equality there are deserved and undeserved inequalities. Or, to say this in another way, inequalities do not all have the same moral status and what is objectionable are inequalities that morally undeserved. Inequalities are morally undeserved when they befall an agent through no fault of his own. At first sight the conception of moral desert implicit in this concept of equality sends back to the idea of moral autonomy. The apparent intuition is that an inequality can only be morally justified if an agent suffers from it through some fault of his own, that is to say, through the exercise of his own moral autonomy. 4. Complete equality I propose to name this the concept of complete equality. Complete equality because from this point of view, in principle, any difference whatsoever between two agents can be seen as an inequality. As soon as an agent is viewed as suffering from a disadvantage relative to others but through no fault of his or her own, the difference that is responsible for this disadvantage becomes an inequality that gives rise to a claim to compensation. Differences in resources or in welfare, natural or social differences between agents, differences in knowledge, in aptitudes, 10

11 physical or intellectual, differences in height or in the ability to digest lactose, or differences in the agents natural or social environment, from the vantage point of the concept of complete equality there is no difference that cannot be transformed into an inequality. Amartya Sen once argued that the important question concerning equality is not Why equality? but Equality of what? and it seems clear that when issues of equality are addressed with the concept of complete equality this does constitute a fundamental question. 19 This concept is also complete in another sense: every inequality is either deserved or undeserved. There is no inequality that is outside of the scope of this moral difference and in that sense for the concept of complete equality there is no such thing as a morally arbitrary inequality. There are it seems three major differences between the political concept of equality and the concept of complete equality. The first one concerns the scope. The scope of the political concept of equality is limited to a unique domain, political equality, and only takes into account other differences between agents if and when they lead to political inequality. The scope of the concept of complete equality is apparently indefinite. There is no domain of properties, no space of variables as economists say, in which it cannot be applied. Sen s question Equality of what? is indicative of one of the major difficulties that this conception faces, how can these different domains be articulated to each other and which rule of priority should be established between them? The second major difference concerns the attitude towards what are often called morally arbitrary factors. According to the political concept of equality natural differences between agents, for example differences in talents, are morally arbitrary and therefore should not give rise to political inequality. They should not because political inequality is a morally relevant difference inasmuch as it violates the moral autonomy of some agents by subjecting them to the private will of others. In other words from the point of view of the political concept of equality morally arbitrary differences between agents are in themselves morally indifferent, what is objectionable is to consider that such differences give rise to or ground moral differences between agents and in particular that they constitute a justification of political inequality. The concept of complete equality considers that differences that are morally arbitrary, like differences in natural asset or bad luck in the social lottery are morally objectionable precisely because they are morally arbitrary, because there is nothing that justifies them. That is why there is a sense in which it can be argued that from that point of view there is not factor that is morally arbitrary. Either, as Temkin said, an inequality is underserved and it is always objectionable or it is deserved or in some way legitimate. Note that according to the political concept of equality morally arbitrary differences are neither right nor wrong, what is wrong is to transform morally arbitrary differences, like difference in race, gender or income into moral difference between agents. 11

12 However, for the concept of complete equality morally arbitrary differences are immediately objectionable. They are wrong in themselves. Finally, according to the political concept of equality there is no such thing as deserved or legitimate inequalities. Natural differences are morally indifferent. They are neither deserved nor undeserved. Political inequality is always illegitimate. On the opposite complete equality establishes a distinction between deserved and undeserved inequalities. As we have seen, ultimately the foundation of that distinction is in the difference between what is and what is not within an agent s control. Inequalities that result from factors that escape a person s control are undeserved; those that proceed from some fault or decision of his or her own are deserved, or at least can be. What is the relationship between these two concepts of equality? Is it possible that the concept of complete equality only constitutes an expanded version of the political concept of equality? Just like I argued that the three conceptions of equal opportunity, formal, material and real equality of opportunity correspond to more ambitious renderings of one and the same idea, can we see complete equality as exporting from politics to other domains the same fundamental concept of equality? Such a reading is suggested by the fact that both concepts of equality are apparently anchored in the idea of moral autonomy. According to the political concept of equality, political inequality is wrong because it robs some agents of their moral autonomy. That is to say, as a consequence of political inequality, there are issues concerning which some agents are deprived by other agents of the possibility on exercising a morally autonomous choice. According to the concept of complete equality inequalities are objectionable whenever they are undeserved. That is to say, whenever they do not result from a morally autonomous decision or action on the part of the agent. It may seem that the main difference is simply that between the two concepts the acceptable range of limitations on moral autonomy has diminished. While the political concept of equality refuses that some agents should have rights that pre-empt the moral autonomy of others, complete equality considers that all limitations on the moral authority of agents, whatever their origin, are equally unjustified. From its point of view, the origin of the disadvantage that is imposed on some agents does not matter, what is important is the disadvantage itself. However, this reading overlooks one major difference between the two concepts: the importance of moral desert for complete equality. What is wrong with undeserved inequalities according to complete equality is that they are undeserved. Yet, compensating an agent for such undeserved inequality will not augment his or her moral autonomy. If I am paid a premium in compensation for my limited talents I am not as a result any more morally autonomous or responsible for my natural assets. My disadvantage is perhaps to some extent lifted, but this does 12

13 not have any consequence whatsoever on my moral autonomy. 20 The case of political inequality is completely different. It is wrong because it deprives agents of their moral autonomy, not because agents do not deserve this inequality. On the contrary, because political inequality limits the moral autonomy of other agents it can never be deserved. Therefore the question of it being deserved or underserved not is not an issue. It is a conceptual mistake. Furthermore, political equality, unlike complete equality creates the conditions under which the exercise of moral autonomy once again becomes possible. All this suggests that we are dealing with two very different concepts of equality, two conceptions of what it is to be equal that are distinct and that do not have the same moral ground. 5. An impossible goal Amartya Sen in Equality of what? claims that equality in one domain or one space of variables most often leads to inequality in another domain. For example equality of libertarian rights might not be compatible with equality of income or equality of welfare consistent with equality before the law. There are two moments in his arguments. First he suggests that this trade off between a domain where equality is the rule and one where inequalities are at least tolerated is what Rawls, Nozick, Buchanan, Nagel, and Scanlon do, as well as most authors who deal with issues of equality. They defend equality as an ideal in one domain that they consider particularly important, but, in order to achieve that goal, for example, equal rights for all, they are ready to accept or even to recommend inequalities in another domain, for example, economic inequalities. Thus he concludes it is important to recognize the limited reach of that usage, and also the fact that demanding equality in one domain no matter how hallowed by tradition can lead one to be anti-egalitarian in some other space. 21 He then goes on to argue that this surprising balancing act is not an accident, nor the result of inattention or confusion on the part of these authors. The fundamental reason, according to him, why equality in one space is generally inseparable from inequality in another space is human diversity. Had all people been exactly similar, equality in one space (e.g. income) would tend to be congruent with equalities in others (e.g. health, wellbeing, happiness). One of the consequences of human diversity is that equality in one space tends to go, in fact, with inequality in another. 22 Tends to go, in fact says Sen. His conclusion is prudently empirical. Had he determined instead, as one might well, that equality in one domain implies inequality in another, he may have been lead to question the consistency of such a concept of equality. Instead, from this fact he inferred that what is most important is to answer the question: the Equality of what? What is the domain in which we want to establish equality? 13

14 His argument nonetheless is not strictly empirical. It rests on two points: the multiplicity of variables from which we can evaluate interpersonal inequalities and human diversity understood as variety both in natural and social circumstances, as well as in personal characteristics. It is because of these two very general considerations that equality in one domain is not congruent with equality in another. Yet this result is not empirical, it simply follows from the structure of the problem that equality cannot be consistently applied simultaneously in all the domains where the question may arise. That the measure of equality over the various variables will give inconsistent results is here imbedded in the structure of the situation as it is construed. To say, as Sen does, that equality in one domain will tend to go with inequalities in another is an understatement. Unless you are ready to abandon either human diversity or the multiplicity of point of views from which inequalities can be measured, this result is inevitable. There is an argument from John Roemer that suggests a similar result: that complete equality can only be consistently applied at the price of abandoning either human diversity or the multiplicity of points of view from which inequalities can be evaluated. In Egalitarianism, responsibility and information (1987), which is a sequel to his (1985) paper where he challenged Dworkin s distinction between preferences and talents, he argues that incompleteness of information concerning welfare functions, in particular, carves out a realm for personal responsibility, and thereby drives a wedge between welfare and resource egalitarianism. (p. 173) In other words, even if Dworkin s distinction is to some extent ambiguous, as argued before because mathematically it is always possible to portray agents who have different preferences as agents who have identical preferences over an extended list of goods, Roemer recognises that in concrete cases this is something that we cannot do. What prevents us from translating differences in preferences into other types of differences, he claims is lack of information about the welfare functions of the agents. In a language closer to Sen s that is to say, it is because, in reason of their various personal, environmental and social circumstances, agents evaluate their welfare from different points of view. It is, Roemer says, the impossibility of gaining perfect knowledge concerning those differences that justifies the distinction between welfare equality and resource equality, and motivates the imputation of personal responsibility to agents. The only reason, he claims, why we assign responsibility to agents for their action is because we lack complete information about agents internal state or the state of the world that determined them. It follows, Roemer adds, that if I knew everything about you, there would be no predictive or instrumental value in letting you choose: your welfare could as well be fulfilled by my choosing for you, insofar as choosing your preferred option is concerned. (p. 175) In other terms, it is only because 14

15 the economist cannot gain perfect knowledge of the welfare functions of agents he studies that there is sense in attributing them personal responsibility. It is true that the problem addressed by John Roemer is different from the question raised by Sen. Yet, the question, equality of what? and the distinction between deserved and undeserved inequalities are clearly closely related. In both cases the issue is to determine which inequalities are acceptable and which are not. Roemer s argument is that this issue only arises and becomes an urgent political question because the welfare functions of agents are different, and because no one can chose for all others given that no one can know everything about them. It seems therefore that complete equality cannot be achieved. It is impossible first of all because the measure of inequality cannot be consistently applied over various domains and in consequence equality in one domain leads to inequality in another. It is impossible also because the distinction between deserved and undeserved inequality is predicated on the state of our knowledge concerning each other. Perfect knowledge of the welfare function of other agents would do away with the distinction. Complete equality is impossible finally because it could only be realised if we could put an end to human diversity, at which point of course perfect knowledge of everyone s welfare function would also be possible. At this point it may be claimed that political equality is just as much impossible. No matter what laws we enact, which measures we take there will always be some agents whose power allows them disproportionate influence upon the political decision process. This is certainly true, nonetheless one fundamental difference remains. In the case of political equality this impossibility is practical rather than conceptual. Perfect political equality cannot be realised in the real world, but the idea is clear and there is nothing contradictory about granting all agents the exercise of their moral autonomy. Because of that political equality can serve as a regulatory ideal. Complete equality is conceptually impossible. The concept of complete equality is inherently inconsistent because it requires the removal of all differences between agents for which the agents themselves are not responsible. That is incoherent because it is equivalent to demanding that agents be causa sui, causes of themselves. Barring that, which is clearly impossible, it settles for second best, and demands that every difference for which agents are not responsible be compensated. Something which if could be realised would effectively put an end to human diversity. In consequence there are I fear little reasons to believe that complete equality constitutes as a useful guide to think about issues of inequality. 15

16 Bibliography: Buchanan, A., Brock, D.W., Daniels, N., & Wilker, D. From Chance to Choice Genetics and Justice (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000) Dworkin, R. What is Equality? Part I: equality of welfare Philosophy and Public Affairs 10: What is Equality? Part II: equality of resources Philosophy and Public Affairs 10: Rawls, J, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1971) Roemer, J. Equality of Talents Economics and Philosophy 1: (1985) reprinted in J. Roemer Egalitarian Perspectives (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1994) pp Egalitarianism, responsibility and information Economics and Philosophy 3: (1987) reprinted in J. Roemer Egalitarian Perspectives (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1994) pp Scanlon, T. A Good Start: Reply to Roemer Boston Review 20(2): 8-9 (1989) Sen, A. Equality of What? in Inequality Reexamined (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992), pp Spitz, J.-F. L Amour de l égalité, essai sur la critique de l égalitarisme républicain en France , (Paris : Vrin, 2000), p G.J. Stigler & G.S. Becker De Gustibus Non Est Disputandum in The American Economic Review 67,2: (1977). Temkin, L. S. Inequality (New York: Oxford University Press, 1993) p Notes: 1 In order to distinguish the political concept of equality from the issue of political equality with which it is often confused. 2 Buchanan, A., Brock, D. W., Daniels, N. & D. Wilker From Chance to Choice Genetics & Justice Cambridge University Press, 2000, p Ibid. 4 Ibid. 5 Note that it is not necessary for existing inequalities to be unjustified in order to compensate agents which suffer from them. The reason why this is so is that even in the conditions of what Rawls (1999) defines as 16

17 ideal theory where it is assumed that existing inequalities are morally justified, bad luck in the social lottery would reflect inequalities that are not to the advantaged of the least privileged and therefore not justified if as a consequence of them some agents would be robbed of equal opportunity. Therefore even ideal theory requires that we compensate for this bad luck. 6 Rawls, Op. cit., p On this last topic one can consult Jean-Fabien Spitz L Amour de l égalité, essai sur la critique de l égalitarisme républicain en France , Paris : Vrin, J. Rawls A Theory of Justice, op. cit., p From Chance to Choice, op. cit., p.66. This is a view of which they believe Rawls is one of the major representatives. 10 As was already indicated in endnote 5 from the point of view of political equality difference due to bad luck in the social lottery should be compensated even if they do not result from past injustices. 11 From Chance to Choice, 0p. cit., p Op. cit., p Ibid, p Ibid, p Ibid, p Stigler, G.J. & G.S. Becker De Gustibus Non Est Disputandum» in The American Economic Review Vol 67, No 2 (March 1977): From Chance to Choice, op. cit., pp L. S. Temkin Inequality New York : Oxford University Press, 1993, p Amartya Sen «Equality of What?» in Inequality Reexamined, Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1992, pp It may be argued that this depends on the importance of the disadvantage from which an agent suffers. Severe deprivation can make moral autonomy impossible and relieving becomes a necessary condition for its exercise. This is true, but note that it depends on the importance of the disadvantage whether or not others also suffer from this disadvantage. Which is why the concept of equality is perhaps not the best to think about this issue. 21 A. Sen, Op. cit., p Ibid, p.20 17

John Rawls THEORY OF JUSTICE

John Rawls THEORY OF JUSTICE John Rawls THEORY OF JUSTICE THE ROLE OF JUSTICE Justice is the first virtue of social institutions, as truth is of systems of thought. A theory however elegant and economical must be rejected or revised

More information

Philosophy 285 Fall, 2007 Dick Arneson Overview of John Rawls, A Theory of Justice. Views of Rawls s achievement:

Philosophy 285 Fall, 2007 Dick Arneson Overview of John Rawls, A Theory of Justice. Views of Rawls s achievement: 1 Philosophy 285 Fall, 2007 Dick Arneson Overview of John Rawls, A Theory of Justice Views of Rawls s achievement: G. A. Cohen: I believe that at most two books in the history of Western political philosophy

More information

Why Does Inequality Matter? T. M. Scanlon. Chapter 8: Unequal Outcomes. It is well known that there has been an enormous increase in inequality in the

Why Does Inequality Matter? T. M. Scanlon. Chapter 8: Unequal Outcomes. It is well known that there has been an enormous increase in inequality in the Why Does Inequality Matter? T. M. Scanlon Chapter 8: Unequal Outcomes It is well known that there has been an enormous increase in inequality in the United States and other developed economies in recent

More information

VI. Rawls and Equality

VI. Rawls and Equality VI. Rawls and Equality A society of free and equal persons Last time, on Justice: Getting What We Are Due 1 Redistributive Taxation Redux Can we justly tax Wilt Chamberlain to redistribute wealth to others?

More information

RECONCILING LIBERTY AND EQUALITY: JUSTICE AS FAIRNESS. John Rawls s A Theory of Justice presents a theory called justice as fairness.

RECONCILING LIBERTY AND EQUALITY: JUSTICE AS FAIRNESS. John Rawls s A Theory of Justice presents a theory called justice as fairness. RECONCILING LIBERTY AND EQUALITY: JUSTICE AS FAIRNESS 1. Two Principles of Justice John Rawls s A Theory of Justice presents a theory called justice as fairness. That theory comprises two principles of

More information

Is Rawls s Difference Principle Preferable to Luck Egalitarianism?

Is Rawls s Difference Principle Preferable to Luck Egalitarianism? Western University Scholarship@Western 2014 Undergraduate Awards The Undergraduate Awards 2014 Is Rawls s Difference Principle Preferable to Luck Egalitarianism? Taylor C. Rodrigues Western University,

More information

Two Pictures of the Global-justice Debate: A Reply to Tan*

Two Pictures of the Global-justice Debate: A Reply to Tan* 219 Two Pictures of the Global-justice Debate: A Reply to Tan* Laura Valentini London School of Economics and Political Science 1. Introduction Kok-Chor Tan s review essay offers an internal critique of

More information

-Capitalism, Exploitation and Injustice-

-Capitalism, Exploitation and Injustice- UPF - MA Political Philosophy Modern Political Philosophy Elisabet Puigdollers Mas -Capitalism, Exploitation and Injustice- Introduction Although Marx fiercely criticized the theories of justice and some

More information

What Is Unfair about Unequal Brute Luck? An Intergenerational Puzzle

What Is Unfair about Unequal Brute Luck? An Intergenerational Puzzle https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-018-00053-5 What Is Unfair about Unequal Brute Luck? An Intergenerational Puzzle Simon Beard 1 Received: 16 November 2017 /Revised: 29 May 2018 /Accepted: 27 December 2018

More information

When Does Equality Matter? T. M. Scanlon. Lecture 1: Introduction. Our country, and the world, are marked by extraordinarily high levels of

When Does Equality Matter? T. M. Scanlon. Lecture 1: Introduction. Our country, and the world, are marked by extraordinarily high levels of When Does Equality Matter? T. M. Scanlon Lecture 1: Introduction Our country, and the world, are marked by extraordinarily high levels of inequality. This inequality raises important empirical questions,

More information

Do we have a strong case for open borders?

Do we have a strong case for open borders? Do we have a strong case for open borders? Joseph Carens [1987] challenges the popular view that admission of immigrants by states is only a matter of generosity and not of obligation. He claims that the

More information

AN EGALITARIAN THEORY OF JUSTICE 1

AN EGALITARIAN THEORY OF JUSTICE 1 AN EGALITARIAN THEORY OF JUSTICE 1 John Rawls THE ROLE OF JUSTICE Justice is the first virtue of social institutions, as truth is of systems of thought. A theory however elegant and economical must be

More information

The Justification of Justice as Fairness: A Two Stage Process

The Justification of Justice as Fairness: A Two Stage Process The Justification of Justice as Fairness: A Two Stage Process TED VAGGALIS University of Kansas The tragic truth about philosophy is that misunderstanding occurs more frequently than understanding. Nowhere

More information

Rawls and Natural Aristocracy

Rawls and Natural Aristocracy [239] Croatian Journal of Philosophy Vol. I, No. 3, 2001 Rawls and Natural Aristocracy MATTHEWCLAYTON Brunel University The author discusses Rawls s conception of socioeconomic justice, Democratic Equality.

More information

Definition: Institution public system of rules which defines offices and positions with their rights and duties, powers and immunities p.

Definition: Institution public system of rules which defines offices and positions with their rights and duties, powers and immunities p. RAWLS Project: to interpret the initial situation, formulate principles of choice, and then establish which principles should be adopted. The principles of justice provide an assignment of fundamental

More information

The Value of Equality and Egalitarianism. Lecture 3 Why not luck egalitarianism?

The Value of Equality and Egalitarianism. Lecture 3 Why not luck egalitarianism? The Value of Equality and Egalitarianism Lecture 3 Why not luck egalitarianism? The plan for today 1. Luck and equality 2. Bad option luck 3. Bad brute luck 4. Democratic equality 1. Luck and equality

More information

E-LOGOS. Rawls two principles of justice: their adoption by rational self-interested individuals. University of Economics Prague

E-LOGOS. Rawls two principles of justice: their adoption by rational self-interested individuals. University of Economics Prague E-LOGOS ELECTRONIC JOURNAL FOR PHILOSOPHY ISSN 1211-0442 1/2010 University of Economics Prague Rawls two principles of justice: their adoption by rational self-interested individuals e Alexandra Dobra

More information

Introduction to Equality and Justice: The Demands of Equality, Peter Vallentyne, ed., Routledge, The Demands of Equality: An Introduction

Introduction to Equality and Justice: The Demands of Equality, Peter Vallentyne, ed., Routledge, The Demands of Equality: An Introduction Introduction to Equality and Justice: The Demands of Equality, Peter Vallentyne, ed., Routledge, 2003. The Demands of Equality: An Introduction Peter Vallentyne This is the second volume of Equality and

More information

VALUING DISTRIBUTIVE EQUALITY CLAIRE ANITA BREMNER. A thesis submitted to the Department of Philosophy. in conformity with the requirements for

VALUING DISTRIBUTIVE EQUALITY CLAIRE ANITA BREMNER. A thesis submitted to the Department of Philosophy. in conformity with the requirements for VALUING DISTRIBUTIVE EQUALITY by CLAIRE ANITA BREMNER A thesis submitted to the Department of Philosophy in conformity with the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts Queen s University Kingston,

More information

Ethics Handout 18 Rawls, Classical Utilitarianism and Nagel, Equality

Ethics Handout 18 Rawls, Classical Utilitarianism and Nagel, Equality 24.231 Ethics Handout 18 Rawls, Classical Utilitarianism and Nagel, Equality The Utilitarian Principle of Distribution: Society is rightly ordered, and therefore just, when its major institutions are arranged

More information

Rawls versus the Anarchist: Justice and Legitimacy

Rawls versus the Anarchist: Justice and Legitimacy Rawls versus the Anarchist: Justice and Legitimacy Walter E. Schaller Texas Tech University APA Central Division April 2005 Section 1: The Anarchist s Argument In a recent article, Justification and Legitimacy,

More information

Phil 115, June 20, 2007 Justice as fairness as a political conception: the fact of reasonable pluralism and recasting the ideas of Theory

Phil 115, June 20, 2007 Justice as fairness as a political conception: the fact of reasonable pluralism and recasting the ideas of Theory Phil 115, June 20, 2007 Justice as fairness as a political conception: the fact of reasonable pluralism and recasting the ideas of Theory The problem with the argument for stability: In his discussion

More information

On Original Appropriation. Peter Vallentyne, University of Missouri-Columbia

On Original Appropriation. Peter Vallentyne, University of Missouri-Columbia On Original Appropriation Peter Vallentyne, University of Missouri-Columbia in Malcolm Murray, ed., Liberty, Games and Contracts: Jan Narveson and the Defence of Libertarianism (Aldershot: Ashgate Press,

More information

The Proper Metric of Justice in Justice as Fairness

The Proper Metric of Justice in Justice as Fairness Georgia State University ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University Philosophy Theses Department of Philosophy 5-8-2009 The Proper Metric of Justice in Justice as Fairness Charles Benjamin Carmichael Follow

More information

Justice and collective responsibility. Zoltan Miklosi. regardless of the institutional or other relations that may obtain among them.

Justice and collective responsibility. Zoltan Miklosi. regardless of the institutional or other relations that may obtain among them. Justice and collective responsibility Zoltan Miklosi Introduction Cosmopolitan conceptions of justice hold that the principles of justice are properly applied to evaluate the situation of all human beings,

More information

Introduction. Cambridge University Press Rawls's Egalitarianism Alexander Kaufman Excerpt More Information

Introduction. Cambridge University Press Rawls's Egalitarianism Alexander Kaufman Excerpt More Information Introduction This study focuses on John Rawls s complex understanding of egalitarian justice. Rawls addresses this subject both in A Theory of Justice andinmanyofhisarticlespublishedbetween1951and1982.inthese

More information

Equality of Opportunity: A Normative Anatomy 1. T. M. Scanlon

Equality of Opportunity: A Normative Anatomy 1. T. M. Scanlon Equality of Opportunity: A Normative Anatomy 1 T. M. Scanlon Equality of opportunity is widely agreed to be important, but surprisingly little is said about why this should be so. In this lecture I will

More information

S.L. Hurley, Justice, Luck and Knowledge, (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2003), 341 pages. ISBN: (hbk.).

S.L. Hurley, Justice, Luck and Knowledge, (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2003), 341 pages. ISBN: (hbk.). S.L. Hurley, Justice, Luck and Knowledge, (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2003), 341 pages. ISBN: 0-674-01029-9 (hbk.). In this impressive, tightly argued, but not altogether successful book,

More information

In Defense of Liberal Equality

In Defense of Liberal Equality Public Reason 9 (1-2): 99-108 M. E. Newhouse University of Surrey 2017 by Public Reason Abstract: In A Theory of Justice, Rawls concludes that individuals in the original position would choose to adopt

More information

The Restoration of Welfare Economics

The Restoration of Welfare Economics The Restoration of Welfare Economics By ANTHONY B ATKINSON* This paper argues that welfare economics should be restored to a prominent place on the agenda of economists, and should occupy a central role

More information

Economic philosophy of Amartya Sen Social choice as public reasoning and the capability approach. Reiko Gotoh

Economic philosophy of Amartya Sen Social choice as public reasoning and the capability approach. Reiko Gotoh Welfare theory, public action and ethical values: Re-evaluating the history of welfare economics in the twentieth century Backhouse/Baujard/Nishizawa Eds. Economic philosophy of Amartya Sen Social choice

More information

Lahore University of Management Sciences. Phil 323/Pol 305 Contemporary Debates in Political Philosophy Fall

Lahore University of Management Sciences. Phil 323/Pol 305 Contemporary Debates in Political Philosophy Fall Phil 323/Pol 305 Contemporary Debates in Political Philosophy Fall 2013-14 Instructor Anwar ul Haq Room No. 219, new SS wing Office Hours TBA Email anwarul.haq@lums.edu.pk Telephone Ext. 8221 Secretary/TA

More information

Empirical research on economic inequality Lecture notes on theories of justice (preliminary version) Maximilian Kasy

Empirical research on economic inequality Lecture notes on theories of justice (preliminary version) Maximilian Kasy Empirical research on economic inequality Lecture notes on theories of justice (preliminary version) Maximilian Kasy July 10, 2015 Contents 1 Considerations of justice and empirical research on inequality

More information

Facts and Principles in Political Constructivism Michael Buckley Lehman College, CUNY

Facts and Principles in Political Constructivism Michael Buckley Lehman College, CUNY Facts and Principles in Political Constructivism Michael Buckley Lehman College, CUNY Abstract: This paper develops a unique exposition about the relationship between facts and principles in political

More information

John Rawls's Difference Principle and The Strains of Commitment: A Diagrammatic Exposition

John Rawls's Difference Principle and The Strains of Commitment: A Diagrammatic Exposition From the SelectedWorks of Greg Hill 2010 John Rawls's Difference Principle and The Strains of Commitment: A Diagrammatic Exposition Greg Hill Available at: https://works.bepress.com/greg_hill/3/ The Difference

More information

Luck Egalitarianism and Democratic Equality

Luck Egalitarianism and Democratic Equality Luck Egalitarianism and Democratic Equality Kevin Michael Klipfel Thesis submitted to the faculty of the Virginia Polytechnic Institute and State University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for

More information

Choice-Based Libertarianism. Like possessive libertarianism, choice-based libertarianism affirms a basic

Choice-Based Libertarianism. Like possessive libertarianism, choice-based libertarianism affirms a basic Choice-Based Libertarianism Like possessive libertarianism, choice-based libertarianism affirms a basic right to liberty. But it rests on a different conception of liberty. Choice-based libertarianism

More information

Equality, Justice and Legitimacy in Selection 1. (This is the pre-proof draft of the article, which was published in the

Equality, Justice and Legitimacy in Selection 1. (This is the pre-proof draft of the article, which was published in the Equality, Justice and Legitimacy in Selection 1 (This is the pre-proof draft of the article, which was published in the Journal of Moral Philosophy, 9 (2012), 8-30. Matthew Clayton University of Warwick

More information

DEFENDING LUCK EGALITARIANISM. Nicholas Barry. This thesis is presented for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy of The University of Western Australia.

DEFENDING LUCK EGALITARIANISM. Nicholas Barry. This thesis is presented for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy of The University of Western Australia. DEFENDING LUCK EGALITARIANISM Nicholas Barry This thesis is presented for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy of The University of Western Australia. School of Social and Cultural Studies Political Science

More information

New Directions for the Capability Approach: Deliberative Democracy and Republicanism

New Directions for the Capability Approach: Deliberative Democracy and Republicanism New Directions for the Capability Approach: Deliberative Democracy and Republicanism Rutger Claassen Published in: Res Publica 15(4)(2009): 421-428 Review essay on: John. M. Alexander, Capabilities and

More information

Theories of Justice to Health Care

Theories of Justice to Health Care Claremont Colleges Scholarship @ Claremont CMC Senior Theses CMC Student Scholarship 2011 Theories of Justice to Health Care Jacob R. Tobis Claremont McKenna College Recommended Citation Tobis, Jacob R.,

More information

Lahore University of Management Sciences. Phil 228/Pol 207 Contemporary Debates in Political Philosophy Summer 2017

Lahore University of Management Sciences. Phil 228/Pol 207 Contemporary Debates in Political Philosophy Summer 2017 Phil 228/Pol 207 Contemporary Debates in Political Philosophy Summer 2017 Instructor Room No. Office Hours Email Telephone Secretary/TA TA Office Hours Course URL (if any) Anwar ul Haq TBA TBA anwarul.haq@lums.edu.pk

More information

Incentives and the Natural Duties of Justice

Incentives and the Natural Duties of Justice Politics (2000) 20(1) pp. 19 24 Incentives and the Natural Duties of Justice Colin Farrelly 1 In this paper I explore a possible response to G.A. Cohen s critique of the Rawlsian defence of inequality-generating

More information

Reply to Arneson. Russel Keat. 1. The (Supposed) Non Sequitur

Reply to Arneson. Russel Keat. 1. The (Supposed) Non Sequitur Analyse & Kritik 01/2009 ( c Lucius & Lucius, Stuttgart) p. 153157 Russel Keat Reply to Arneson Abstract: Arneson says that he disagrees both with the main claims of Arneson (1987) and with my criticisms

More information

Daniel Butt University of Bristol, UK

Daniel Butt University of Bristol, UK Option Luck, Gambling, and Fairness Daniel Butt University of Bristol, UK ABSTRACT. This article is concerned with the question of whether luck egalitarians should view the outcomes of option luck, understood

More information

In his account of justice as fairness, Rawls argues that treating the members of a

In his account of justice as fairness, Rawls argues that treating the members of a Justice, Fall 2003 Feminism and Multiculturalism 1. Equality: Form and Substance In his account of justice as fairness, Rawls argues that treating the members of a society as free and equal achieving fair

More information

CHAPTER II. THE PRINCIPLES OF JUSTICE

CHAPTER II. THE PRINCIPLES OF JUSTICE CHAPTER II. THE PRINCIPLES OF JUSTICE The theory of justice may be divided into two main parts: (1) an interpretation of the initial situation and a formulation of the various principles available for

More information

CONTEXTUALISM AND GLOBAL JUSTICE

CONTEXTUALISM AND GLOBAL JUSTICE CONTEXTUALISM AND GLOBAL JUSTICE 1. Introduction There are two sets of questions that have featured prominently in recent debates about distributive justice. One of these debates is that between universalism

More information

Equality of Resources. In discussing libertarianism, I distinguished two kinds of criticisms of

Equality of Resources. In discussing libertarianism, I distinguished two kinds of criticisms of Justice, Fall 2002, 1 Equality of Resources 1. Why Equality? In discussing libertarianism, I distinguished two kinds of criticisms of programs of law and public policy that aim to address inequalities

More information

RESPONSE TO JAMES GORDLEY'S "GOOD FAITH IN CONTRACT LAW: The Problem of Profit Maximization"

RESPONSE TO JAMES GORDLEY'S GOOD FAITH IN CONTRACT LAW: The Problem of Profit Maximization RESPONSE TO JAMES GORDLEY'S "GOOD FAITH IN CONTRACT LAW: The Problem of Profit Maximization" By MICHAEL AMBROSIO We have been given a wonderful example by Professor Gordley of a cogent, yet straightforward

More information

Princeton University Press

Princeton University Press Princeton University Press Justice: Means versus Freedoms Author(s): Amartya Sen Reviewed work(s): Source: Philosophy & Public Affairs, Vol. 19, No. 2 (Spring, 1990), pp. 111-121 Published by: Blackwell

More information

From the veil of ignorance to the overlapping consensus: John Rawls as a theorist of communication

From the veil of ignorance to the overlapping consensus: John Rawls as a theorist of communication From the veil of ignorance to the overlapping consensus: John Rawls as a theorist of communication Klaus Bruhn Jensen Professor, dr.phil. Department of Media, Cognition, and Communication University of

More information

The Injustice of Affirmative Action: A. Dworkian Perspective

The Injustice of Affirmative Action: A. Dworkian Perspective The Injustice of Affirmative Action: A Dworkian Perspective Prepared for 17.01J: Justice Submitted for the Review of Mr. Adam Hosein First Draft: May 10, 2006 This Draft: May 17, 2006 Ali S. Wyne 1 In

More information

Why Left-Libertarianism Is Not Incoherent, Indeterminate, or Irrelevant: A Reply to Fried

Why Left-Libertarianism Is Not Incoherent, Indeterminate, or Irrelevant: A Reply to Fried PETER VALLENTYNE, HILLEL STEINER, AND MICHAEL OTSUKA Why Left-Libertarianism Is Not Incoherent, Indeterminate, or Irrelevant: A Reply to Fried Over the past few decades, there has been increasing interest

More information

JUSTICE, NON-VIOLENCE, AND THE PRACTICE OF POLITICAL JUDGMENT: A STUDY OF RICOEUR S CONCEPTION OF JUSTICE YANG-SOO LEE

JUSTICE, NON-VIOLENCE, AND THE PRACTICE OF POLITICAL JUDGMENT: A STUDY OF RICOEUR S CONCEPTION OF JUSTICE YANG-SOO LEE JUSTICE, NON-VIOLENCE, AND THE PRACTICE OF POLITICAL JUDGMENT: A STUDY OF RICOEUR S CONCEPTION OF JUSTICE By YANG-SOO LEE (Under the Direction of CLARK WOLF) ABSTRACT In his recent works, Paul Ricoeur

More information

THE CAPABILITY APPROACH AS A HUMAN DEVELOPMENT PARADIGM AND ITS CRITIQUES

THE CAPABILITY APPROACH AS A HUMAN DEVELOPMENT PARADIGM AND ITS CRITIQUES THE CAPABILITY APPROACH AS A HUMAN DEVELOPMENT PARADIGM AND ITS CRITIQUES Nuno Martins Faculty of Economics and Management, Portuguese Catholic University, Porto, Portugal Keywords: capability approach,

More information

At a time when political philosophy seemed nearly stagnant, John Rawls

At a time when political philosophy seemed nearly stagnant, John Rawls Bronwyn Edwards 17.01 Justice 1. Evaluate Rawls' arguments for his conception of Democratic Equality. You may focus either on the informal argument (and the contrasts with Natural Liberty and Liberal Equality)

More information

Comments: Individual Versus Collective Responsibility

Comments: Individual Versus Collective Responsibility Fordham Law Review Volume 72 Issue 5 Article 28 2004 Comments: Individual Versus Collective Responsibility Thomas Nagel Recommended Citation Thomas Nagel, Comments: Individual Versus Collective Responsibility,

More information

Last time we discussed a stylized version of the realist view of global society.

Last time we discussed a stylized version of the realist view of global society. Political Philosophy, Spring 2003, 1 The Terrain of a Global Normative Order 1. Realism and Normative Order Last time we discussed a stylized version of the realist view of global society. According to

More information

FAIRNESS VERSUS WELFARE. Louis Kaplow & Steven Shavell. Thesis: Policy Analysis Should Be Based Exclusively on Welfare Economics

FAIRNESS VERSUS WELFARE. Louis Kaplow & Steven Shavell. Thesis: Policy Analysis Should Be Based Exclusively on Welfare Economics FAIRNESS VERSUS WELFARE Louis Kaplow & Steven Shavell Thesis: Policy Analysis Should Be Based Exclusively on Welfare Economics Plan of Book! Define/contrast welfare economics & fairness! Support thesis

More information

DEMOCRACY AND EQUALITY

DEMOCRACY AND EQUALITY The Philosophical Quarterly 2007 ISSN 0031 8094 doi: 10.1111/j.1467-9213.2007.495.x DEMOCRACY AND EQUALITY BY STEVEN WALL Many writers claim that democratic government rests on a principled commitment

More information

PPE 160 Fall Overview

PPE 160 Fall Overview PPE 160 Fall 2017 Freedom, Markets, and Well-Being E. Brown and M. Green TR 2:45 4, Pearsons 202 Office hours Brown: Wednesdays 2:00-3:30, Fridays 9:30-10:30, and by appt., Carnegie 216, 607-2810. Green:

More information

Introduction Questions and Themes

Introduction Questions and Themes Introduction Questions and Themes The idea of equality is confronted by two different types of diversities." (1) the basic heterogeneity of human beings, and (2) the multiplicity of variables in terms

More information

The problem of global distributive justice in Rawls s The Law of Peoples

The problem of global distributive justice in Rawls s The Law of Peoples Diametros nr 17 (wrzesień 2008): 45 59 The problem of global distributive justice in Rawls s The Law of Peoples Marta Soniewicka Introduction In the 20 th century modern political and moral philosophy

More information

Social and Political Philosophy Philosophy 4470/6430, Government 4655/6656 (Thursdays, 2:30-4:25, Goldwin Smith 348) Topic for Spring 2011: Equality

Social and Political Philosophy Philosophy 4470/6430, Government 4655/6656 (Thursdays, 2:30-4:25, Goldwin Smith 348) Topic for Spring 2011: Equality Richard W. Miller Spring 2011 Social and Political Philosophy Philosophy 4470/6430, Government 4655/6656 (Thursdays, 2:30-4:25, Goldwin Smith 348) Topic for Spring 2011: Equality What role should the reduction

More information

24.03: Good Food 3/13/17. Justice and Food Production

24.03: Good Food 3/13/17. Justice and Food Production 1. Food Sovereignty, again Justice and Food Production Before when we talked about food sovereignty (Kyle Powys Whyte reading), the main issue was the protection of a way of life, a culture. In the Thompson

More information

Educational Adequacy, Educational Equality, and Ideal Theory. Jaime Ahlberg. University of Wisconsin Madison

Educational Adequacy, Educational Equality, and Ideal Theory. Jaime Ahlberg. University of Wisconsin Madison Educational Adequacy, Educational Equality, and Ideal Theory Jaime Ahlberg University of Wisconsin Madison Department of Philosophy University of Wisconsin - Madison 5185 Helen C. White Hall 600 North

More information

Capabilities vs. Opportunities for Well-being. Peter Vallentyne, University of Missouri-Columbia

Capabilities vs. Opportunities for Well-being. Peter Vallentyne, University of Missouri-Columbia Capabilities vs. Opportunities for Well-being Peter Vallentyne, University of Missouri-Columbia Short Introduction for reprint in Capabilities, edited by Alexander Kaufman: Distributive justice is concerned

More information

What is the Relationship Between The Idea of the Minimum and Distributive Justice?

What is the Relationship Between The Idea of the Minimum and Distributive Justice? What is the Relationship Between The Idea of the Minimum and Distributive Justice? David Bilchitz 1 1. The Question of Minimums in Distributive Justice Human beings have a penchant for thinking about minimum

More information

POLITICAL AUTHORITY AND PERFECTIONISM: A RESPONSE TO QUONG

POLITICAL AUTHORITY AND PERFECTIONISM: A RESPONSE TO QUONG SYMPOSIUM POLITICAL LIBERALISM VS. LIBERAL PERFECTIONISM POLITICAL AUTHORITY AND PERFECTIONISM: A RESPONSE TO QUONG JOSEPH CHAN 2012 Philosophy and Public Issues (New Series), Vol. 2, No. 1 (2012): pp.

More information

Brute Luck Equality and Desert. Peter Vallentyne. In recent years, interest in desert-based theories of justice has increased, and this seems to

Brute Luck Equality and Desert. Peter Vallentyne. In recent years, interest in desert-based theories of justice has increased, and this seems to Brute Luck Equality and Desert Peter Vallentyne Desert and Justice, edited by Serena Olsaretti (Oxford University Press, 2003) 1. INTRODUCTION In recent years, interest in desert-based theories of justice

More information

Though several factors contributed to the eventual conclusion of the

Though several factors contributed to the eventual conclusion of the Aporia vol. 24 no. 1 2014 Nozick s Entitlement Theory of Justice: A Response to the Objection of Arbitrariness Though several factors contributed to the eventual conclusion of the Cold War, one of the

More information

Nations and Global Justice

Nations and Global Justice Nations and Global Justice Paul DUMOUCHEL Keywords : Global and social justice Proponents of global justice, for example, Thomas Pogge, Kok-Chor Tan, Charles Beitz, Gillian Brock, or Henry Shue, argue

More information

In his theory of justice, Rawls argues that treating the members of a society as. free and equal achieving fair cooperation among persons thus

In his theory of justice, Rawls argues that treating the members of a society as. free and equal achieving fair cooperation among persons thus Feminism and Multiculturalism 1. Equality: Form and Substance In his theory of justice, Rawls argues that treating the members of a society as free and equal achieving fair cooperation among persons thus

More information

INSTITUTIONAL ISSUES INVOLVING ETHICS AND JUSTICE Vol.I - Economic Justice - Hon-Lam Li

INSTITUTIONAL ISSUES INVOLVING ETHICS AND JUSTICE Vol.I - Economic Justice - Hon-Lam Li ECONOMIC JUSTICE Hon-Lam Li Chinese University of Hong Kong, Hong Kong Keywords: Analytical Marxism, capitalism, communism, complex equality, democratic socialism, difference principle, equality, exploitation,

More information

Between Equality and Freedom of Choice: Educational Policy for the Least Advantaged

Between Equality and Freedom of Choice: Educational Policy for the Least Advantaged Philosophy of Education Society of Great Britain Annual Conference New College, Oxford 1-3 April 2016 Between Equality and Freedom of Choice: Educational Policy for the Least Advantaged Mr Nico Brando

More information

Libertarianism and the Justice of a Basic Income. Peter Vallentyne, University of Missouri at Columbia

Libertarianism and the Justice of a Basic Income. Peter Vallentyne, University of Missouri at Columbia Libertarianism and the Justice of a Basic Income Peter Vallentyne, University of Missouri at Columbia Abstract Whether justice requires, or even permits, a basic income depends on two issues: (1) Does

More information

Phil 115, June 13, 2007 The argument from the original position: set-up and intuitive presentation and the two principles over average utility

Phil 115, June 13, 2007 The argument from the original position: set-up and intuitive presentation and the two principles over average utility Phil 115, June 13, 2007 The argument from the original position: set-up and intuitive presentation and the two principles over average utility What is the role of the original position in Rawls s theory?

More information

Rawls and Feminism. Hannah Hanshaw. Philosophy. Faculty Advisor: Dr. Jacob Held

Rawls and Feminism. Hannah Hanshaw. Philosophy. Faculty Advisor: Dr. Jacob Held Rawls and Feminism Hannah Hanshaw Philosophy Faculty Advisor: Dr. Jacob Held In his Theory of Justice, John Rawls uses what he calls The Original Position as a tool for defining the principles of justice

More information

Democracy and Common Valuations

Democracy and Common Valuations Democracy and Common Valuations Philip Pettit Three views of the ideal of democracy dominate contemporary thinking. The first conceptualizes democracy as a system for empowering public will, the second

More information

Notes from discussion in Erik Olin Wright Lecture #2: Diagnosis & Critique Middle East Technical University Tuesday, November 13, 2007

Notes from discussion in Erik Olin Wright Lecture #2: Diagnosis & Critique Middle East Technical University Tuesday, November 13, 2007 Notes from discussion in Erik Olin Wright Lecture #2: Diagnosis & Critique Middle East Technical University Tuesday, November 13, 2007 Question: In your conception of social justice, does exploitation

More information

AMY GUTMANN: THE CONSTRUCTIVE POTENTIAL OF COMMUNITARIAN VALUES DOES GUTMANN SUCCEED IN SHOWING THE CONSTRUCTIVE POTENTIAL OF COMMUNITARIAN VALUES?

AMY GUTMANN: THE CONSTRUCTIVE POTENTIAL OF COMMUNITARIAN VALUES DOES GUTMANN SUCCEED IN SHOWING THE CONSTRUCTIVE POTENTIAL OF COMMUNITARIAN VALUES? AMY GUTMANN: THE CONSTRUCTIVE POTENTIAL OF COMMUNITARIAN VALUES DOES GUTMANN SUCCEED IN SHOWING THE CONSTRUCTIVE POTENTIAL OF COMMUNITARIAN VALUES? 1 The view of Amy Gutmann is that communitarians have

More information

Political equality, wealth and democracy

Political equality, wealth and democracy 1 Political equality, wealth and democracy Wealth, power and influence are often mentioned together as symbols of status and prestige. Yet in a democracy, they can make an unhappy combination. If a democratic

More information

PPE 160 Fall Overview. Coursework and grading

PPE 160 Fall Overview. Coursework and grading PPE 160 Fall 2014 Freedom, Markets, and Well-Being E. Brown & M. Green TR 1:15 2:30, Pearsons 202 Office hours Brown: Wednesdays 10:00 11:45 and Thursdays 2:30 3:45, Carnegie 216, 607-2810. Green: Tuesdays

More information

Institutional Cosmopolitanism and the Duties that Human. Rights Impose on Individuals

Institutional Cosmopolitanism and the Duties that Human. Rights Impose on Individuals Institutional Cosmopolitanism and the Duties that Human Ievgenii Strygul Rights Impose on Individuals Date: 18-06-2012 Bachelor Thesis Subject: Political Philosophy Docent: Rutger Claassen Student Number:

More information

Aggregation and the Separateness of Persons

Aggregation and the Separateness of Persons Aggregation and the Separateness of Persons Iwao Hirose McGill University and CAPPE, Melbourne September 29, 2007 1 Introduction According to some moral theories, the gains and losses of different individuals

More information

1 Justice as fairness, utilitarianism, and mixed conceptions

1 Justice as fairness, utilitarianism, and mixed conceptions Date:15/7/15 Time:00:43:55 Page Number: 18 1 Justice as fairness, utilitarianism, and mixed conceptions David O. Brink It would be hard to overstate the philosophical significance of John Rawls s TJ. 1

More information

PH 3022 SOCIAL AND POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY UK LEVEL 5 UK CREDITS: 15 US CREDITS: 3/0/3

PH 3022 SOCIAL AND POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY UK LEVEL 5 UK CREDITS: 15 US CREDITS: 3/0/3 DEREE COLLEGE SYLLABUS FOR: PH 3022 SOCIAL AND POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY UK LEVEL 5 UK CREDITS: 15 US CREDITS: 3/0/3 (SPRING 2018) PREREQUISITES: CATALOG DESCRIPTION: RATIONALE: LEARNING OUTCOMES: METHOD OF

More information

POS 103, Introduction to Political Theory Peter Breiner

POS 103, Introduction to Political Theory Peter Breiner Fall 2016 POS 103, Introduction to Political Theory Peter Breiner SUNY Albany Tu Th 11:45 LC19 This course will introduce you to some of the major books of political theory and some of the major problems

More information

Political Obligation 4

Political Obligation 4 Political Obligation 4 Dr Simon Beard Sjb316@cam.ac.uk Centre for the Study of Existential Risk Summary of this lecture Why Philosophical Anarchism doesn t usually involve smashing the system or wearing

More information

When Does Equality Matter? 1. T. M. Scanlon. The first theme of this paper is that we have many different reasons for being

When Does Equality Matter? 1. T. M. Scanlon. The first theme of this paper is that we have many different reasons for being When Does Equality Matter? 1 T. M. Scanlon The first theme of this paper is that we have many different reasons for being opposed to inequality. Only some of these reasons are egalitarian that is to say,

More information

Do we have a moral obligation to the homeless?

Do we have a moral obligation to the homeless? Fakultät Für geisteswissenschaften Prof. Dr. matthew braham Do we have a moral obligation to the homeless? Fakultät Für geisteswissenschaften Prof. Dr. matthew braham The moral demands of the homeless:

More information

Balancing Equality and Liberty in Rawls s Theory of Justice

Balancing Equality and Liberty in Rawls s Theory of Justice University of Tennessee, Knoxville Trace: Tennessee Research and Creative Exchange Masters Theses Graduate School 8-2002 Balancing Equality and Liberty in Rawls s Theory of Justice Young-Soon Bae University

More information

LIBERAL EQUALITY, FAIR COOPERATION AND GENETIC ENHANCEMENT

LIBERAL EQUALITY, FAIR COOPERATION AND GENETIC ENHANCEMENT 423 Etica & Politica / Ethics & Politics, XVIII, 2016, 3, pp. 423-440 LIBERAL EQUALITY, FAIR COOPERATION AND GENETIC ENHANCEMENT IVAN CEROVAC Università di Trieste Departimento di Studi Umanistici ivan.cerovac@phd.units.it

More information

Political Norms and Moral Values

Political Norms and Moral Values Penultimate version - Forthcoming in Journal of Philosophical Research (2015) Political Norms and Moral Values Robert Jubb University of Leicester rj138@leicester.ac.uk Department of Politics & International

More information

ECONOMIC POLICIES AND SOCIO-ECONOMIC CLAUSES IN THE SOUTH AFRICAN BILL OF RIGHTS.

ECONOMIC POLICIES AND SOCIO-ECONOMIC CLAUSES IN THE SOUTH AFRICAN BILL OF RIGHTS. ECONOMIC POLICIES AND SOCIO-ECONOMIC CLAUSES IN THE SOUTH AFRICAN BILL OF RIGHTS. The general ( or pre-institutional ) conception of HUMAN RIGHTS points to underlying moral objectives, like individual

More information

Politics between Philosophy and Democracy

Politics between Philosophy and Democracy Leopold Hess Politics between Philosophy and Democracy In the present paper I would like to make some comments on a classic essay of Michael Walzer Philosophy and Democracy. The main purpose of Walzer

More information

Commentary on Idil Boran, The Problem of Exogeneity in Debates on Global Justice

Commentary on Idil Boran, The Problem of Exogeneity in Debates on Global Justice Commentary on Idil Boran, The Problem of Exogeneity in Debates on Global Justice Bryan Smyth, University of Memphis 2011 APA Central Division Meeting // Session V-I: Global Justice // 2. April 2011 I am

More information

Is Dworkin a luck egalitarian? Matr

Is Dworkin a luck egalitarian? Matr Dipartimento di Scienze politiche Cattedra di Filosofia politica Is Dworkin a luck egalitarian? RELATORE Prof. Sebastiano Maffettone CANDIDATO Miryam Magro Matr.068902 ANNO ACCADEMICO 2013/2014 Contents

More information

Working Paper No. 14/05. Relocating the responsibility cut: Should more responsibility imply less redistribution?

Working Paper No. 14/05. Relocating the responsibility cut: Should more responsibility imply less redistribution? Working Paper No. 14/05 Relocating the responsibility cut: Should more responsibility imply less redistribution? by Alexander W. Cappelen Bertil Tungodden SNF Project No. 2515 From circumstance to choice:

More information