Applicable Game Theory

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Applicable Game Theory"

Transcription

1 Chapter 3: Deterrence * 3.1 Introduction How should nations behave to prevent a nuclear first strike? How can incumbent firms prevent the entry of new competitors? The answer lies in the art of deterrence, which, if successful, encourages your opponent to refrain from the unwanted course of action in anticipation of your retaliatory response. Successful deterrence requires persuasion. Your opponent must believe that the costs suffered as a result of your response will outweigh the benefits of his action. Consider the following deterrence success story: Harry is a foul beaked parrot who, to his owner Mr. Brown's dismay, spends most of his days experimenting with uncouth and obscene language. Mr. Brown, a mild mannered gentleman, finds these expectorations offensive and constantly reprimands the bird. To no avail. In fact the more Mr. Brown complains, the more Harry cusses until, one day, Mr. Brown decides to take action. He grabs the bird and throws him into the freezer. Follows an innovative string of obscenities and vigorous scraping of the inner door. Then silence. Total silence. Worried that his pet might have hurt himself, Mr. Brown opens the freezer door. Out comes Harry, looking as contrite as any parrot can be. "I'm so dreadfully sorry to have bothered you" says Harry, "I do declare that my cussing is over forever." And the bird snuggles up to Mr. Brown's ear and whispers, "By the way, what did the chicken do?" Harry kept his word and took to reciting Walt Whitman much to Mr Brown's delight and amazement. Had Mr. Brown known about game theory he could have predicted the impact of his frozen chicken on poor Harry's psyche. To the parrot, the frozen bird was the retaliatory threat he exposed himself to if he insisted on pursuing the less elegant forms of language. And after all, is it not better to speak well and be alive even if one has to forego the pleasures of a well rounded swears word? To Harry the cost of freezing to death outweighed the benefit of hearing himself cuss. And the threat was truly credible to Harry since another bird had clearly fallen victim to Mr. Brown's retaliatory measures. Deterrence is a major theme of game theory. This is hardly surprising since only the rational decision maker with enough concern for tomorrow is likely to be moved by deterrent threats. When such threats are the product of the rule of law, there is rarely any issue of credibility. However, when a deterrent threat is made by a firm or by a nationstate, its credibility can be at issue especially if the course of action it is attempting to deter is not a clear encroachment of its vital interests. For example, the threat to intervene militarily to defend an ally against a third party attack can be the subject of considerable doubt on the part of the attacker. The fundamental question it raises is the following; should deterrence fail, the defender might find it too costly to implement the threatened course of action. The credibility of such a threat is therefore intimately associated with a * Copyright , Jean-Pierre P. Langlois. All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopy, recording, or any information storage and retrieval system, without permission in writing from the author. 1

2 cost/benefit analysis not unlike that faced by the attacker. Should the cost of intervention outweigh that of submitting to the attack the threat will hardly appear credible. So if Harry was knowledgeable about game theory, he could consider the credibility of Mr. Brown's freezing threat: would Mr. Brown really prefer to lose his pet rather than hear a few obscenities a day? If Harry were to realize that the chicken had never been Mr. Brown's pet, he may even entertain the possibility of breaking his promise, abandoning Walt Whitman, to resume his exploration of crude and ugly vocabulary. Game theory equates the credibility of a threat with the rationality of carrying it out. From a game theoretic viewpoint, Mr. Brown would need to clearly prefer silence to the company of a cussing pet for Harry to find his threat credible. Game theory has played an important role in the modeling of deterrence in economics as well as in political science. It has been a source of insight into policy relevant issues such as nuclear deterrence or predatory pricing. The sections that follow present game theoretic models of deterrence theory in political science and in economics. 3.2 The Nuclear Deterrence Debate In the early days of the nuclear age, before the Soviet Union acquired its first nuclear capability, the nuclear deterrence equation was a rather simple one: the U.S. could threaten with impunity a nuclear retaliation for any serious encroachment of the status quo in central Europe. Indeed, it has been argued that one major reason for the Hiroshima and Nagasaki bombings was President Truman's intent to warn Stalin against pushing his advantage in Europe after the defeat of Germany. With the evidence of the destructiveness of the bomb and of the willingness of the U.S. to use it, any territorial or political gain that the Red Army could achieve could be quickly outweighed by the thorough destruction of Moscow and other major Soviet cities. The Soviets did not need a great deal of rationality to be impressed by the argument. The situation began changing considerably with the first Soviet nuclear tests 1 and their subsequent development of the hydrogen bomb and long-range delivery systems. How could the U.S. credibly threaten Moscow with nuclear destruction when the Soviet Union could inflict the same damage on Washington or New York? How could the nuclear threat thus be used to protect Western Europe from Soviet ambitions? De Gaulle who asked whether the U.S. would risk New York for Paris raised the issue most emphatically. Although the question was never actually put to the test, the answer was quite evident for the French who decided to develop their nuclear capability. One American answer to this credibility issue was the creation of NATO. The American commitment to the defense of Western Europe that lies at the heart of the NATO alliance explicitly involved the possibility of nuclear warfare. But how would the nuclear escalation come about? Would it be a deliberate decision that enough was enough and that a desperate military situation warranted the escalation to a nuclear exchange? Official declarations were never that clear and, even if they had been, their credibility 1 It now appears that, although Soviet scientists had reached an excellent and in some ways superior design, the first Soviet atomic bomb was a copy of an American design obtained by Soviet intelligence. 2

3 would have remained highly dubious. In fact, it has been argued 2 that a threat of deliberate nuclear first use can never be credible between approximately equal nuclear opponents. Instead, nuclear deterrence theorists have adopted the proposal 3 of a "strategy that leaves something to chance." The argument goes as follows: in the fog of war that would inevitably envelop a conventional Soviet drive on western Europe, it would be impossible for either side to keep complete control of all developments. In particular, if nuclear arms happen to be available to the local commanders whose communication channels have been cut, and if they have authority in that case to use their weapons, chances are that they will use them in desperate situations. So, nuclear first use becomes a chance move that need not be deliberately ordered by the central authorities. This thinking was so pervasive among military and intellectual strategists that NATO deployed numerous "tactical" nuclear weapons in Western Europe and adopted a policy that delegated the authority to use them to the local commanders under certain circumstances. 4 This was based on a distinction between "tactical" and "strategic" nuclear weapons, which is not obvious. In principle, a weapon is tactical if its primary use is intended against military targets, such as an armored division or a naval battle group, or their support and supply structure. It is strategic if its primary destination is the economic, industrial, and even civilian resources of the opponent, or its command and control structure. The trouble is that tactical nuclear weapons were never thought to be very effective against armored divisions unless one used them in the hundreds, thus inflicting tremendous collateral damage that would become either a suicidal or a strategic use. 5 And indeed, the fuzziness of that distinction served a major purpose: since tactical use could result from a loss of control on the battlefield, and since the tactical use would easily border on the strategic, a Soviet conventional drive on western Europe would place its own society at a significant and unacceptable risk of nuclear destruction. One may feel appalled that this kind of thinking served as a centerpiece of the defense strategy of the western world during the Cold War, not just an emotional response to the risk of nuclear holocaust, but as a simple questioning of the very logic of the edifice. For instance, is it sensible to argue that the tactical use would necessarily lead to the strategic? Although tactical nuclear warfare would have messed up central Europe (and deprived the Soviets of the fruits of victory) local NATO or Soviet commanders would never have been in a position to attack a Soviet or a U.S. city. So, both U.S. and Soviet societies seemed relatively immune to the "loss of control" thesis, at least as far as local commanders were concerned. The strategic "button" always remained in the very close hands of the highest authority on each side. 2 See for instance The Illogic of American Nuclear Strategy (1984) by Robert Jervis or Deterrence (1977) by Patrick Morgan. 3 See for instance The Strategy of Conflict (1960) and Arms and Influence (1966) both by Thomas Schelling, and Escalation and the Nuclear Option by Bernard Brodie for the evolution of those ideas. 4 At the same time NATO built numerous safety features such as Permissive Action Links (PALs) into the system to prevent accidental or unauthorized use. 5 This dilemma led to the invention of the so-called neutron bomb whose primary effect was to emit tremendous amounts of radiation that would kill tank crews almost instantly and inflict limited collateral damage on the countryside. Neutron bombs were never deployed because they threatened the very principle that nuclear escalation needed to be uncontrollable. 3

4 Could the supreme command, instead, become responsible for this loss of control? The very proposition sounds like a contradiction in terms within the intellectual framework of deterrence theory: on the one hand one argues that deterrence will succeed because the central decision makers will see that the risks clearly outweigh the benefits; on the other hand they may lose control in the heat of a crisis to the point of not seeing through that obvious calculus any longer. 6 Finally, one wonders why NATO went to such great pain and expense to ensure that the conventional defense of Western Europe would succeed. If the "strategy that leaves something to chance" were really credible, wouldn't it be simpler (and cheaper) to keep only those forces necessary to guard the nuclear weapons and serve as a tripwire, thus demonstrating a complete confidence that the loss of control would indeed occur at the tactical level and propagate upward to the strategic? Volumes have been written about the credibility issues of extended nuclear deterrence and, lacking any direct evidence of its failure, most of these issues are still largely unsettled. The contribution of game theory to the debate is similarly ambiguous. On the one hand, it clarifies some of the arguments by exposing the critical elements and relationships necessary to achieve credibility. On the other hand, it over-simplifies the inevitably complex structure of international crises. 3.3 Early Game Theoretic Models of Nuclear Deterrence Herman Kahn 7 likened nuclear crises to the game of Chicken supposedly played by California teenagers: two cars race toward each other driving in the middle of the road. The first driver who swerves is "chicken." The game and its variations would be played for prestige and related prerogatives. The chicken metaphor was soon "formalized" into the normal form game of Table Implicit in the strategic form is the assumption that each side has a strategy in mind before even starting the race. In Table 3.01, the set of possible strategies has been reduced to "Challenge" and "No challenge," a clearly extreme simplification. 8 If both sides challenge each other to the end, the inevitable collision will result in a disaster: death for both sides. And the posthumous prestige is not quite enough to compensate for the loss of opportunity to enjoy life (even without prestige). Each player's preferences are therefore in the following order: (1) to win, (2) to draw, (3) to lose, and (4) to die. 6 One may also argue that a Minuteman crew, for instance, could initiate a launch in the heat of a crisis. But this could only arise from a total loss of communication between the silo and the central command, loss that would likely result from a successful Soviet first strike. Both sides deployed immense ingenuity in guarding complete control over the strategic arsenals, evidence that a loss of control was not intended to happen at that level. 7 On Thermonuclear War (1960). 8 The representation of Chicken (as originally described) by a normal form game is, to say the least, highly dubious. It is in fact a game of timing with numerous decision steps to account for. Even if one is stupid enough to play that game, it is difficult to believe that he will not reconsider a few times the possibility of swerving as he races toward the incoming car. 4

5 Table 3.01: Chicken In the nuclear crisis version of Chicken, the "strategies" available to the two sides have been given various names depending on the authors. Brams, for instance, uses the terms "cooperation" and "non-cooperation." 9 Other authors have used the terms "cooperate" and "defect." In any case, if neither side is willing to cooperate the crisis is assumed to result in an escalation to nuclear disaster, which neither side prefers to any other outcome. But if one side behaves cooperatively, it is likely to be exploited by the other to its advantage. Only if both sides are willing to cooperate will some compromise emerge. Of course, the simplification of the complex options available in a nuclear crisis to two extreme attitudes seems at best naive. But, more importantly, it portrays decision making in a rather odd way. In essence, the two players independently commit to one "strategy" at the outset of the crisis. If that commitment is uncooperative on both sides, neither side is given a chance to reconsider and to promote a more compromising attitude. The game model appears to erase essential components of actual crises, especially those of timing and learning from each other s actions. In fact, if used as a model, Chicken leads to serious logical inconsistencies. It is found to have three Nash equilibria: (1) Player 1's victory, (2) Player 2's victory, and (3) a mixed strategy equilibrium with each side playing their two extreme choices with some probability that depends on the exact payoff values used to represent player utilities The latter has not been given much attention in the literature. The two other equilibria imply that one side will rational pre-empt the other, an outcome that contradicts much of the empirical evidence. Indeed, the famous Cuban Missile Crisis is a typical case where the Soviet Union attempted to pre-empt by establishing a more favorable status quo. The final outcome, however, was not quite to its advantage. Indeed, the very existence of a crisis seems to imply that the other party contested an attempt at pre-emption. Nevertheless, numerous models were developed around the Chicken approach, often by adding at least a second turn to the model. 10 A few authors, notably Frank Zagare, have criticized the Chicken model. 11 Most of the criticism is based on the observation that, in a real crisis, if one side challenges it is 9 See Superpower Games (1985, p. 15) by Steven Brams. 10 See for instance Game Theory and National Security (1988) by Steven Brams and Marc Kilgour. 11 The Dynamics of Deterrence (1987) by Frank Zagare. 5

6 usually better for the other to respond in kind than to submit, thereby escalating the level of tension. This is especially true in the case of approximately equal opponents. Other two-by-two normal form games have been proposed as models of international crises. A major contender is the famous Prisoner's Dilemma of Table Table 3.02: The Prisoner's Dilemma The story that gave the game its name is usually attributed to Tucker: two prisoners are held in separate cells with no way to communicate among themselves. They are suspected of being accomplices in some crime. The prosecutor offers each of them the following bargain: if only one of the prisoners confesses, thus providing much needed evidence to the prosecution, he will be given great leniency while his accomplice will get the heaviest possible sentence. If both confess, they will be given heavy sentences, but not the heaviest. If neither confesses, they will still get significant sentences (based on existing evidence) certainly heavier than what a sole confessor would get. The payoff values in Table 3.02 translate their individual preferences for a minimum sentence. The Prisoner's Dilemma, in its simplest one-shot form admits a single rational solution: each side finds it preferable to defect no matter what the other side does. This results in the single Nash equilibrium (Defect,Defect) with utilities that are worse than what the two sides could obtain by both cooperating, thereby the dilemma. In its simplest form, the Prisoner's Dilemma model does not offer a much better prediction than Chicken for international crises. The rational outcome here should be the sole Nash equilibrium Defect/Defect that results in all out escalation. But again, the model over-simplifies the complex decision structure of a crisis. In reality, escalation can be a step-by-step process of retaliation upon retaliation with the two sides edging closer and closer to the nuclear abyss. This critique gave rise to numerous models that add options and turns of play to the decision structure. Eventually, the modeling efforts turned to the extensive game form in order to better capture the sequentiality of decision making as well as the timing and information components of the problem. 3.4 Extensive Form Models of Deterrence Perhaps the simplest situation where deterrence issues arise in international relations is when a challenger can attempt to grab some piece of real estate held by a defender. In the simplest analysis, if the challenger challenges the defender may resist or submit. If the challenger waits, the status quo continues. A weak defender is one who will prefer to submit rather than defend with possibly worse consequences. A strong defender 6

7 is one who will prefer to defend, perhaps with the perspective of winning some concessions as an outcome of the crisis. The two cases are pictured in Figure Figure 3.01: Two Deterrence Configurations There is only one solution to each of these two games. When the defender is weak, a challenge occurs followed by a submission. And when the defender is strong, the challenger waits. Game theory does not seem to contribute extraordinary insight here. This elementary model can now be complexified in some interesting ways. First, it seems more realistic to allow the challenger a bit more sophistication in his decision process. He may, for instance, first express a demand and only act later if that demand is not met. This will give him a chance to back down should the defender appear too resolute in her resistance to the demand. This situation is now pictured in Figure Again, there are two cases of defender. The challenger's outcomes are affected by whether he faces a weak or a strong defender. Should the defender be weak, it would be silly to back down instead of going to a war the challenger can win whereas, if the defender is strong, that same war will be far too costly. The rational solution in the case of a weak defender is for the challenger to demand expecting the defender to submit on the assumption that the challenger would attack next. In the case of a strong defender, the challenger will wait expecting the defender to resist on the assumption that the challenger will backdown. Again, there is little here that game theory tells us that we did not already know. 7

8 Figure 3.02: Several Stages and Configurations Of course, the games of Figure 3.02 are still greatly limited in several ways. First, they limit severely the number of turns and options available to the two sides. There are presumably numerous ways to resist, escalate, and possibly propose settlements. Second, although the sequentiality of play seems appealing, it is not always the rule at higher escalation levels since both sides could choose to move at the same time. Third, the players have perfect information, especially concerning their opponent's preferences, a dubious assumption. And, fourth, the number of allowable turns is pre-programmed into the model, an equally dubious proposition since crises only end (in war or compromise) when the protagonists choose so, not when the theorist does. 3.5 Hawks and Doves 12 One alternative to the above perfect information models that has been developed in various ways in the literature is worth mentioning. Using the Cuban missile crisis as a referent, it appears that the very composition of the Executive Committee of the National Security Council, especially the proportion of so-called hawks and doves, very much influenced the strategic behavior of the U.S. side. Similarly, the decision-making authority on the Soviet side, presumably the Soviet Politburo, determined its own strategic behavior. To simplify, each side's strategic behavior could be labeled "dovish" or "hawkish." The issue of deterrence can now be reframed into that of whether a challenge would occur and what its outcome would be. The game of Figure 3.03 is perhaps the simplest that captures the issue. 12 Section 6 of Chapter 1 on advanced solution concepts should be read before this section and the following ones. 8

9 Figure 3.03: Hawks and Doves Game Hawkish behavior on both sides is assumed to escalate to war (possibly nuclear) with disastrous consequences for both sides valued here at -10. Dovish behavior from the defender will yield a compromise with a dovish challenger and an outright victory to a hawkish challenger. But a hawkish defender will win against a dovish challenger. The utility parameters can be almost endlessly adjusted to represent stronger or weaker protagonists with various rational outcomes. But the equilibria of this game are worth discussing from the point of view of the credibility of deterrence and what contribution game theory has to make to its understanding. The game has three pure Nash equilibria (and several mixed ones) that can be easily obtained with GamePlan and that we will discusse in words. The first one yields a "challenger victory" with a challenge followed by hawkish behavior from the challenger while the defender adopts a dovish stand. In the second one, the defender is hawkish while the challenger is dovish and doesn't challenge in the first place. This could be called a self deterrence" equilibrium. The third equilibrium is pictured in Figure 3.04 and deserves some more game theoretic attention. Here the challenger appears to be deterred by the threat of eventual nuclear war. The trouble is that the execution of the threat is not a rational development from Node 2. Indeed, both players would be better off switching to a dovish strategy in response to their opponent's hawkish stand. In game theoretic terms, the Nash equilibrium of Figure 3.04 is not subgame perfect. There is clearly a subgame starting at Node 2 in which the two-sided hawkish stand is not a Nash equilibrium. 9

10 Figure 3.04: A Non-Credible Threat When one restricts the solving to subgame perfect equilibria, only three solutions arise, the challenger victory and the self deterrence equilibria described above, and a mixed strategy solution with a challenge followed by a high probability of dovish behavior on both sides. However, that equilibrium involves a small but distinct probability of all out escalation. Of course, the model would deserve to be further developed, especially from the hawkish/hawkish stand that would presumably yield some further decision steps. However, with a similar structure as that starting from Node 2, there is little difference in the type of equilibria obtained (see homework problem #2). The question arises again of whether we have learnt from game theory something about deterrence that we did not already know. The answer is a bit ambiguous. First, we have not covered all possible preference patterns that could arise in such situations. But in the above example, we were able to rule out one type of equilibrium by a purely game theoretic argument: the lack of subgame perfection in Figure 3.04 was interpreted as a lack of credibility in the underlying threats of escalation. However, of the two valid pure equilibria remaining, one assures a challenger victory and the other maintains the status quo through something like self-deterrence. Which of the two should spontaneously arise from a real world situation? Each of the two has the flavor of a self-fulfilling prophecy: it is rational as long as it is assumed. But what if the two sides differ in their assumptions of which prophecy will come about? Game theory does not provide very convincing answers to this question of equilibrium selection. Perhaps further refinements of the model will provide better answers. 3.6 Deterrence by Uncertainty In many actual deterrence situations, the challenger is unsure about the defender's true preferences. Is he facing a weak or a strong defender? The uncertain case is represented in Figure 3.05 below. There is now a chance move at the beginning with specified probabilities that the defender is weak or strong. The challenger never really knows which type of defender he is facing although he will form beliefs about it. If the defender were weak, backing down would be costly to the challenger while escalating would be more beneficial. But if the defender is strong, escalation will be costly and backing down will be less so. Of course, the defender's preferences follow a similar logic. 10

11 Figure 3.05: Challenger Uncertainty There are several solutions to this game depending on the initial chance move probabilities that are usually called "initial" (or prior) beliefs since they will appear as such at the challenger s first decision turn. For instance, let us take a probability of the defender being weak of 90%. We find two kinds of solutions (in the perfect mode): on the one hand, there are several equilibria where the challenger does not make any demand. One of these is illustrated in Figure Such solutions can be appropriately called "successful deterrence" equilibria since the challenger is deterred from making demands by an expectation that the defender will always resist and that he will have to backdown, at least with some high probability. Figure 3.06: Successful Deterrence 11

12 Figure 3.07: Failure of Deterrence On the other hand, there is one equilibrium shown in Figure 3.07 where a challenge occurs and the defender resists with certainty when he is strong and with probability 1/9 (approximately ) when he is weak. The challenger ends up escalating with probability 2/3. This can be accurately described as the "failure of deterrence" equilibrium since war eventually breaks out with significant probability. The solutions raise interesting and important technical and theoretical questions. As noted before, the numbers above the nodes in the solution display indicate players' beliefs about where they are within information sets. For instance, b above Node 1 means that Player 1 has a 90% chance of being at that node when facing his first decision turn. The intriguing fact is that beliefs are 50% at each of Nodes 5 and 6 in both solutions shown. The question is how these come about. In Figure 3.07, it is not too difficult to reconstruct the logic of that: after Player 1's challenge, Node 2 will be reached with probability 0.9 and Node 3 with probability Since Player 2 resists with certainty at Node 4, the probability of reaching Node 6 is also 0.1. But from Node 2, there is only a probability 1/9 of proceeding to Node 5. So, standard laws of conditional probabilities tell us that Node 5 will be reached with probability 0.9 (1/9)=0.1 (while the game will end in submit at Node 3 with probability 0.9) (8/9)=0.8. So, if Player 1 ever reaches his second decision turn, he can infer that he has equal chances (50%) of being at Nodes 5 or 6 since these could be reached with equal probabilities (p=0.1). Unfortunately, this argument cannot be made for the successful deterrence solution: Since Player 1 never challenges in the first place, the probabilities of reaching all later nodes are all zero! So, the beliefs displayed above nodes 5 and 6 in Figure 3.06 cannot result from a similar argument. Indeed, they are wholly arbitrary. As noted in Chapter 1, the deterrence equilibria in this case are simply perfect Bayesian since strategies are optimal given beliefs and beliefs are consistent with strategies on the equilibrium path. However, off the equilibrium path, beliefs need not be consistent in the sense of Bayes' law. However, the deterrence failure equilibrium does not have any such inconsistency since all information sets are on the equilibrium path. In game theoretic terms, the equilibrium of Figure 3.07 is sequential. 13 Beliefs at singletons are always 1. 12

13 Again, the question of whether the game theoretic analysis has taught us something we did not already know has an ambiguous answer. On the one hand, deterrence equilibria arise even in the case of very low chances (10%) that a defender be strong. On the other hand that type of equilibrium is vulnerable to the game theoretic criticism that beliefs off the equilibrium path are fairly arbitrary. Indeed, the only equilibrium that passes the stronger sequentiality test is the deterrence failure one that agrees with the conventional wisdom: a defender that is likely to be weak isn't likely to deter a strong challenger. 3.7 Nuclear Brinkmanship The term "brinkmanship" was coined after the Cuban missile crisis as a combination of the term statesmanship and the expression "on the brink" (of disaster) to describe Kennedy's skillful handling of the risks of nuclear escalation to bring about a successful outcome of the crisis. Together with the prevalent thinking that a threat of deliberate nuclear retaliation could not be credible between approximately equal opponents, this was seen as the triumph of the "strategy that leaves something to chance." The first game model that attempted to capture this conception of deterrence is due to Robert Powell. 14 A crisis situation is viewed as a ladder of escalation steps that the two sides can in turn climb. Each time a further step is taken, an autonomous risk of nuclear escalation rises. At each of its turns, each side may either quit (surrender or backdown) and therefore lose the contest, attack by conducting a full scale nuclear strike with disastrous results for both sides, or simply escalate, thus handing the onus of a further escalation to the other side. To represent the autonomous risk of losing control and plunging accidentally into full-scale nuclear war, Powell introduces a chance move at the end of each escalation step. Chance decides with a probability that rises with the escalation steps whether to plunge the players into nuclear war or to allow them a further turn. A typical chance node between two escalation steps, together with the two possible chance moves is pictured in the upper part of Figure See Nuclear Deterrence Theory (1990) by Robert Powell. 13

14 Figure 3.08: The Risk of Loosing Control There is a much simpler way of representing that situation that is pictured in the lower part of Figure The chance node and its associated moves are entirely replaced by a single move between the two escalation steps with additional attributes: (1) a discount factor that is in fact the probability that chance will allow one further turn; and (2) a pair of payoffs that are the outcomes of the final chance move multiplied by the probability that they occur. This representation has the great advantage of simplifying the representation of the complex games constructed by Powell. A typical case with only three escalation steps is pictured in Figure The "attack" move is a deliberate escalation to nuclear war and is given the arbitrary payoff -2. At Node 2, escalation involves a probability of nuclear war assumed to be 1/3 and the resulting expected payoff is 2/3. At Node 3, this probability rises to 2/3 with corresponding expected payoff 4/3. Figure 3.09: Three-Steps Escalation Game This game has two (perfect) equilibria that are easily obtained by backward induction. Although the defender will rationally submit at Node 4, the chance of nuclear war resulting from escalating at Node 3 results in an expected payoff E=-4/3+1/3=-1 for that move. So, the challenger may rationally either escalate or backdown at Node 3, 14

15 resulting in the defender either submitting or escalating at Node 2, and the challenger either waiting (in self-deterrence) or challenging at Node 1. Figure 3.10: Four-Steps Escalation Game The situation changes somewhat when the escalation ladder is made finer. In Figure 3.10 there are four escalation steps with a similar pattern. Now there is only one (perfect) equilibrium with the defender always submitting and a challenge at Node 1. The trouble is that if one adds an escalation step with a similar pattern (incrementing the chance of autonomous nuclear war by 20% at each step of the ladder), the result is deterrence (see homework problem #4). Indeed, adding one escalation step at a time results in this same oscillating pattern in the result: with an even number of equal steps there is a successful challenge and with an odd number there is deterrence. The problem with such a model is that, in reality, it is mostly up to the players to choose the magnitude and number of escalation steps. This is of course possible to model if one adds several branches to the game of Figure With enough options, the challenger can then challenge exactly to the point where the next escalation step is too risky for the defender. Then the challenger always wins. This however presupposes that the challenger knows exactly where that point is. There are other features in Powell's models that are debatable. At the last step the deciding player has no choice other than defeat or a deliberate plunge into full-scale nuclear war. So, the results depend on the assumption that there is no further choice short of nuclear attack. In particular, the game allows no temporizing or de-escalation. This is troublesome since there is almost always such an alternative. Finally, the attack option at all escalation steps is really purely cosmetic since it is always inferior to quitting. One could just as well dispense with it. This type of model becomes more interesting if one adds incomplete information features about the cost of submitting versus that of taking nuclear risks. The critical strategic decision for the challenger is then to target as precisely as possible the escalation level that the defender will not accept to raise. A typical one-sided incomplete information version of the above game is pictured in Figure

16 Figure 3.11: One-Sided Incomplete Information In the lower part of the game, the defender is strong since the cost of submitting is higher. Of course, the solution depends on the probability that the defender is strong. In essence, this is a variation of the model of section 3.6 with the added features of discounting and costly non-final moves. Two-sided incomplete information games are also possible with this structure. 3.8 Crisis Stability 15 The models proposed by Powell and by Kilgour and Zagare have their advantages in capturing some essential effects of uncertainty on deterrence and brinkmanship. But the limitations on timing and options implicit in both models are substantial. For instance, Powell does not allow a de-escalation option. The players can either escalate or surrender. The Kilgour and Zagare types of models do allow the challenger to back down, but this is pictured as quasi-surrender. And in both classes of models the timing is highly contrived. In real crises, there is always a tomorrow and the possibility to temporize or to initiate some de-escalation sequence that may lead through tacit bargaining to a stabilization of the crisis and to an eventual return to the status quo ante. It is in response to those criticisms that the following alternative models have been proposed. 15 Section 7 of Chapter 1 on advanced game structures should read before this one. 16

17 Figure 3.12: An Open Ended Crisis Game At the basis of any crisis is a status quo that can either persist or be challenged by one side or the other. A challenge leads to a state of crisis that can also either persist or be resolved to the advantage of one side. To represent the persistence of a state of affairs, the game of Figure 3.12 involves two loops. In the status quo loop, the players play in turn and either may stay or escalate. If one player escalates, they move to the crisis loop. If he stays, he gives the opponent the turn and both receive a payoff of zero. Note that a discount factor of 0.99 is associated to the choice of stay. This is similar to the models of the previous section: one may imagine a chance node on each of the "stay" moves with a probability 0.99 of continuing the game and a probability 0.01 of ending it in the outcome (0,0). As a result, the players value the immediate future with a discount factor of If an escalation occurs, the players find themselves in the crisis loop. There, the discount factor is 0.8 and a payoff to both sides of -2 is involved in each "resist" move. Here again, one may picture a chance move with probability 0.2 of ending the game in an outcome (-10,-10). If either side submits, the other side prevails and the crisis ends. This game has four distinct solutions. Two are pre-emption equilibria where one side escalates and the other side submits. In a third solution, both sides escalate but neither submits with certainty. Instead, a crisis persists with probability at each turn. This is a brinkmanship equilibrium where each side hopes that the other side will be first to blink. The fourth solution is a deterrence equilibrium where neither side escalates in fear of a continuing crisis. One limitation of this model is the absence of any de-escalation option. The game of Figure 3.13 offers one remedy by introducing a few more escalation steps. A first escalation is only a challenge that may lead to an immediate surrender by the other side. Only if that other side chooses to resist does the game enter the crisis stage. In that case, the initial challenger may backdown, wait, or escalate further by choosing strike. This game has only two solutions, a pre-emption by either side, or deterrence. 17

18 Figure 3.13: The De-escalation Option However, the model still suffers from some drawbacks. For instance, it does not seem that either side has any initial advantage to escalate and either can de-escalate a crisis initiated by the other side and return to the status quo. This is not realistic. The game of Figure 3.14 is the next answer. Figure 3.14: Mutual Deterrence Here, if one side escalates and the other does not take up the challenge, the game enters a new loop where the challenger has a clear benefit and the defender suffers losses. Moreover, once the crisis loop is entered, it takes both sides' willingness to de-escalate in order to return to the status quo ante. Of course, various discount factors account for the chances of a loss of control in the heat of the crisis. This game has thirteen distinct solutions (although many are symmetrical). Two interesting ones merit to be discussed briefly. One solution could be called the Cold War equilibrium whereby both sides tend to challenge each other periodically and go through a few crisis turns before de-escalating back to the status quo ante. There is also a slightly less dangerous variation of that Cold War equilibrium where both sides 18

19 challenge each other somewhat less frequently and return to the status quo without engaging in a full-scale crisis. Of course, further variations on the theme of these models are possible, with different coefficients and more complex structures. But one feature that recurs in the models of this section is the possibility of deterrence that allows crises to occur, escalate, and eventually return to the status quo ante. In both above classes of models (Powell and Kilgour-Zagare) this behavior does not seem to ever occur. Indeed, in many cases there is a very efficient deterrence that never allows crises to develop. And when they do develop, they never return to the status quo. Finally, one must note the explosion of the number of solutions in the last model. This is in fact a typical discounted stochastic game model where solutions are generally numerous. This raises again a question that game theory has never dealt with adequately: which of these equilibria is the most likely rational outcome of such a game? 3.9 Extended Deterrence Although the French felt very insecure about the U.S. nuclear umbrella during the Cold War, there is ample historical evidence of states relying on ententes and alliances to ensure their security. Indeed, NATO is the most prominent example of a successful defensive alliance. Each member relies on the commitment by all other members to join in its defense to deter anyone from threatening its vital interests. Sometimes, however, ententes or alliances can have the opposite of a deterrent effect. One of the most prominent examples is the July Crisis of 1914 that led to WWI. After the assassination, in Sarajevo, of the heir to the Dual Monarchy by a Serbian nationalist, Austria sent Serbia an unacceptable ultimatum. 16 But, before engaging in actual hostilities, the Austrians checked that their German allies would support them, should Russia come to the aid of its Serbian ally, and they were given "carte blanche." 17 In turn, Russia checked on its French ally before committing to the defense of Serbia. And France, as well as everyone else, checked on Great Britain and even on the United States, Italy, and so on. This created a situation where each proponent could involve a probability of military assistance in its calculus of respective capabilities. Optimistic but contradictory estimates on the two sides led to an uncontrollable escalation. There is in fact a difference between ententes and alliances. The former is merely an agreement between the partners while the latter is a formal and usually public commitment. So, if an alliance leaves (hopefully) little doubt about the responsibilities of the parties to come to each other's aid, an entente can leave the nature and strength of the commitment to anyone's best guess. This situation is pictured in Figure Austria demanded that its police be given free access to Serbia in order to investigate the crime, a clearly unacceptable encroachment of Serbian sovereignty. It has been argued that Austria s real purpose was to check the growing Serbian power in the Balkans. 17 This meant that Germany would fight on the side of Austria no matter the reasons. 19

20 The Entente may or may not come into play, depending on the strength of Supporter's commitment to Defender. Challenger, however, is left guessing about it. So, Supporter is first to move in making its commitment, presumably at the request of Defender. Challenger, however, faces the decision to go ahead with its challenge with some uncertainty about what was really agreed to, and this is represented by the information sets at its two turns. After Defender chooses to resist, Challenger may be facing a single Defender or the whole Entente with much greater capabilities. The game has several solution, some achieving deterrence and others not. In the final analysis, this is a question of expectation formation. If Supporter's declaration is sufficiently firm, Challenger will believe that it is likely to face the Entente. On the other hand, Supporter might lack credibility and still be dragged into the fight as may have been the case in July Figure 3.15: An Entente Deterrence Game 3.10 Economic Issues of Entry Deterrence Neoclassical economics celebrates competition. If firms compete for customers prices will be lower, and products more abundant than if firms are allowed to monopolize a market shifting power away from consumers to a single greedy profit maximizing producer. The social benefits of competition are considered sufficiently great for anticompetitive behavior to be prohibited by law. If the erection of barriers to competition is considered reprehensible and even punishable by law, the maximization of one's own profit is not. In fact, the true beauty of the market system allegedly lies in its ability to foster outcomes that are good for society while allowing each individual agent the freedom to act in his own self-interest. But then, a monopolist should indeed try to protect his status since entry of a new firm in the 20

21 market would necessarily reduce his profits. Barring foul play, what is reprehensible about protecting one's own interests? And if there is profitable room for two, could attempts by monopolists to lock out potential competitors always be successful? In the terms of game theory, one would like to know whether an incumbent firm can credibly and rationally deter the entry of a potential rival. This requires that the rival be persuaded that, because of the retaliatory measure threatened by the incumbent, entry will result in a negative payoff. But it must also be the case that, if deterrence fails, it is still in the incumbent's best interest to implement the threatened course of action. It turns out, that such strategic entry deterrence is indeed possible and, its terms have been explored and refined in the vast game theoretic literature on entry deterrence. Following Wilson (1992) one can distinguish between three types of models: preemption models, signaling models, and predation models. Preemption refers to actions such as early investment in productive capacity, customer goodwill, or research and development taken by the incumbent in order to preserve its monopoly position. Signaling models focus instead on the ways in which an incumbent can reliably convey information that discourages potential entrants. Finally predation refers to those costly actions that an incumbent may take against an entrant in order to discourage any subsequent entry. In this section we will only discuss the predation model. The story of predation starts with a characterization of the incumbent firm's character. The incumbent can be weak or strong. If weak, it would loose if it fought a firm who enters its market. If it is strong, the incumbent looses more by accommodating a new entrant than by fighting him. So, again two players are involved in such a game: the incumbent and the entrant. The entrant can decide to enter or not, while the incumbent then decides to accommodate or fight. An entrant that is fought has a negative payoff while the entrant that is accommodated has a positive outcome. A simple game model of this situation can be derived from Figure 3.01 with adequate payoff parameters. But the game becomes more strategically interesting if the incumbent can face several rounds of entry as in Figure 3.02, with a first round of entry and incumbent fighting or accommodation followed by a second round of entry followed by an incumbent response. The incumbent can be weak or strong. The game reproduced below is inspired by Kreps and Wilson (1982) 21

22 Figure 3.16: The Chain Store Paradox Applicable Game Theory Even with a small probability that the incumbent is strong, the potential entrant can be deterred. This is because a weak incumbent has an incentive to fight a first round of entry. Such a response would deter a second round of entry, since the potential entrant would now be persuaded that the incumbent is strong. The game has several such solutions that shade each of the firm's behavior somewhat. In particular, the entrant may be deterred from entry probabilistically in the second round. But all solutions have one behavioral point in common. The incumbent always fights a first round entrant with positive probability, even if he is weak. Homework 1. Edit the game of Table 3.01 by entering symmetric payoffs that respect the given preference ordering and solve using GamePlan. What happens to the mixed equilibrium as the payoff of nuclear disaster becomes worse and worse? 2. Edit the game of Figure 3.03 by adding Nodes 5, 6, and 7 with a structure similar to that of Nodes 2, 3, and 4. Then make the hawkish move from Node 3 continue on to Node 5. Add and adjust payoffs to reflect the possible pluses and minuses in utilities resulting from the adoption of an early hawkish stand by both sides. Solve the game and comment on the solutions. 3. Edit the chance node probabilities (the initial beliefs) in Figure 3.05 first to 50% and then to 90% chances that the defender is strong. Solve in perfect Bayesian mode and discuss your solutions in terms of the credibility of deterrence. 4. Edit the game of Figure 3.10 by adding one escalation step and changing the incremental probability of nuclear war from 25% to 20% at each step. Solve. 5. Solve all three game models of section 3.8 in Markov perfect and sequential modes and discuss the solutions. 6. Solve the game of section 3.9 in sequential mode and discuss the solutions. 22

Weapons of Mass Destruction and their Effect on Interstate Relationships

Weapons of Mass Destruction and their Effect on Interstate Relationships STUDENT 2 PS 235 Weapons of Mass Destruction and their Effect on Interstate Relationships We make war that we may live in Peace. -Aristotle A lot of controversy has been made over the dispersion of weapons

More information

Bargaining Power and Dynamic Commitment

Bargaining Power and Dynamic Commitment Bargaining Power and Dynamic Commitment We are studying strategic interaction between rational players. Interaction can be arranged, rather abstractly, along a continuum according to the degree of conflict

More information

Chapter 8: The Use of Force

Chapter 8: The Use of Force Chapter 8: The Use of Force MULTIPLE CHOICE 1. According to the author, the phrase, war is the continuation of policy by other means, implies that war a. must have purpose c. is not much different from

More information

The Principle of Convergence in Wartime Negotiations. Branislav L. Slantchev Department of Political Science University of California, San Diego

The Principle of Convergence in Wartime Negotiations. Branislav L. Slantchev Department of Political Science University of California, San Diego The Principle of Convergence in Wartime Negotiations Branislav L. Slantchev Department of Political Science University of California, San Diego March 25, 2003 1 War s very objective is victory not prolonged

More information

Nuclear Proliferation, Inspections, and Ambiguity

Nuclear Proliferation, Inspections, and Ambiguity Nuclear Proliferation, Inspections, and Ambiguity Brett V. Benson Vanderbilt University Quan Wen Vanderbilt University May 2012 Abstract This paper studies nuclear armament and disarmament strategies with

More information

Game Theory for Political Scientists. James D. Morrow

Game Theory for Political Scientists. James D. Morrow Game Theory for Political Scientists James D. Morrow Princeton University Press Princeton, New Jersey CONTENTS List of Figures and Tables Preface and Acknowledgments xiii xix Chapter 1: Overview What Is

More information

Conventional Deterrence: An Interview with John J. Mearsheimer

Conventional Deterrence: An Interview with John J. Mearsheimer Conventional Deterrence: An Interview with John J. Mearsheimer Conducted 15 July 2018 SSQ: Your book Conventional Deterrence was published in 1984. What is your definition of conventional deterrence? JJM:

More information

Deterrence and Compellence

Deterrence and Compellence Deterrence and Compellence We begin our foray into the substantive areas of IR, quite appropriately, by looking at an important issue that has not only guided U.S. foreign policy since the end of the Second

More information

PS 0500: Basic Models of Conflict and Cooperation. William Spaniel williamspaniel.com/classes/worldpolitics

PS 0500: Basic Models of Conflict and Cooperation. William Spaniel williamspaniel.com/classes/worldpolitics PS 0500: Basic Models of Conflict and Cooperation William Spaniel williamspaniel.com/classes/worldpolitics Outline Background The Prisoner s Dilemma The Cult of the Offensive Tariffs and Free Trade Arms

More information

The Origins of the Modern State

The Origins of the Modern State The Origins of the Modern State Max Weber: The state is a human community that (successfully) claims the monopoly of the legitimate use of physical force within a given territory. A state is an entity

More information

PSC/IR 106: Basic Models of Conflict and Cooperation. William Spaniel williamspaniel.com/ps

PSC/IR 106: Basic Models of Conflict and Cooperation. William Spaniel williamspaniel.com/ps PSC/IR 106: Basic Models of Conflict and Cooperation William Spaniel williamspaniel.com/ps-0500-2017 Outline Background The Prisoner s Dilemma The Cult of the Offensive Tariffs and Free Trade Arms Races

More information

PSC/IR 106: Basic Models of Conflict and Cooperation. William Spaniel williamspaniel.com/pscir-106

PSC/IR 106: Basic Models of Conflict and Cooperation. William Spaniel williamspaniel.com/pscir-106 PSC/IR 106: Basic Models of Conflict and Cooperation William Spaniel williamspaniel.com/pscir-106 Outline Background The Prisoner s Dilemma The Cult of the Offensive Tariffs and Free Trade Arms Races Repeated

More information

LEARNING FROM SCHELLING'S STRATEGY OF CONFLICT by Roger Myerson 9/29/2006

LEARNING FROM SCHELLING'S STRATEGY OF CONFLICT by Roger Myerson 9/29/2006 LEARNING FROM SCHELLING'S STRATEGY OF CONFLICT by Roger Myerson 9/29/2006 http://home.uchicago.edu/~rmyerson/research/stratcon.pdf Strategy of Conflict (1960) began with a call for a scientific literature

More information

Supporting Information Political Quid Pro Quo Agreements: An Experimental Study

Supporting Information Political Quid Pro Quo Agreements: An Experimental Study Supporting Information Political Quid Pro Quo Agreements: An Experimental Study Jens Großer Florida State University and IAS, Princeton Ernesto Reuben Columbia University and IZA Agnieszka Tymula New York

More information

1 Strategic Form Games

1 Strategic Form Games Contents 1 Strategic Form Games 2 1.1 Dominance Problem #1.................................... 2 1.2 Dominance Problem #2.................................... 2 1.3 Collective Action Problems..................................

More information

Winning with the bomb. Kyle Beardsley and Victor Asal

Winning with the bomb. Kyle Beardsley and Victor Asal Winning with the bomb Kyle Beardsley and Victor Asal Introduction Authors argue that states can improve their allotment of a good or convince an opponent to back down and have shorter crises if their opponents

More information

Crisis Bargaining and Mutual Alarm

Crisis Bargaining and Mutual Alarm Crisis Bargaining and Mutual Alarm 1 Crisis Bargaining When deterrence fails (that is, when a demand by a challenger is made), an international crisis begins. During this brief and intense period, actors

More information

THE NUCLEAR REVOLUTION AND WORLD POLITICS

THE NUCLEAR REVOLUTION AND WORLD POLITICS 17.423 // Causes & Prevention of War // MIT poli. sci. dept. THE NUCLEAR REVOLUTION AND WORLD POLITICS Background questions: Would the world be better off if nuclear weapons had never been invented? Would

More information

Disarmament and Deterrence: A Practitioner s View

Disarmament and Deterrence: A Practitioner s View frank miller Disarmament and Deterrence: A Practitioner s View Abolishing Nuclear Weapons is an important, thoughtful, and challenging paper. Its treatment of the technical issues associated with verifying

More information

Defensive Weapons and Defensive Alliances

Defensive Weapons and Defensive Alliances Defensive Weapons and Defensive Alliances Sylvain Chassang Princeton University Gerard Padró i Miquel London School of Economics and NBER December 17, 2008 In 2002, U.S. President George W. Bush initiated

More information

UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA, SAN DIEGO DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS

UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA, SAN DIEGO DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS 2000-03 UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA, SAN DIEGO DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS JOHN NASH AND THE ANALYSIS OF STRATEGIC BEHAVIOR BY VINCENT P. CRAWFORD DISCUSSION PAPER 2000-03 JANUARY 2000 John Nash and the Analysis

More information

Cyber War and Competition in the China-U.S. Relationship 1 James A. Lewis May 2010

Cyber War and Competition in the China-U.S. Relationship 1 James A. Lewis May 2010 Cyber War and Competition in the China-U.S. Relationship 1 James A. Lewis May 2010 The U.S. and China are in the process of redefining their bilateral relationship, as China s new strengths means it has

More information

THREATS TO SUE AND COST DIVISIBILITY UNDER ASYMMETRIC INFORMATION. Alon Klement. Discussion Paper No /2000

THREATS TO SUE AND COST DIVISIBILITY UNDER ASYMMETRIC INFORMATION. Alon Klement. Discussion Paper No /2000 ISSN 1045-6333 THREATS TO SUE AND COST DIVISIBILITY UNDER ASYMMETRIC INFORMATION Alon Klement Discussion Paper No. 273 1/2000 Harvard Law School Cambridge, MA 02138 The Center for Law, Economics, and Business

More information

U.S. Foreign Policy: The Puzzle of War

U.S. Foreign Policy: The Puzzle of War U.S. Foreign Policy: The Puzzle of War Branislav L. Slantchev Department of Political Science, University of California, San Diego Last updated: January 15, 2016 It is common knowledge that war is perhaps

More information

Strategy in Law and Business Problem Set 1 February 14, Find the Nash equilibria for the following Games:

Strategy in Law and Business Problem Set 1 February 14, Find the Nash equilibria for the following Games: Strategy in Law and Business Problem Set 1 February 14, 2006 1. Find the Nash equilibria for the following Games: A: Criminal Suspect 1 Criminal Suspect 2 Remain Silent Confess Confess 0, -10-8, -8 Remain

More information

Example 8.2 The Economics of Terrorism: Externalities and Strategic Interaction

Example 8.2 The Economics of Terrorism: Externalities and Strategic Interaction Example 8.2 The Economics of Terrorism: Externalities and Strategic Interaction ECONOMIC APPROACHES TO TERRORISM: AN OVERVIEW Terrorism would appear to be a subject for military experts and political scientists,

More information

4. Organize supportive and relevant information into a brief outline.

4. Organize supportive and relevant information into a brief outline. Name Date DBQ 10: Causes of World War I (Adapted from Document-Based Assessment for Global History, Walch Education) Historical Context: At the turn of the twentieth century, Europe seemed to enjoy a period

More information

A More Disastrous World War II. World War II, the most devastating war in world history, followed the 1919 Versailles

A More Disastrous World War II. World War II, the most devastating war in world history, followed the 1919 Versailles MIT Student Professor Van Evera 17.42 A More Disastrous World War II World War II, the most devastating war in world history, followed the 1919 Versailles Peace, the most elaborate and determined effort

More information

Property Rights and the Rule of Law

Property Rights and the Rule of Law Property Rights and the Rule of Law Topics in Political Economy Ana Fernandes University of Bern Spring 2010 1 Property Rights and the Rule of Law When we analyzed market outcomes, we took for granted

More information

International Cooperation, Parties and. Ideology - Very preliminary and incomplete

International Cooperation, Parties and. Ideology - Very preliminary and incomplete International Cooperation, Parties and Ideology - Very preliminary and incomplete Jan Klingelhöfer RWTH Aachen University February 15, 2015 Abstract I combine a model of international cooperation with

More information

Goods, Games, and Institutions : A Reply

Goods, Games, and Institutions : A Reply International Political Science Review (2002), Vol 23, No. 4, 402 410 Debate: Goods, Games, and Institutions Part 2 Goods, Games, and Institutions : A Reply VINOD K. AGGARWAL AND CÉDRIC DUPONT ABSTRACT.

More information

Topic 5: The Cold War. Kissinger Chapter 23: Khrushchev s Ultimatum: The Berlin Crisis

Topic 5: The Cold War. Kissinger Chapter 23: Khrushchev s Ultimatum: The Berlin Crisis Major Theme: Origins of the Cold War Topic 5: The Cold War Kissinger Chapter 23: Khrushchev s Ultimatum: The Berlin Crisis 1958-63 Ideological Differences Mutual Suspicion and Fear From Wartime Allies

More information

War Gaming: Part I. January 10, 2017 by Bill O Grady of Confluence Investment Management

War Gaming: Part I. January 10, 2017 by Bill O Grady of Confluence Investment Management War Gaming: Part I January 10, 2017 by Bill O Grady of Confluence Investment Management One of the key elements of global hegemony is the ability of a nation to project power. Ideally, this means a potential

More information

World War II Ends Ch 24-5

World War II Ends Ch 24-5 World War II Ends Ch 24-5 The Main Idea While the Allies completed the defeat of the Axis Powers on the battlefield, Allied leaders were making plans for the postwar world. Content Statement Summarize

More information

Democracy, and the Evolution of International. to Eyal Benvenisti and George Downs. Tom Ginsburg* ... National Courts, Domestic

Democracy, and the Evolution of International. to Eyal Benvenisti and George Downs. Tom Ginsburg* ... National Courts, Domestic The European Journal of International Law Vol. 20 no. 4 EJIL 2010; all rights reserved... National Courts, Domestic Democracy, and the Evolution of International Law: A Reply to Eyal Benvenisti and George

More information

Economics Marshall High School Mr. Cline Unit One BC

Economics Marshall High School Mr. Cline Unit One BC Economics Marshall High School Mr. Cline Unit One BC Political science The application of game theory to political science is focused in the overlapping areas of fair division, or who is entitled to what,

More information

Enriqueta Aragones Harvard University and Universitat Pompeu Fabra Andrew Postlewaite University of Pennsylvania. March 9, 2000

Enriqueta Aragones Harvard University and Universitat Pompeu Fabra Andrew Postlewaite University of Pennsylvania. March 9, 2000 Campaign Rhetoric: a model of reputation Enriqueta Aragones Harvard University and Universitat Pompeu Fabra Andrew Postlewaite University of Pennsylvania March 9, 2000 Abstract We develop a model of infinitely

More information

FULLY INFORMED AND ON THE ROAD TO RUIN: THE PERFECT FAILURE OF ASYMMETRIC DETERRENCE. Jean-Pierre P. Langlois *

FULLY INFORMED AND ON THE ROAD TO RUIN: THE PERFECT FAILURE OF ASYMMETRIC DETERRENCE. Jean-Pierre P. Langlois * FULLY INFORMED AND ON THE ROAD TO RUIN: THE PERFECT FAILURE OF ASYMMETRIC DETERRENCE by Jean-Pierre P. Langlois * Department of Mathematics, San Francisco State University langlois@math.sfsu.edu and Catherine

More information

Political Economics II Spring Lectures 4-5 Part II Partisan Politics and Political Agency. Torsten Persson, IIES

Political Economics II Spring Lectures 4-5 Part II Partisan Politics and Political Agency. Torsten Persson, IIES Lectures 4-5_190213.pdf Political Economics II Spring 2019 Lectures 4-5 Part II Partisan Politics and Political Agency Torsten Persson, IIES 1 Introduction: Partisan Politics Aims continue exploring policy

More information

Origins of the Cold War. A Chilly Power Point Presentation Brought to You by Mr. Raffel

Origins of the Cold War. A Chilly Power Point Presentation Brought to You by Mr. Raffel Origins of the Cold War A Chilly Power Point Presentation Brought to You by Mr. Raffel What was the Cold War? The Cold War was the bitter state of indirect conflict that existed between the U.S. and the

More information

Introduction to Political Economy Problem Set 3

Introduction to Political Economy Problem Set 3 Introduction to Political Economy 14.770 Problem Set 3 Due date: October 27, 2017. Question 1: Consider an alternative model of lobbying (compared to the Grossman and Helpman model with enforceable contracts),

More information

PROBLEMS OF CREDIBLE STRATEGIC CONDITIONALITY IN DETERRENCE by Roger B. Myerson July 26, 2018

PROBLEMS OF CREDIBLE STRATEGIC CONDITIONALITY IN DETERRENCE by Roger B. Myerson July 26, 2018 PROBLEMS OF CREDIBLE STRATEGIC CONDITIONALITY IN DETERRENCE by Roger B. Myerson July 26, 2018 We can influence others' behavior by threatening to punish them if they behave badly and by promising to reward

More information

PS 0500: Nuclear Weapons. William Spaniel https://williamspaniel.com/classes/ps /

PS 0500: Nuclear Weapons. William Spaniel https://williamspaniel.com/classes/ps / PS 0500: Nuclear Weapons William Spaniel https://williamspaniel.com/classes/ps-0500-2017/ Outline The Nuclear Club Mutually Assured Destruction Obsolescence Of Major War Nuclear Pessimism Why Not Proliferate?

More information

1 Grim Trigger Practice 2. 2 Issue Linkage 3. 3 Institutions as Interaction Accelerators 5. 4 Perverse Incentives 6.

1 Grim Trigger Practice 2. 2 Issue Linkage 3. 3 Institutions as Interaction Accelerators 5. 4 Perverse Incentives 6. Contents 1 Grim Trigger Practice 2 2 Issue Linkage 3 3 Institutions as Interaction Accelerators 5 4 Perverse Incentives 6 5 Moral Hazard 7 6 Gatekeeping versus Veto Power 8 7 Mechanism Design Practice

More information

Unit 8, Period 8 HISTORICAL ANALYSIS Analyzing Causation and DBQ Essentials Early Cold War, From the 2015 Revised Framework:

Unit 8, Period 8 HISTORICAL ANALYSIS Analyzing Causation and DBQ Essentials Early Cold War, From the 2015 Revised Framework: HISTORICAL ANALYSIS Analyzing Causation and DBQ Essentials Early Cold War, 1945-1960 From the 2015 Revised Framework: Causation - Historical thinking involves the ability to identify, analyze, and evaluate

More information

PS 0500: Nuclear Weapons. William Spaniel

PS 0500: Nuclear Weapons. William Spaniel PS 0500: Nuclear Weapons William Spaniel https://williamspaniel.com/classes/worldpolitics/ Outline The Nuclear Club Mutually Assured Destruction Obsolescence Of Major War Nuclear Pessimism Why Not Proliferate?

More information

Sincere versus sophisticated voting when legislators vote sequentially

Sincere versus sophisticated voting when legislators vote sequentially Soc Choice Welf (2013) 40:745 751 DOI 10.1007/s00355-011-0639-x ORIGINAL PAPER Sincere versus sophisticated voting when legislators vote sequentially Tim Groseclose Jeffrey Milyo Received: 27 August 2010

More information

Sincere Versus Sophisticated Voting When Legislators Vote Sequentially

Sincere Versus Sophisticated Voting When Legislators Vote Sequentially Sincere Versus Sophisticated Voting When Legislators Vote Sequentially Tim Groseclose Departments of Political Science and Economics UCLA Jeffrey Milyo Department of Economics University of Missouri September

More information

Level 3 History Analyse the causes and consequences of a significant historical event SAMPLE ASSESSMENT

Level 3 History Analyse the causes and consequences of a significant historical event SAMPLE ASSESSMENT 91438 914380 3SUPERVISOR S USE ONLY Level 3 History 91438 Analyse the causes and consequences of a significant historical event SAMPLE ASSESSMENT Achievement Achievement with Merit Achievement with Excellence

More information

The 25 years since the end of the Cold War have seen several notable

The 25 years since the end of the Cold War have seen several notable roundtable approaching critical mass The Evolving Nuclear Order: Implications for Proliferation, Arms Racing, and Stability Aaron L. Friedberg The 25 years since the end of the Cold War have seen several

More information

OBJECTIVE 7.2 IRON CURTAIN DESCENDS THE ANALYZING THE EVENTS THAT BEGAN THE IDEOLOGICAL CONFLICT BETWEEN THE UNITED STATES AND THE SOVIET UNION

OBJECTIVE 7.2 IRON CURTAIN DESCENDS THE ANALYZING THE EVENTS THAT BEGAN THE IDEOLOGICAL CONFLICT BETWEEN THE UNITED STATES AND THE SOVIET UNION Name Period OBJECTIVE 7.2 IRON CURTAIN DESCENDS ANALYZING EVENTS THAT BEGAN IDEOLOGICAL CONFLICT BETWEEN UNITED STATES AND SOVIET UNION Name Period OBJECTIVE 7.2 begins FOLLOWING IS A CHRONOLOGICALLY ORDERED

More information

Revising NATO s nuclear deterrence posture: prospects for change

Revising NATO s nuclear deterrence posture: prospects for change Revising NATO s nuclear deterrence posture: prospects for change ACA, BASIC, ISIS and IFSH and lsls-europe with the support of the William and Flora Hewlett Foundation Paul Ingram, BASIC Executive Director,

More information

Chapter 2: War s Inefficiency Puzzle

Chapter 2: War s Inefficiency Puzzle Chapter 2: War s Inefficiency Puzzle This book s preface showed why court cases are inefficient. However, we can recast that story as two countries on the verge of a military crisis. Imagine Venezuela

More information

1. Militarism 2. Alliances 3. Imperialism 4. Nationalism

1. Militarism 2. Alliances 3. Imperialism 4. Nationalism 1. Militarism 2. Alliances 3. Imperialism 4. Nationalism Policy of glorifying military power and keeping an army prepared for war Led to arms race Different nations formed military alliances with one another

More information

The Power to Hurt: Costly Conflict with Completely Informed States. Branislav L. Slantchev Department of Political Science University of Rochester

The Power to Hurt: Costly Conflict with Completely Informed States. Branislav L. Slantchev Department of Political Science University of Rochester The Power to Hurt: Costly Conflict with Completely Informed States Branislav L. Slantchev Department of Political Science University of Rochester February 16, 2002 Overview Why do wars occur? Why don t

More information

Choosing Among Signalling Equilibria in Lobbying Games

Choosing Among Signalling Equilibria in Lobbying Games Choosing Among Signalling Equilibria in Lobbying Games July 17, 1996 Eric Rasmusen Abstract Randolph Sloof has written a comment on the lobbying-as-signalling model in Rasmusen (1993) in which he points

More information

the Cold War The Cold War would dominate global affairs from 1945 until the breakup of the USSR in 1991

the Cold War The Cold War would dominate global affairs from 1945 until the breakup of the USSR in 1991 U.S vs. U.S.S.R. ORIGINS OF THE COLD WAR After being Allies during WWII, the U.S. and U.S.S.R. soon viewed each other with increasing suspicion Their political differences created a climate of icy tension

More information

International Security Problems and Solutions by Patrick M. Morgan (Washington, D.C.: CQ Press, 2006)

International Security Problems and Solutions by Patrick M. Morgan (Washington, D.C.: CQ Press, 2006) Global Tides Volume 2 Article 6 1-1-2008 International Security Problems and Solutions by Patrick M. Morgan (Washington, D.C.: CQ Press, 2006) Jacqueline Sittel Pepperdine University Recommended Citation

More information

Introduction to the Cold War

Introduction to the Cold War Introduction to the Cold War What is the Cold War? The Cold War is the conflict that existed between the United States and Soviet Union from 1945 to 1991. It is called cold because the two sides never

More information

Resolved: United Nations peacekeepers should have the power to engage in offensive operations.

Resolved: United Nations peacekeepers should have the power to engage in offensive operations. Resolved: United Nations peacekeepers should have the power to engage in offensive operations. Keith West After the tragedy of World War II and the ineffectiveness of the League of Nations, the world came

More information

Threats and Assurances in Crisis Bargaining

Threats and Assurances in Crisis Bargaining Threats and Assurances in Crisis Bargaining Andrew H. Kydd Roseanne W. McManus December 29, 2014 10,844 words A supplementary appendix and replication data are available at http://jcr.sagepub.com/. We

More information

The Victory of Communism is Inevitable!

The Victory of Communism is Inevitable! The Victory of Communism is Inevitable! Nikita Khrushchev s speech to the 22nd Communist Party Congress in 1962. The most rabid imperialists, acting on the principle of after us the deluge, openly voice

More information

(i) Aim is to understand foreign policy decisions, understood in the first. instance as action undertaken by a government.

(i) Aim is to understand foreign policy decisions, understood in the first. instance as action undertaken by a government. Class on Allison 1. Three approaches (i) Aim is to understand foreign policy decisions, understood in the first instance as action undertaken by a government. (ii) Proposing an approach to foreign policy,

More information

Interests, Interactions, and Institutions. Interests: Actors and Preferences. Interests: Actors and Preferences. Interests: Actors and Preferences

Interests, Interactions, and Institutions. Interests: Actors and Preferences. Interests: Actors and Preferences. Interests: Actors and Preferences Analytical Framework: Interests, Interactions, and Interests, Interactions, and 1. Interests: Actors and preferences 2. Interactions Cooperation, Bargaining, Public Goods, and Collective Action 3. Interests:

More information

Lesson Activity Overview. Lesson Objectives

Lesson Activity Overview. Lesson Objectives Should Japan Amend Article 9 of the Constitution? A Common Core study on World History (Strategy) end of World War II(1945) This lesson was created in post-second World War II in response to Japan s constitution

More information

The Dangers of Strategic Solitude

The Dangers of Strategic Solitude January 2017 The Dangers of Strategic Solitude Jakub Grygiel www.cepa.org Transition Brief No. 3 About the author Jakub Grygiel is a Senior Fellow-in-Residence at the Center for European Policy Analysis.

More information

GCSE HISTORY (8145) EXAMPLE RESPONSES. Marked Papers 1B/A - Conflict and tension The first World War,

GCSE HISTORY (8145) EXAMPLE RESPONSES. Marked Papers 1B/A - Conflict and tension The first World War, GCSE HISTORY (8145) EXAMPLE RESPONSES Marked Papers 1B/A - Conflict and tension The first World War, 1894-1918 Understand how to apply the mark scheme for our sample assessment papers. Version 1.0 April

More information

Politics is the subset of human behavior that involves the use of power or influence.

Politics is the subset of human behavior that involves the use of power or influence. What is Politics? Politics is the subset of human behavior that involves the use of power or influence. Power is involved whenever individuals cannot accomplish their goals without either trying to influence

More information

World War I. United States History

World War I. United States History World War I United States History Section 1 Nationalism Arms Race Alliances Assassination of Austrian- Hungary Archduke Causes of War Nationalism Militarism Alliances -Devotion to one s nation. - A nation

More information

FAIR REPUTATIONS: A GAME-THEORETIC MECHANISM FOR E-COMMERCE DISPUTES*

FAIR REPUTATIONS: A GAME-THEORETIC MECHANISM FOR E-COMMERCE DISPUTES* FAIR REPUTATIONS: A GAME-THEORETIC MECHANISM FOR E-COMMERCE DISPUTES* James F. Ring** February 7, 2008 Abstract This paper provides an overview of an online, game-theoretic bargaining mechanism that can

More information

RUSSIA S SYRIAN MILITARY SURPRISE: STRATEGIC TAKEAWAYS FROM A WIKISTRAT WARGAME

RUSSIA S SYRIAN MILITARY SURPRISE: STRATEGIC TAKEAWAYS FROM A WIKISTRAT WARGAME 1 RUSSIA S SYRIAN MILITARY SURPRISE: STRATEGIC TAKEAWAYS FROM A WIKISTRAT WARGAME President Putin s decision to begin the withdrawal of most of his forces from Syria is sensible. Having stabilized the

More information

Rethinking Future Elements of National and International Power Seminar Series 21 May 2008 Dr. Elizabeth Sherwood-Randall

Rethinking Future Elements of National and International Power Seminar Series 21 May 2008 Dr. Elizabeth Sherwood-Randall Rethinking Future Elements of National and International Power Seminar Series 21 May 2008 Dr. Elizabeth Sherwood-Randall Senior Research Scholar Center for International Security and Cooperation (CISAC)

More information

Game Theory and Climate Change. David Mond Mathematics Institute University of Warwick

Game Theory and Climate Change. David Mond Mathematics Institute University of Warwick Game Theory and Climate Change David Mond Mathematics Institute University of Warwick Mathematical Challenges of Climate Change Climate modelling involves mathematical challenges of unprecedented complexity.

More information

REVISITING THE ROLE OF NUCLEAR WEAPONS

REVISITING THE ROLE OF NUCLEAR WEAPONS REVISITING THE ROLE OF NUCLEAR WEAPONS A Nuclear-Weapon-Free World: Making Steady Progress from Vision to Action 22 nd United Nations Conference on Disarmament Issues Saitama, Japan, 25 27 August 2010

More information

STRATEGIC LOGIC OF NUCLEAR PROLIFERATION

STRATEGIC LOGIC OF NUCLEAR PROLIFERATION STRATEGIC LOGIC OF NUCLEAR PROLIFERATION Nuno P. Monteiro, Alexandre Debs Sam Bleifer INTRODUCTION Security-based theory of proliferation This interaction is shaped by the potential proliferator s ability

More information

1 Electoral Competition under Certainty

1 Electoral Competition under Certainty 1 Electoral Competition under Certainty We begin with models of electoral competition. This chapter explores electoral competition when voting behavior is deterministic; the following chapter considers

More information

Causes of Conflict & Political Violence: An Introduction & Review of Anarchy in IR

Causes of Conflict & Political Violence: An Introduction & Review of Anarchy in IR Causes of Conflict & Political Violence: An Introduction & Review of Anarchy in IR MVZ 203 / 448 Spring 2010 Masaryk University Dave McCuan Let s begin with a basic point: Conflict ranges from minor disagreements,

More information

EFFICIENCY OF COMPARATIVE NEGLIGENCE : A GAME THEORETIC ANALYSIS

EFFICIENCY OF COMPARATIVE NEGLIGENCE : A GAME THEORETIC ANALYSIS EFFICIENCY OF COMPARATIVE NEGLIGENCE : A GAME THEORETIC ANALYSIS TAI-YEONG CHUNG * The widespread shift from contributory negligence to comparative negligence in the twentieth century has spurred scholars

More information

Utilitarianism, Game Theory and the Social Contract

Utilitarianism, Game Theory and the Social Contract Macalester Journal of Philosophy Volume 14 Issue 1 Spring 2005 Article 7 5-1-2005 Utilitarianism, Game Theory and the Social Contract Daniel Burgess Follow this and additional works at: http://digitalcommons.macalester.edu/philo

More information

The Americans (Survey)

The Americans (Survey) The Americans (Survey) Chapter 26: TELESCOPING THE TIMES Cold War Conflicts CHAPTER OVERVIEW After World War II, tensions between the United States and the Soviet Union lead to a war without direct military

More information

In Hierarchy Amidst Anarchy, Katja Weber offers a creative synthesis of realist and

In Hierarchy Amidst Anarchy, Katja Weber offers a creative synthesis of realist and Designing International Institutions Hierarchy Amidst Anarchy: Transaction Costs and Institutional Choice, by Katja Weber (Albany, NY: State University of New York Press, 2000). 195 pp., cloth, (ISBN:

More information

Analysis of the Draft Defence Strategy of the Slovak Republic 2017

Analysis of the Draft Defence Strategy of the Slovak Republic 2017 Analysis of the Draft Defence Strategy of the Slovak Republic 2017 Samuel Žilinčík and Tomáš Lalkovič Goals The main goal of this study consists of three intermediate objectives. The main goal is to analyze

More information

Candidate Citizen Models

Candidate Citizen Models Candidate Citizen Models General setup Number of candidates is endogenous Candidates are unable to make binding campaign promises whoever wins office implements her ideal policy Citizens preferences are

More information

Notes toward a Theory of Customary International Law The Challenge of Non-State Actors: Standards and Norms in International Law

Notes toward a Theory of Customary International Law The Challenge of Non-State Actors: Standards and Norms in International Law University of Chicago Law School Chicago Unbound Journal Articles Faculty Scholarship 1998 Notes toward a Theory of Customary International Law The Challenge of Non-State Actors: Standards and Norms in

More information

Congressional Investigations:

Congressional Investigations: Congressional Investigations: INNER WORKINGS JERRY VooRRist ONGRESSIONAL investigations have a necessary and important place in the American scheme of government. First, such investigations should probably

More information

Research Note: Gaming NAFTA. March 15, Gaming NAFTA: Trump v. Nieto

Research Note: Gaming NAFTA. March 15, Gaming NAFTA: Trump v. Nieto Research Note: Gaming NAFTA March 15, 2017 Gaming NAFTA: v. K.P. O Reilly, PhD JD kpo@nwpcapital.com 414.755.0461, ext. 110 172 N. Broadway, Suite 300 Milwaukee, WI 53202 Until recent remarks by incoming

More information

Write 3 words you think of when you hear Cold War? THE COLD WAR ( )

Write 3 words you think of when you hear Cold War? THE COLD WAR ( ) THE Write 3 words you think of when you hear Cold War? COLD WAR (1948-1989) ORIGINS of the Cold War: (1945-1948) Tension or rivalry but NO FIGHTING between the United States and the Soviet Union This rivalry

More information

World War I The War to End All Wars

World War I The War to End All Wars World War I The War to End All Wars 1914-1918 Causes of Impending War Web of Alliances Triple Alliance Germany Austria / Hungary Italy Triple Entente France England Russia Problem Borders not aligned geographically

More information

Voters Interests in Campaign Finance Regulation: Formal Models

Voters Interests in Campaign Finance Regulation: Formal Models Voters Interests in Campaign Finance Regulation: Formal Models Scott Ashworth June 6, 2012 The Supreme Court s decision in Citizens United v. FEC significantly expands the scope for corporate- and union-financed

More information

Ask an Expert: Dr. Jim Walsh on the North Korean Nuclear Threat

Ask an Expert: Dr. Jim Walsh on the North Korean Nuclear Threat Ask an Expert: Dr. Jim Walsh on the North Korean Nuclear Threat In this interview, Center contributor Dr. Jim Walsh analyzes the threat that North Korea s nuclear weapons program poses to the U.S. and

More information

2014 Brain Wrinkles. Origins and Consequences

2014 Brain Wrinkles. Origins and Consequences Origins and Consequences Standards SS5H7 The student will discuss the origins and consequences of the Cold War. a. Explain the origin and meaning of the term Iron Curtain. b. Explain how the United States

More information

Radio and Telephone communications became part of warfare at the beginning of the Twentieth Century.

Radio and Telephone communications became part of warfare at the beginning of the Twentieth Century. Radio and Telephone communications became part of warfare at the beginning of the Twentieth Century. Signal Intelligence has ever since played a vital role in Military Operations and has had a major impact

More information

INFORMATION SERIES Issue No. 427 February 7, 2018

INFORMATION SERIES Issue No. 427 February 7, 2018 Issue No. 427 February 7, 2018 The New US Nuclear Posture Review: Return to Realism Hans Rühle Hans Rühle headed the Policy Planning Staff of the German Ministry of Defense from 1982-1988 and is a frequent

More information

The Provision of Public Goods, and the Matter of the Revelation of True Preferences: Two Views

The Provision of Public Goods, and the Matter of the Revelation of True Preferences: Two Views The Provision of Public Goods, and the Matter of the Revelation of True Preferences: Two Views Larry Levine Department of Economics, University of New Brunswick Introduction The two views which are agenda

More information

Knowledge about Conflict and Peace

Knowledge about Conflict and Peace Knowledge about Conflict and Peace by Dr Samson S Wassara, University of Khartoum, Sudan Extract from the Anglican Peace and Justice Network report Community Transformation: Violence and the Church s Response,

More information

I assume familiarity with multivariate calculus and intermediate microeconomics.

I assume familiarity with multivariate calculus and intermediate microeconomics. Prof. Bryan Caplan bcaplan@gmu.edu Econ 812 http://www.bcaplan.com Micro Theory II Syllabus Course Focus: This course covers basic game theory and information economics; it also explores some of these

More information

THE COLD WAR ( )

THE COLD WAR ( ) THE COLD WAR (1948-1989) ORIGINS of the Cold War: (1945-1948) Tension or rivalry but NO FIGHTING between the United States and the Soviet Union This rivalry divided the world into two teams (capitalism

More information

Europe and North America Section 1

Europe and North America Section 1 Europe and North America Section 1 Europe and North America Section 1 Click the icon to play Listen to History audio. Click the icon below to connect to the Interactive Maps. Europe and North America Section

More information

John Rawls THEORY OF JUSTICE

John Rawls THEORY OF JUSTICE John Rawls THEORY OF JUSTICE THE ROLE OF JUSTICE Justice is the first virtue of social institutions, as truth is of systems of thought. A theory however elegant and economical must be rejected or revised

More information