DEMOCRACY, JUDICIAL REVIEW AND DISAGREEMENTS ABOUT JUSTICE

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "DEMOCRACY, JUDICIAL REVIEW AND DISAGREEMENTS ABOUT JUSTICE"

Transcription

1 DEMOCRACY, JUDICIAL REVIEW AND DISAGREEMENTS ABOUT JUSTICE Dean Machin* Abstract Jeremy Waldron claims to have identified the core of the case against judicial review. He argues that as citizens have fundamental but reasonable and good faith disagreements about justice (ie, we live in the circumstances of politics ) it is morally obnoxious for unelected judges to strike down primary legislation. Waldron, though, does accept the permissibility of judicial review of administrative and executive decision-making. This paper offers an account of what makes a disagreement about justice fundamental and, in light of this, argues that the intrinsic fairness considerations that imply that the judicial review of primary legislation is impermissible apply equally to the judicial review of administrative and executive decision-making. So, either both are permissible or neither is. The paper concludes by showing that the circumstances of politics have considerably fewer implications for the issue of the proper role of judicial review than Waldron s arguments imply. Keywords Democracy, judicial review, Jeremy Waldron, fundamental disagreements about justice, circumstances of politics. A. INTRODUCTION There are few more determined opponents of judicial review than Jeremy Waldron and recently he claims to have identified the core of the case against judicial review. 1 His argument is important because, unlike other political and legal philosophers who approach this question through the relationship between * Department of Philosophy, University of Warwick. 1 See J Waldron, The Core of the Case Against Judicial Review (2006) 115 Yale Law Journal

2 44 Machin democracy and justice 2 Waldron predicates his argument against judicial review on the fact that we disagree about justice, ie, that we live in what he calls the circumstances of politics. Waldron argues that in the face of fundamental and good faith disagreement about justice it is morally obnoxious for unelected judges to second-guess or over-ride the declared will of the people. Waldron s argument is very powerful both because it is analytically clear and because it fits well with widely-held views about the role of judicial review. However, in this paper I argue that it cannot pass muster. More specifically I aim to show that the existence of good faith disagreements about justice is irrelevant to the case for or against judicial review and that, contrary to some of Waldron s claims, in the circumstances of politics one can justify a decision-making procedure by appealing to the kinds of outcomes it is likely to produce. In sections B-E I set out Waldron s claims, I outline the circumstances of politics and explain the role that it plays in Waldron s case against judicial review; I also explain what form of judicial review Waldron thinks is permissible. We will see that Waldron s argument relies on the idea that some disagreements about justice are fundamental and that these disagreements must be resolved democratically. This requirement rules-out the judicial review of primary legislation but not of executive or administrative decisions. In sections F-J I look at the ways in which one might label disagreements about justice fundamental and argue that there is no principled way of saying what kind of disagreement is, in the relevant sense, fundamental. Therefore, if Waldron s argument rules out the judicial review of primary legislation it also rules out the judicial review of executive and administrative decisions. In light of this I claim that the kind of disagreement about justice is no guide to how that disagreement should be resolved. Finally, in section K I interrogate the idea of the circumstances of politics a little further and show that it has considerably fewer implications for the permissibility of judicial review than Waldron s arguments imply. Principally, I argue that we should assess claims about judicial review s permissibility in terms of its relative ability to deliver substantively just decisions whether citizens agree with those decisions or not. I should note, though, that my interests are both broader and narrower than Waldron s. At the general level my interests are broader because the issue in which I am interested is the role of democracy and the general utility and acceptability of non-democratic decision-making. Waldron s (much narrower) primary concern is the role of judicial review within a democratic society. However, so far as this paper is concerned my interests are narrower than Waldron s. While Waldron s claims constitute an argument for democracy my 2 For examples of attempts to justify the role of judicial review on the basis of its relationship to justice-values see J Rawls, Political Liberalism (New York, Columbia University Press, 1996) and T Christiano, The Constitution of Equality (Oxford University Press, 2008).

3 Democracy, Judicial Review and Disagreements About Justice 45 claims are not a case against democracy. All that I intend to show is that one cannot base an argument for democracy on Waldron s specific claims; this does not rule out other ways of justifying democracy. One final introductory comment: what do I mean by democracy? I mean simply that, subject to a generous definition of citizenship issues of justice are addressed democratically where all citizens together have one vote each to make decisions or, more likely, where all citizens have one vote each to appoint and remove those (ie, their representatives) who makes decisions and where there is some form of majority-rule. B. DISAGREEMENTS ABOUT JUSTICE John Rawls has argued that we can expect pluralism about the good life to be a permanent fact of a free society. People differ about what constitutes a good life there are Christians, atheists, Millian liberals and Aristotelians and given people s different experiences and understandings, their limited reasoning capacities and life s complexities, there is no reason to expect that disagreement to disappear. 3 The free operation of people s reason will always lead to different people prioritizing different values and reaching different conclusions about what is and what is not a meaningful life. The only way to alter this, claims Rawls, is through the oppressive use of state power 4. However, despite this widespread disagreement about the good life Rawls does think that it is possible to reach agreement on matters of justice, such as his account of justice as fairness 5 ; it is this second claim about the possibility of agreement about justice that Waldron challenges. 6 Waldron argues that the considerations that imply permanent reasonable disagreement about the good life show that we can also expect there to be permanent and reasonable disagreement about justice. Issues of justice are as complex as issues about the good life and they are also informed by the different experiences and understandings of different citizens. Furthermore, different conceptions of the good life often contain within them their own conceptions of justice: 3 Rawls explains the fact of reasonable disagreement about the good life in terms of the burdens of judgement. See Rawls, supra, n 2, J Rawls, The Domain of the Political and Overlapping Consensus, in S Freeman (ed), John Rawls: Collected Papers (Cambridge, MA, Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 1999), For a concise statement of justice as fairness, see J Rawls, Justice as Fairness: A Restatement (Cambridge, MA, Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 2001). 6 See in particular J Waldron, Law and Disagreement (Oxford University Press, 1999), chapter seven.

4 46 Machin If a religious or philosophical tradition has nurtured a rich and resourceful conception of the good, it would be odd to expect its priests, ideologues, or philosophers not to have developed that conception also in a social and political direction. Social and political concerns are, after all, among the most pressing concerns we have: it would be odd if a tradition had views about what made life worth living but no views at all about the basis on which we ought to live our lives together. 7 For Waldron, then, we can expect widespread reasonable disagreement about justice to be a fact of contemporary life; this fact Waldron labels the circumstances of politics. C. THE CIRCUMSTANCES OF POLITICS For our purposes, there are four key features to the circumstances of politics. They are (i) that unlike questions about the good life, disagreements about justice must be resolved, (ii) the fact of fundamental disagreement about justice, (iii) that citizens disagreements about justice are reasonable and in good faith, and (iv) that neither (ii) nor (iii) imply any form of moral relativism. I will explain each of these points in turn. 8 Political decisions must be made. For example, while a political community need never make any decision about the nature of the Eucharist it must permit or prohibit faith schools; and while any political decision can be undone or reversed, at any one time it must be resolved one way or another and all citizens are required to respect the decisions made. Furthermore, a determination not to resolve some issues is itself a resolution. The fact of fundamental disagreement about justice is also important to Waldron s argument because, while he introduces the circumstances of politics as a contrast to Rawls, it is certainly not the case that Rawls envisages agreement on 7 Ibid, These points are taken from both Waldron, ibid, chapters five, seven and eight and Waldron, The Core of the Case Against Judicial Review, supra, n 1. In the latter piece Waldron does not use the phrase the circumstances of politics nor does he talk about disagreement about justice; instead he talks about disagreements about rights. However, I take it that the same ideas are in operation. For example, Waldron s idea of rights includes the possibility of socio-economic rights so I take him to be talking about justice as we ordinarily understand the term; and as justice rather than rights fits better with ordinary usage I employ the former term. I should add, though, that this account of the circumstances of politics is an (in my view good) interpretation of Waldron s views; this is because Waldron seems loose in some of his claims.

5 Democracy, Judicial Review and Disagreements About Justice 47 justice on all issues. Rather Rawls thinks that agreement on principles of justice is possible but that there will be lasting disagreement on what legislation and social policies the agreed conception of justice requires; in fact Rawls bases part of his case for democracy on this fact. 9 The key difference between Rawls and Waldron, then, is that, for Waldron, citizens will always disagree about the basic terms and principles of their association 10. There will always be fundamental disagreements about justice 11 and arguments for and against judicial review should be informed by this fact. The third important point is that, for Waldron, disagreements about justice in the circumstances of politics are, for the most part, reasonable and in good faith. [T]here is a strong commitment [to rights/justice] on the part of most members of society [citizens] accept that individuals have certain interests and are entitled to certain liberties that should not be denied simply because it would be more convenient for most people to deny them. 12 Moreover, citizens: care about [rights/justice], they keep their own and others views on rights under constant consideration and lively debate, and they are alert to issues of rights in regard to all the social decisions that are canvassed or discussed in their midst. 13 One reaction to this claim may be that it is straight-forwardly false: many actual disagreements about justice seem not to be reasonable at all. Often disagreements seem to be caused by no more than a deliberate attempt by one group of people to foist their values on to everyone else, and such disagreements are often characterized by each side s distinct lack of respect for those with whom they disagree. As an empirical claim perhaps this is correct but Waldron has good reasons for ignoring unreasonable and bad faith disagreements about justice. First, Waldron wants to develop the core case against judicial review; this requires that his argument applies where all parties have some meaningful commitment to justice (as they differently understand that idea). If Waldron s argument assumes that some citizens reason strategically, are manipulative or have no respect for their opponents his argument may lack scope and may count only as an argument 9 See J Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Oxford University Press, 1999), Waldron, supra, n 6, Ibid, 158 (italics in original). 12 Waldron, supra, n 1, Ibid, 1365.

6 48 Machin against judicial review in fractured societies. 14 The second reason follows from the comments above about the free operation of people s reason: even if selfinterested disagreements about justice cease to exist, fundamental reasonable and good faith disagreements will not so we will still need some account of how such disagreements ought to be resolved. The question of the proper role of judicial review, then, will remain a live one should everyone become reasonable overnight. But how should we explain and understand the permanence of fundamental, and good faith disagreements about justice? Is it the case that citizens disagree about justice because there are no facts of the matter about justice and its requirements? More generally, do the circumstances of politics imply some form of moral relativism? Perhaps citizens disagree because, unlike science, in politics there is no independent subject matter about which they can agree or disagree. Waldron is clear that the circumstances of politics do not imply any form of moral relativism and nor does his argument tacitly assume it: The assumption of disagreement has nothing to do with moral relativism. One can recognize the existence of disagreement on matters of rights and justice without staking the meta-ethical claim that there is no fact of the matter about the issue that the participants are disputing. The recognition of disagreement is perfectly compatible with there being a truth of the matter 15 For Waldron, then, we can meaningfully talk about substantively better and worse decisions; it is just that citizens disagree about which decisions are in fact better or worse. This point is important because I take it that, generally speaking, people are not moral relativists; they do think that laws, judicial rulings etc. can be substantively good or bad and so decisions can be better or worse. It is true that different people will cash out the ideas of better and worse differently some will appeal to the authority of God, others to utility, and yet others will appeal to a privileged decision-making procedure that yields principles of justice but, generally, I take it that most citizens in Western Europe and the USA accept that we meaningfully talk about substantively better or worse laws, and judicial and democratic decisions In fact Waldron is very critical of those who argue for judicial review precisely on the grounds that some citizens are unreasonable. See Waldron, ibid, 2. Waldron identifies the non-core case for and against judicial review as applying to societies in which the commitment to rights is tenuous and fragile. (ibid, 1366). 15 Ibid, Also see Waldron, supra, n 6, chapter eight. 16 Also, if Waldron s argument was predicated on some form of moral relativism it would lose scope quite significantly. For example, to show that his argument was wrong one would be required only to show that there are very few moral relativists or, more laboriously, to argue that moral relativism is itself false. Equally, while the issue of moral relativism is important and interesting, people disagree

7 Democracy, Judicial Review and Disagreements About Justice 49 With the background explained, let us now turn to Waldron s argument. D. RESOLVING DISAGREEMENTS ABOUT JUSTICE IN THE CIRCUMSTANCES OF POLITICS While Waldron s most recent argument against judicial review has invoked what he labels outcome-related reasons, ie, claims about the substance of democratic and judicial decisions, I will develop my argument against him with reference to what, in the same piece, he labels process-related reasons, ie, reasons about the process through which the decisions are made. 17 This is because I take the argument based on process-related reasons to be more central to Waldron s concerns and because, as he himself notes, the argument against judicial review on the basis of outcome-related reasons is less clear cut. Waldron s core claims are as follows: 1. We live in the circumstances of politics, ie, citizens have permanent, fundamental and good faith disagreements about justice which must be resolved. 2. The procedure used to resolve questions of justice must not re-ignite, the controversies whose existence called for a decision-procedure in the first place Disagreements about justice can either by resolved collectively by the citizens (either directly or by their elected representatives) or they can be resolved by some sub-set of the citizenry (e.g., the judiciary). 4. Of whatever decision-making procedure used to resolve issues of justice citizens can ask (i) why did those decisions-makers get to decide? (or [w]hy them? Why not me? 19 ) and (ii) [i]n the decision-procedure that was used, why wasn t greater weight given to the views of those decision-makers who felt as I do about the matter? Given 1-2 above, we cannot appeal to outcomes to answer (i) and (ii). 6. Resolving disagreements collectively by the citizens (either directly or by their elected representatives) is intrinsically fairer than allowing some sub-set of the citizenry to resolve disagreements. This is because a about its truth so Waldron would be unwise to rest any weight on it when offering an argument against judicial review in the face of fundamental disagreement. 17 Waldron, supra, n 1, esp Ibid, Ibid, Ibid.

8 50 Machin collective resolution resolves disagreements about justice in a way that gives citizens the greatest say possible compatible with an equal say for 21 everyone affected by the decisions. Judicial review necessarily excludes most citizens from decision-making and so is intrinsically less fair. 7. Therefore, disagreements about justice must be resolved collectively by the citizens (either directly or by their elected of representatives). This argument is plausible and is, so it seems to me, an argument that is widelyaccepted both inside and outside of academic circles. It is, then, worth interrogating to see whether we should accept its conclusion. We should also note how central the circumstances of politics are to the conclusion. If, say, we assume that society is well-ordered in the Rawlsian sense, ie, that there is agreement on a single conception of justice, then the case for democracy will be different. In a well-ordered society premise 1 is false (and by implication so is 5). If we are all committed to a single conception of justice, then, when determining which procedure to use to address questions of justice there is absolutely no reason why we cannot appeal to the likely outcomes of different decision-making procedures. This is not to say that in the well-ordered society there is no case for democracy; my claim is only that in the well-ordered society any case for democracy will be based on its connection to justice-values, either as a constitutive or intrinsic feature of justice or as the most reliable means to identify the requirements of justice. 22 Importantly, for Waldron, such appeals are illegitimate. The central virtue of Waldron s argument, then, is that, if correct, it rules out judicial review without making any substantive claims about what justice is or what it requires. 23 E. IS JUDICIAL REVIEW ALWAYS IMPERMISSIBLE? So far I have been quite general but to do justice to Waldron s argument and show why it is problematic we need to be more specific. Must all disagreements about justice be resolved democratically? Does Waldron think that there are any circumstances in which judicial review is permissible? Waldron intends his 21 Ibid, For Rawls, democracy is justified both on intrinsic and instrumental grounds. See Rawls, supra, n 9, 37. Also, see Christiano, supra, n 2 for a different argument with similar conclusions. 23 For another argument that tries to rule out non-democratic decision-making without appealing to justice-values see D Estlund, Making Truth Safe for Democracy, in D Copp, J Hampton and J Roemer (eds), The Idea of Democracy (Cambridge University Press, 1993), For an account of why that argument fails, see D Machin, The Irrelevance of Democracy to the Public Justification of Political Authority (2009) Res Publica, published online 19 April 2009.

9 Democracy, Judicial Review and Disagreements About Justice 51 argument to apply only to primary legislation enacted by the elected legislature of a polity 24; it does not apply to executive or administrative decision-making. Therefore, his argument is compatible with some kinds of judicial review; it rules out only strong judicial review that strikes down democratically-enacted legislation. This qualification is plausible and is also widely-shared. While many people think that judicial review has a role in establishing whether the executive has behaved in accordance with the law there is often a sense of outrage when unelected (and by implication unrepresentative) judges strike down legislation that may have sound democratic provenance and be the considered will of the people. However, is there a significant distinction between the judicial review of primary legislation and the judicial review of executive action? The fact of fundamental disagreement about justice is central to Waldron s argument and it does seem that it enables us to draws the distinction that Waldron requires. Intuitively it makes sense to describe a disagreement between two citizens about whether their society should have any free speech laws as, in some sense, a fundamental disagreement about free speech. In contrast, we would not similarly describe a disagreement between the same citizens over whether their society s extant free speech laws require decision A or decision B. The latter kind of disagreement does not seem to be fundamental in the way the former disagreement is. In the next section I will try to establish whether it is possible to draw the distinction Waldron requires. I will argue that the most plausible understanding of what makes a disagreement about justice fundamental is ill-suited to Waldron aims of only ruling out judicial review of primary legislation. I will claim that either Waldron s argument should be rejected or it commits him to the impermissibility of judicial review of executive decisions as well. F. FUNDAMENTAL DISAGREEMENTS ABOUT JUSTICE In order for Waldron s argument to be successful we need an account of why disagreements about primary legislation are fundamental disagreements. Any such account must meet the following conditions: i. It must be informative Waldron cannot simply define fundamental disagreements about justice as disagreements about primary legislation. 24 Waldron, supra, n 1, 1354.

10 52 Machin ii. iii. iv. It must cleave the distinction in the correct place Waldron requires that disagreements about primary legislation are fundamental disagreements but that disagreements about executive and administrative decisions are not. It cannot appeal to any substantive considerations that, to some parties to the disagreement, seem like considerations of justice. Any account of why fundamental disagreements about justice are disagreements about primary legislation that does appeal to substantive justice-like considerations would violate the restrictions imposed by the circumstances of politics and so would be illegitimate by Waldron s own lights. It must be normatively significant any account must attach some normative weight to the idea of a disagreement being fundamental. After all, the issue before is whether such disagreements about justice ought to be resolved democratically. Normative significance is different to condition i. because condition i. can be met by an explanatory account. For example, one important debate in political philosophy is the degree to which it is permissible to treat some people, such as one s conationals or fellow EU citizens, differently to others. 25 One account might refer to the division of the world into states, or claims about shared language and shared history and, in some explanatory sense, this is informative; but such accounts would not justify differential treatment. A further account is needed to show why these facts are morally significant. 26 The next task is to develop a plausible account of what makes a disagreement about justice fundamental and to see if it maps on to conditions i-iv in the right way. I will do this by looking at different kinds of disagreement about justice (in section G) and the different senses in which disagreements can be fundamental (section H). Then (in section I) I will argue that the most plausible understanding of what makes a disagreement about justice fundamental does not satisfy condition ii. Overall, I argue that Waldron s argument fails. In section J I summarize my main claims. 25 For arguments in this debate see T Nagel, The Problem of Global Justice (2005) 33 Philosophy and Public Affairs and A J Julius, Nagel s Atlas (2006) 34 Philosophy and Public Affairs It should also be noted that, in light of condition iii, what makes the account normatively significant cannot appeal to justice-like considerations.

11 Democracy, Judicial Review and Disagreements About Justice 53 G. TYPES OF DISAGREEMENT ABOUT JUSTICE There are many types of disagreement about justice and table 1 below identifies three different types. While table 1 is not exhaustive it is sufficient for our purposes. 27 Table 1: Levels of disagreement about justice 1 Disagreement Disagreements about principles Illustration Rawls and Nozick disagree about principles of justice. 2 Legislative disagreements Should there be laws permitting abortion? If so, under what circumstances? 3 Disagreements about law s application Does a freedom of speech law require that permission be granted to David Irving to visit university X at t? One important thing to note about these three levels of disagreement is the degree of independence between each kind of disagreement. People who disagree at the level of principle can nevertheless agree on what laws there should be. So while Rawls and Nozick disagree about principles of justice, given the history of property rights violations in the USA, they may agree on the sorts of laws that the USA should currently have. For Rawls such laws would be justified by (among other things) his difference principle, and for Nozick they would be justified by his principle of justice in rectification 28. Disagreement at the level of principle, then, does not prohibit agreement at the level of legislation. Similarly, two people can agree on what the law should be but disagree about its application. Two people may, say, agree on a permissive abortion law but disagree that in this case 27 For example, one could add another type of disagreement that is prior to disagreements about principles of justice. People can disagree about what sort of thing justice is about and so what sorts of things are relevant to questions of justice. For example, Rawls and Nozick disagree about what considerations are relevant to justice. For Rawls justice is about freedom and citizens social and economic shares. For Nozick justice is about no more than the protection of people s property rights. 28 See R Nozick, Anarchy, State, and Utopia (Oxford, Blackwell, 1974), chapter seven.

12 54 Machin woman A at t1 should be permitted an abortion. 29 The general point is that agreement or disagreement at any level does not imply agreement or disagreement at another level. 30 Waldron claims that it is acceptable for type 3 disagreements to be resolved through judicial review but that type 2 disagreements disagreements about the content of primary legislation must be resolved democratically. Where do type 1 disagreements fit? As we saw in sections C-D, the circumstances of politics is central to Waldron s argument against judicial review but given the points made above it seems not to be. If there is a degree of independence between agreements and disagreements of type 1 and 2 and as Waldron claims only that disagreements about primary legislation must be addressed democratically perhaps he does not need to invoke the circumstances of politics for his argument. Moreover, as there is no way to resolve disagreements about principles of justice except perhaps through people s convergence on good reason (which seems unlikely) the existence of type 1 disagreements seems irrelevant to Waldron s claims. This, though, is incorrect. The significance for Waldron of disagreements about principles of justice is that they are normatively significant in the same way as disagreements about primary legislation; both should be thought of as fundamental disagreements about justice. Equally, for Waldron, disagreements about law s application are not normatively significant in the same way and so are not fundamental disagreements about justice. Our task, then, is to establish whether there is some account of the idea of a fundamental disagreement about justice that differentiates type 1 and 2 disagreements from type 3 disagreements in a way that respects conditions i-iv above. H. WHAT MAKES A DISAGREEMENT ABOUT JUSTICE FUNDAMENTAL? Below are three ways in which disagreements can be fundamental; as above, this list is not exhaustive but it is sufficient for our purposes: 29 For example, perhaps they disagree about whether a woman in the seventh month of pregnancy should be permitted an abortion so that she can go on a trip abroad. See J J Thomson, A Defense of Abortion (1971) 1 Philosophy and Public Affairs Thomson thinks that, in this case, an abortion would be indecent. 30 Although it may in fact be the case that people use differences at one level as proxies or short-hand for differences at other levels. For example, socialists may use their disagreement with conservatives principles to imply that they should disagree with conservatives legislative proposals as well. There may be many reasons for this but they will probably include the fact that an assessment of legislative proposals is more time-consuming,

13 Democracy, Judicial Review and Disagreements About Justice 55 a) Basic disagreements: A disagreement can be fundamental when there is no more basic disagreement to be had, such that if two people disagree they no longer have anything to say to each other. An example of this could be a disagreement between an atheist and a Christian. If an atheist claims that she has never seen any reason to believe in God and has never felt the need to believe in God there is very little the Christian can say to continue the discussion, except perhaps by appealing to the role of faith. Beyond this probably unsuccessful appeal, though, any discussion must probably end. b) Justificatory disagreements: A disagreement can be fundamental in a justificatory sense. So, if you ask X why she went to the shops and she says that she went to get some apples you can press her and ask why she wants apples. Ultimately, she may say to make apple pie because I like apple pie. It is X s liking of apple pie that explains and justifies her actions. A disagreement in this sense, then, would be about whether apple pie is in fact likeable. If it is likeable, X s actions are justified; if is not, they are not. As this example neatly illustrates, justificatory disagreements may admit of no uniquely correct resolution. c) Disagreements over interests (or interest-disagreements): A disagreement can be fundamental when it is a disagreement about a person s interests in living their life the way they want to or think is valuable. So, for example, a parent and child can have a fundamental disagreement about whether the child should go to university. The parent may want the child to go and the child may resist. In making her case the parent may appeal to the child s long-term interests but the child may respond that she has other plans for her life and she does not want to live the kind of life her parent describes. This kind of disagreement would be about the child s interest in living the life she wants to and in becoming a certain kind of person. It is clear that each kind of disagreement is, at least in some sense, fundamental and many actual disagreements can be fundamental in more than one sense: but in what sense is Waldron using fundamental and is it the most appropriate understanding of the term? Superficially it may seem that disagreements about principles of justice are basic disagreements. For example, at some point Nozick and Rawls will cease to have anything to say to each other about justice and this seems to be because they disagree about principles of justice; they have very few shared premises. Conceiving of disagreements about principles of justice as basic disagreements, though, is incorrect. People can disagree about principles of

14 56 Machin justice but agree about what sorts of things are relevant to principles of justice. So even where they disagree about principles they will still have things to say to each other, and while there may be some kind of basic disagreement between the two at some point it will not be over principles of justice. 31 We should also reject the idea that disagreements about primary legislation are basic disagreements; this is because, as was noted above, two people can disagree about primary legislation but agree on principles of justice. Citizens who disagree about what the law should be then may still have many things to say to each other and to agree on. In light of this, we will focus on b) and c). It seems that Waldron wants us to understand the idea of a fundamental disagreement as a justificatory disagreement. For example, when citizen A is coerced to desist from Z-ing and is taken to the police station, any answer to A s protestations about why this is happening would refer to the law prohibiting Z- type acts; it is the existence of the law that in this case justifies the coercive acts of the police. The idea of a justificatory disagreement as a fundamental disagreement, then, makes legislative disagreements fundamental but not disagreements about the law s application; the application of a law will always stand in need of a justification that is provided by the law itself. 32 Furthermore, fundamental disagreements as justificatory disagreements also makes disagreements about principles of justice fundamental. This is because in explaining and justifying any law reference will be made to the principles that underpin it. So, if Z is an act of hate-speech, when justifying A s arrest the police or the courts may refer to the reasons why hate-speech is unacceptable; this will invoke ideas and principles about citizens entitlements and what counts as the just treatment of other people. Conceiving of fundamental disagreements about justice as justificatory disagreements, then, enables us to identify a similarity between a) disagreements about justice and b) legislative disagreements that distinguishes them from c) disagreements about law s application. In doing this it enables us to satisfy condition ii. above, ie, it cleaves the fundamental/non-fundamental distinction in 31 The disagreement between Sen and Rawls about the importance of primary goods is an illustration of people who disagree about principles of justice but who still have a great deal to discuss and so agree and disagree about. See A Sen, Equality of What? (1979) The Tanner Lecture on Human Values, delivered at Stanford University May 22, See (last accessed on 23 May 2006). 32 It is for this reason that a legislature is seen as the fundamental decision-making body within a polity; it determines what justice requires while other decision-making bodies exist only to implement whatever the legislature determines. For example, if a law is passed that demands certain health and safety features in all workplaces an executive decision-making body will implement this law; it will determine what it requires in different kinds of workplace and it will administer the law. If there are questions of the law s violation judicial decision-making bodies will determine whether any violation has occurred and what punishment, if any, is necessary. However, if the law becomes problematic, inadequate or, due to changing circumstances, redundant only the legislature can change or revoke it; otherwise it must continue to be implemented.

15 Democracy, Judicial Review and Disagreements About Justice 57 the correct place. Furthermore, because the distinction is found at the level of justification this account is informative and it does not appeal to any justice-like considerations. Conditions i and iii, then, are also met. But what of condition iv? As outlined, justificatory disagreements are normatively significant but, so I will argue, they are not as normatively significant as interest-disagreements about justice. To see why this is the case let us turn to interest-disagreements. Interest-disagreements about justice are fundamental because they are disagreements about the connection between citizens beliefs and their actions, in particular what they are required to do and prohibited from doing. So, in the example above the disagreement between the parent and child is over what actions the child should perform in light of the beliefs she has, or (to take the parent s side) the beliefs the child ought to have, or even about what the child s future beliefs will be about the actions she wished she had performed in the past. Do interest-disagreements map the distinction Waldron draws? Unfortunately, they do not. Disagreements over citizens interests can occur at any level. Some citizens may be Rawlsians and so will disagree at the level of principle with other citizens; while other citizens may want to live in the sort of society that prohibits bloodsports and so will disagree with other citizens about what the law should be. It will also be the case that citizens interests in living the life they want to or think is valuable will be determined not just by what the law is but also by how it is applied. For example, two citizens may agree that their society should have a law permitting abortion where pregnancy and/or child-rearing will cause hardship to the prospective mother but disagree that in this case there will be any hardship. And if we imagine that one of the parties to this disagreement is the prospective mother in question we can see how this is a disagreement about a citizen s interests in living the life she wants to or thinks is valuable; it is not, though, a disagreement at the level of principle nor is it a disagreement about what the law should be. Fundamental disagreements as interest-disagreements, then, can occur at any of the levels outlined in table 1. So, if we should understand fundamental disagreements about justice this way condition ii is not met: there is no distinction to draw that makes only some types of disagreement about justice fundamental. Clearly this is not how Waldron wants us to interpret the idea of fundamental disagreements about justice. So, which of the two accounts is to be preferred? Both are informative and neither appeals to considerations that to some citizens may seem justice-like and both appeal to normatively significant ideas about why that type of disagreement is fundamental. What is to be done? As our enquiry is about whether disagreements about justice ought to be resolved democratically the appropriate next step is to interrogate the normative significance of the two accounts a little further.

16 58 Machin I. INTEREST-DISAGREEMENTS AS FUNDAMENTAL DISAGREEMENTS It is reasonably clear why interest-disagreements are fundamental. After all, that citizens have a fundamental interest in living the life they want to or think is valuable makes sense without any specification of what individual citizen s interests are. Moreover, all things equal, all citizens are entitled to live the life they want to or think is valuable. 33 Is it equally clear why justificatory disagreements are fundamental? 34 In spite of the account in section H we can still ask of J-disagreements what is significant about them? They are not directly about what citizens are required to do; they are primarily about why citizens are required to behave in certain ways. Obviously, there is some connection between the-what and the-why but as there is also a degree of independence between justification and action after all different reasons can justify the same action we are entitled to further explanation. If this is the case the next logical step is to explain why J-disagreements are fundamental in terms of their connection to citizens interests in living the life they want to or think is valuable. For example, in the hate-speech illustration above presumably A is forced not to Z because it is believed that Z-ing has a detrimental effect on some citizens ability to freely move around without feeling oppressed and/or because it affects citizens self-conception as others moral equals. So conceived, the best way to understand the prohibition on Z is because Z is generally incompatible with some citizens interests in living the life they want to or think is valuable. After all, if no-one were negatively affected by hatespeech it would be odd to prohibit it. The general point is that in completing the account of the normative significance of J-disagreements we appeal to how J-disagreements are also I- disagreements and so we appeal to the greater normative significance of I- disagreements. But completing the account this way also gives I-disagreements greater explanatory power than J-disagreements. This is because I-disagreements can explain why justificatory disagreements are fundamental disagreements. We should, then, explain why justificatory disagreements are fundamental in terms of interest-disagreements; the latter are more fundamental. If this is correct Waldron s argument is in trouble. I-disagreements do not identify legislative disagreements or disagreements about principles as any more 33 Of course, not all things are equal citizens have contrary interests, some have offensive or pernicious preferences, and the world has finite resources for which we all compete. This is why these disagreements require some kind of authoritative resolution. 34 In this section the phrases interest disagreements and justificatory disagreements will occur a lot, often in the same sentence. To ease the reader s burden I introduce abbreviations and refer to the disagreements as I-disagreements and J-disagreements respectively.

17 Democracy, Judicial Review and Disagreements About Justice 59 or less fundamental than disagreements about law s application. Waldron s rationale for the impermissibility of the judicial review of primary legislation then falls. I will look into the implications of this in sections J-K; for the moment I want to consider two objections that Waldron may make. The first invokes an affecting all, non-affecting all distinction; the idea that law affects all citizens is important for Waldron. He notes that: If we believe that everyone affected by a problem has the right to a say in its solution, then there is nothing to do but set up a procedure for counting and somehow assessing millions of different opinions. 35 and that: if the problem affects millions, then a respectful decision procedure requires those millions to listen to one another to settle on a common policy in a way that takes everyone s opinion into account. 36 And again : What touches all should be decided by all. 37 The idea here, then, is that legislation is fundamental because all citizens are affected by it. This seems plausible and it may also help Waldron to draw the distinction he needs because it can seem that disagreements over a law s application do not affect all citizens; rather they affect only those who are party to any particular decision. If this is correct, then there is a normatively significant difference between the judicial review of primary legislation and the judicial review of its application. The problem with this objection is easy to spot: all that has been achieved is to replace one claim that needs explanation (ie, what makes a disagreement fundamental?) with another that requires just as much explanation. What is it to be affected by a law? On a common sense level it is simply false to claim that everyone is affected either by all laws or by the problems that laws are intended to solve. For example, is a single male who intends on maturity to enter the Catholic priesthood affected by an abortion law? Perhaps we can presume that he believes that abortion is wrong but we need some account of why that constitutes being affected by an abortion law. This is particularly important because, at an empirical level, it is simply not true that the judicial review of a 35 Waldron, supra, n 6, Ibid. 37 Ibid, 114.

18 60 Machin law s application will affect fewer people than the judicial review of legislation. Judicial review of executive decisions can set precedents which in turn will affect how similar cases are dealt with in the future whereas some legislation may only ever affect very few people. Certainly there will be ways of cashing out affectedness appropriately but they will not be unproblematic. For example Christiano 38 argues that citizens have fundamental interests in feeling at home in their society where feeling at home constitutes some form of emotional identification with one s polity. This could form the basis of an argument to show that one is affected by the existence of laws with which one disagrees or thinks are wrong even if one is materially unaffected by such laws. But Christiano s claim is part of a broader conception of justice and, so it seems me, it will be very difficult to cash out any appropriate conception of affectedness that does not seem, to some citizens at least, like a substantive consideration of justice. The inference to draw from this is that without unpacking affectedness what it is to be affected by a law or a decision is simply too vague to enable us to pick out classes of, or kinds of, disagreements about justice. The second objection is that I am focusing on the wrong issue. Waldron could claim that it is not the kind of disagreement that is normatively significant but it is the kind of things the law and principles of justice are that makes them fundamental. Let me explain the claim then show why it, too, fails. The key idea is that what appropriate principles of justice are and what the law should be are essentially contested hence the circumstances of politics but that once we have established some law (whatever it is) its application is primarily a technical enterprise that is not essentially contested and so can be carried out without controversy by appointed specialists. These specialists, ie, judges, need only know what the law is, understand how their legal system works, and grasp the idea of the rule of law in order to adjudicate cases properly. When making decisions judges need not invoke their own moral views nor rely on their own judgement (beyond, of course, identifying the relevant points of law). If this contrast is valid, it may warrant treating disagreements about the application of law very differently to disagreements about what the law should be. The problem is that in reality this contrast is nowhere near as clear as these comments imply. It is beyond the scope of this paper to offer an assessment of essential contestability 39 so I will confine my comments here to showing that the 38 See T Christiano, The Authority of Democracy (2004) 12 Journal of Political Philosophy 266; and Christiano, supra, n 2, chapters two and three. 39 Although on the issue see J Gray, On the Contestability of Social and Political Concepts (1977) 5 Political Theory 331, and J Gray, On Liberty, Liberalism and Essential Contestability (1978) 8 British Journal of Political Science 385.

19 Democracy, Judicial Review and Disagreements About Justice 61 application of the law is not merely a technical enterprise. I do not want to claim that the model of the law just outlined does not fit many actual legal cases; all I hope to show is that it does not fit all cases, and in particular it does not fit those cases that are likely to come become subject to judicial review. There are two reasons for this. First, many cases of judicial review will be about citizens (and non-citizens ) fundamental rights 40, such as their right to die, their rights to free speech or their right to marry; and in such cases it will be very difficult for the judgement of the decision-makers to be completely unaffected by their own moral views of the matter. Second, many citizens will have firmly-held views on these matters that will be incompatible with whatever decisions are made in particular cases; this is in part because laws are not self-applying; they must be interpreted and this requires judgement and there will always be room to disagree about whether any particular judge s judgment is the correct one. For example, to elaborate on the abortion illustration from section H, if there is a law permitting abortion in cases of physical or mental hardship then, whatever judgements are made in particular cases, some citizens will disagree that the judgements are correct. They will have their own views about what constitutes hardship and will weigh the relevant factors differently. So, if such cases are addressed by the judiciary, some citizens will in good faith ask of those judgements why was I excluded? I would have weighed the relevant issues differently. Or, Why didn t a judge who agrees with me hear the case? 41 The considerations that tell against judicial review of primary legislation, then, tell just as much against judicial review of a particular law s application. I conclude, then, that the contrast between the essentially contested task of law-making and the technical enterprise of applying the law does not reflect how the law does work or can reasonably be expected to work. The second objection fails. Overall, I conclude that the most plausible way of understanding the idea of fundamental disagreements about justice does not map the kinds of disagreements outlined in table 1 in the way Waldron requires. Let me now summarize the argument. We will see that Waldron may not be too dissatisfied with its conclusion. 40 I use fundamental here in a loose intuitive sense. 41 This is premise four of Waldron s argument from section D.

POLITICAL AUTHORITY AND PERFECTIONISM: A RESPONSE TO QUONG

POLITICAL AUTHORITY AND PERFECTIONISM: A RESPONSE TO QUONG SYMPOSIUM POLITICAL LIBERALISM VS. LIBERAL PERFECTIONISM POLITICAL AUTHORITY AND PERFECTIONISM: A RESPONSE TO QUONG JOSEPH CHAN 2012 Philosophy and Public Issues (New Series), Vol. 2, No. 1 (2012): pp.

More information

Rawls versus the Anarchist: Justice and Legitimacy

Rawls versus the Anarchist: Justice and Legitimacy Rawls versus the Anarchist: Justice and Legitimacy Walter E. Schaller Texas Tech University APA Central Division April 2005 Section 1: The Anarchist s Argument In a recent article, Justification and Legitimacy,

More information

Is Rawls s Difference Principle Preferable to Luck Egalitarianism?

Is Rawls s Difference Principle Preferable to Luck Egalitarianism? Western University Scholarship@Western 2014 Undergraduate Awards The Undergraduate Awards 2014 Is Rawls s Difference Principle Preferable to Luck Egalitarianism? Taylor C. Rodrigues Western University,

More information

Introduction 478 U.S. 186 (1986) U.S. 558 (2003). 3

Introduction 478 U.S. 186 (1986) U.S. 558 (2003). 3 Introduction In 2003 the Supreme Court of the United States overturned its decision in Bowers v. Hardwick and struck down a Texas law that prohibited homosexual sodomy. 1 Writing for the Court in Lawrence

More information

Politics between Philosophy and Democracy

Politics between Philosophy and Democracy Leopold Hess Politics between Philosophy and Democracy In the present paper I would like to make some comments on a classic essay of Michael Walzer Philosophy and Democracy. The main purpose of Walzer

More information

DEMOCRACY AND EQUALITY

DEMOCRACY AND EQUALITY The Philosophical Quarterly 2007 ISSN 0031 8094 doi: 10.1111/j.1467-9213.2007.495.x DEMOCRACY AND EQUALITY BY STEVEN WALL Many writers claim that democratic government rests on a principled commitment

More information

Law and Philosophy (2015) 34: Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2015 DOI /s ARIE ROSEN BOOK REVIEW

Law and Philosophy (2015) 34: Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2015 DOI /s ARIE ROSEN BOOK REVIEW Law and Philosophy (2015) 34: 699 708 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2015 DOI 10.1007/s10982-015-9239-8 ARIE ROSEN (Accepted 31 August 2015) Alon Harel, Why Law Matters. Oxford: Oxford University

More information

Thom Brooks University of Newcastle, UK

Thom Brooks University of Newcastle, UK Equality and democracy: the problem of minimal competency * Thom Brooks University of Newcastle, UK ABSTRACT. In a recent article, Thomas Christiano defends the intrinsic justice of democracy grounded

More information

CHAPTER 1 PROLOGUE: VALUES AND PERSPECTIVES

CHAPTER 1 PROLOGUE: VALUES AND PERSPECTIVES CHAPTER 1 PROLOGUE: VALUES AND PERSPECTIVES Final draft July 2009 This Book revolves around three broad kinds of questions: $ What kind of society is this? $ How does it really work? Why is it the way

More information

The Justification of Justice as Fairness: A Two Stage Process

The Justification of Justice as Fairness: A Two Stage Process The Justification of Justice as Fairness: A Two Stage Process TED VAGGALIS University of Kansas The tragic truth about philosophy is that misunderstanding occurs more frequently than understanding. Nowhere

More information

The character of public reason in Rawls s theory of justice

The character of public reason in Rawls s theory of justice A.L. Mohamed Riyal (1) The character of public reason in Rawls s theory of justice (1) Faculty of Arts and Culture, South Eastern University of Sri Lanka, Oluvil, Sri Lanka. Abstract: The objective of

More information

Philosophy 267 Fall, 2010 Professor Richard Arneson Introductory Handout revised 11/09 Texts: Course requirements: Week 1. September 28.

Philosophy 267 Fall, 2010 Professor Richard Arneson Introductory Handout revised 11/09 Texts: Course requirements: Week 1. September 28. 1 Philosophy 267 Fall, 2010 Professor Richard Arneson Introductory Handout revised 11/09 Class meets Tuesdays 1-4 in the Department seminar room. My email: rarneson@ucsd.edu This course considers some

More information

The limits of background justice. Thomas Porter. Social Philosophy & Policy volume 30, issues 1 2. Cambridge University Press

The limits of background justice. Thomas Porter. Social Philosophy & Policy volume 30, issues 1 2. Cambridge University Press The limits of background justice Thomas Porter Social Philosophy & Policy volume 30, issues 1 2 Cambridge University Press Abstract The argument from background justice is that conformity to Lockean principles

More information

The limits of background justice. Thomas Porter. Rawls says that the primary subject of justice is what he calls the basic structure of

The limits of background justice. Thomas Porter. Rawls says that the primary subject of justice is what he calls the basic structure of The limits of background justice Thomas Porter Rawls says that the primary subject of justice is what he calls the basic structure of society. The basic structure is, roughly speaking, the way in which

More information

Social and Political Philosophy

Social and Political Philosophy Schedule Social and Political Philosophy Philosophy 33 Fall 2006 Wednesday, 30 August OVERVIEW I have two aspirations for this course. First, I would like to cover what the major texts in political philosophy

More information

E-LOGOS. Rawls two principles of justice: their adoption by rational self-interested individuals. University of Economics Prague

E-LOGOS. Rawls two principles of justice: their adoption by rational self-interested individuals. University of Economics Prague E-LOGOS ELECTRONIC JOURNAL FOR PHILOSOPHY ISSN 1211-0442 1/2010 University of Economics Prague Rawls two principles of justice: their adoption by rational self-interested individuals e Alexandra Dobra

More information

Jan Narveson and James P. Sterba

Jan Narveson and James P. Sterba 1 Introduction RISTOTLE A held that equals should be treated equally and unequals unequally. Yet Aristotle s ideal of equality was a relatively formal one that allowed for considerable inequality. Likewise,

More information

Do we have a strong case for open borders?

Do we have a strong case for open borders? Do we have a strong case for open borders? Joseph Carens [1987] challenges the popular view that admission of immigrants by states is only a matter of generosity and not of obligation. He claims that the

More information

CHAPTER 1 PROLOGUE: VALUES AND PERSPECTIVES

CHAPTER 1 PROLOGUE: VALUES AND PERSPECTIVES CHAPTER 1 PROLOGUE: VALUES AND PERSPECTIVES Final draft July 2009 This Book revolves around three broad kinds of questions: $ What kind of society is this? $ How does it really work? Why is it the way

More information

Comments on Justin Weinberg s Is Government Supererogation Possible? Public Reason Political Philosophy Symposium Friday October 17, 2008

Comments on Justin Weinberg s Is Government Supererogation Possible? Public Reason Political Philosophy Symposium Friday October 17, 2008 Helena de Bres Wellesley College Department of Philosophy hdebres@wellesley.edu Comments on Justin Weinberg s Is Government Supererogation Possible? Public Reason Political Philosophy Symposium Friday

More information

PUBLIC POLICY RESEARCH PAPER SERIES

PUBLIC POLICY RESEARCH PAPER SERIES Authority, Equality and Democracy Andrei Marmor USC Public Policy Research Paper No. 03-15 PUBLIC POLICY RESEARCH PAPER SERIES University of Southern California Law School Los Angeles, CA 90089-0071 This

More information

Ethics Handout 18 Rawls, Classical Utilitarianism and Nagel, Equality

Ethics Handout 18 Rawls, Classical Utilitarianism and Nagel, Equality 24.231 Ethics Handout 18 Rawls, Classical Utilitarianism and Nagel, Equality The Utilitarian Principle of Distribution: Society is rightly ordered, and therefore just, when its major institutions are arranged

More information

Political Norms and Moral Values

Political Norms and Moral Values Penultimate version - Forthcoming in Journal of Philosophical Research (2015) Political Norms and Moral Values Robert Jubb University of Leicester rj138@leicester.ac.uk Department of Politics & International

More information

Reconciling Educational Adequacy and Equity Arguments Through a Rawlsian Lens

Reconciling Educational Adequacy and Equity Arguments Through a Rawlsian Lens Reconciling Educational Adequacy and Equity Arguments Through a Rawlsian Lens John Pijanowski Professor of Educational Leadership University of Arkansas Spring 2015 Abstract A theory of educational opportunity

More information

Political equality, wealth and democracy

Political equality, wealth and democracy 1 Political equality, wealth and democracy Wealth, power and influence are often mentioned together as symbols of status and prestige. Yet in a democracy, they can make an unhappy combination. If a democratic

More information

Phil 115, June 20, 2007 Justice as fairness as a political conception: the fact of reasonable pluralism and recasting the ideas of Theory

Phil 115, June 20, 2007 Justice as fairness as a political conception: the fact of reasonable pluralism and recasting the ideas of Theory Phil 115, June 20, 2007 Justice as fairness as a political conception: the fact of reasonable pluralism and recasting the ideas of Theory The problem with the argument for stability: In his discussion

More information

LEGAL POSITIVISM AND NATURAL LAW RECONSIDERED

LEGAL POSITIVISM AND NATURAL LAW RECONSIDERED LEGAL POSITIVISM AND NATURAL LAW RECONSIDERED David Brink Introduction, Polycarp Ikuenobe THE CONTEMPORARY AMERICAN PHILOSOPHER David Brink examines the views of legal positivism and natural law theory

More information

Incentives and the Natural Duties of Justice

Incentives and the Natural Duties of Justice Politics (2000) 20(1) pp. 19 24 Incentives and the Natural Duties of Justice Colin Farrelly 1 In this paper I explore a possible response to G.A. Cohen s critique of the Rawlsian defence of inequality-generating

More information

Lahore University of Management Sciences. Phil 228/Pol 207 Contemporary Debates in Political Philosophy Summer 2017

Lahore University of Management Sciences. Phil 228/Pol 207 Contemporary Debates in Political Philosophy Summer 2017 Phil 228/Pol 207 Contemporary Debates in Political Philosophy Summer 2017 Instructor Room No. Office Hours Email Telephone Secretary/TA TA Office Hours Course URL (if any) Anwar ul Haq TBA TBA anwarul.haq@lums.edu.pk

More information

Playing Fair and Following the Rules

Playing Fair and Following the Rules JOURNAL OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY brill.com/jmp Playing Fair and Following the Rules Justin Tosi Department of Philosophy, University of Michigan jtosi@umich.edu Abstract In his paper Fairness, Political Obligation,

More information

Great Philosophers: John Rawls ( ) Brian Carey 13/11/18

Great Philosophers: John Rawls ( ) Brian Carey 13/11/18 Great Philosophers: John Rawls (1921-2002) Brian Carey 13/11/18 Structure: Biography A Theory of Justice (1971) Political Liberalism (1993) The Law of Peoples (1999) Legacy Biography: Born in Baltimore,

More information

Theories of Social Justice

Theories of Social Justice Theories of Social Justice Political Science 331/5331 Professor: Frank Lovett Assistant: William O Brochta Fall 2017 flovett@wustl.edu Monday/Wednesday Office Hours: Mondays and Time: 2:30 4:00 pm Wednesdays,

More information

What is the Relationship Between The Idea of the Minimum and Distributive Justice?

What is the Relationship Between The Idea of the Minimum and Distributive Justice? What is the Relationship Between The Idea of the Minimum and Distributive Justice? David Bilchitz 1 1. The Question of Minimums in Distributive Justice Human beings have a penchant for thinking about minimum

More information

When Does Equality Matter? T. M. Scanlon. Lecture 1: Introduction. Our country, and the world, are marked by extraordinarily high levels of

When Does Equality Matter? T. M. Scanlon. Lecture 1: Introduction. Our country, and the world, are marked by extraordinarily high levels of When Does Equality Matter? T. M. Scanlon Lecture 1: Introduction Our country, and the world, are marked by extraordinarily high levels of inequality. This inequality raises important empirical questions,

More information

Political Obligation 4

Political Obligation 4 Political Obligation 4 Dr Simon Beard Sjb316@cam.ac.uk Centre for the Study of Existential Risk Summary of this lecture Why Philosophical Anarchism doesn t usually involve smashing the system or wearing

More information

ELIMINATING CORRECTIVE JUSTICE. Steven Walt *

ELIMINATING CORRECTIVE JUSTICE. Steven Walt * ELIMINATING CORRECTIVE JUSTICE Steven Walt * D ISTRIBUTIVE justice describes the morally required distribution of shares of resources and liberty among people. Corrective justice describes the moral obligation

More information

Political Obligation 2

Political Obligation 2 Political Obligation 2 Dr Simon Beard Sjb316@cam.ac.uk Centre for the Study of Existential Risk Summary of this lecture What was David Hume actually objecting to in his attacks on Classical Social Contract

More information

Justice and Democracy

Justice and Democracy CPSA Draft Justice and Democracy Laura Valentini Princeton & Oxford laura.valentini@queens.ox.ac.uk Abstract: Is democracy a requirement of justice or an instrument for realizing it? The correct answer

More information

Two Pictures of the Global-justice Debate: A Reply to Tan*

Two Pictures of the Global-justice Debate: A Reply to Tan* 219 Two Pictures of the Global-justice Debate: A Reply to Tan* Laura Valentini London School of Economics and Political Science 1. Introduction Kok-Chor Tan s review essay offers an internal critique of

More information

Democratic Rights and the Choice of Economic Systems

Democratic Rights and the Choice of Economic Systems A&K Analyse & Kritik 2017; 39(2):405 412 Discussion: Comments on J. Holt, Requirements of Justice and Liberal Socialism Jeppe von Platz* Democratic Rights and the Choice of Economic Systems https://doi.org/10.1515/auk-2017-0022

More information

Justice and collective responsibility. Zoltan Miklosi. regardless of the institutional or other relations that may obtain among them.

Justice and collective responsibility. Zoltan Miklosi. regardless of the institutional or other relations that may obtain among them. Justice and collective responsibility Zoltan Miklosi Introduction Cosmopolitan conceptions of justice hold that the principles of justice are properly applied to evaluate the situation of all human beings,

More information

Comment on Baker's Autonomy and Free Speech

Comment on Baker's Autonomy and Free Speech University of Minnesota Law School Scholarship Repository Constitutional Commentary 2011 Comment on Baker's Autonomy and Free Speech T.M. Scanlon Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.law.umn.edu/concomm

More information

THE POSSIBILITY OF A FAIR PLAY ACCOUNT OF LEGITIMACY. Justin Tosi

THE POSSIBILITY OF A FAIR PLAY ACCOUNT OF LEGITIMACY. Justin Tosi VC 2015 John Wiley & Sons Ltd Ratio (new series) XXX 1 March 2017 0034-0006 doi: 10.1111/rati.12114 THE POSSIBILITY OF A FAIR PLAY ACCOUNT OF LEGITIMACY Justin Tosi Abstract The philosophical literature

More information

AMY GUTMANN: THE CONSTRUCTIVE POTENTIAL OF COMMUNITARIAN VALUES DOES GUTMANN SUCCEED IN SHOWING THE CONSTRUCTIVE POTENTIAL OF COMMUNITARIAN VALUES?

AMY GUTMANN: THE CONSTRUCTIVE POTENTIAL OF COMMUNITARIAN VALUES DOES GUTMANN SUCCEED IN SHOWING THE CONSTRUCTIVE POTENTIAL OF COMMUNITARIAN VALUES? AMY GUTMANN: THE CONSTRUCTIVE POTENTIAL OF COMMUNITARIAN VALUES DOES GUTMANN SUCCEED IN SHOWING THE CONSTRUCTIVE POTENTIAL OF COMMUNITARIAN VALUES? 1 The view of Amy Gutmann is that communitarians have

More information

Multiculturalism and liberal democracy

Multiculturalism and liberal democracy Will Kymlicka, Filimon Peonidis Multiculturalism and liberal democracy Published 25 July 2008 Original in English First published in Cogito (Greece) 7 (2008) (Greek version) Downloaded from eurozine.com

More information

From the veil of ignorance to the overlapping consensus: John Rawls as a theorist of communication

From the veil of ignorance to the overlapping consensus: John Rawls as a theorist of communication From the veil of ignorance to the overlapping consensus: John Rawls as a theorist of communication Klaus Bruhn Jensen Professor, dr.phil. Department of Media, Cognition, and Communication University of

More information

Theories of Justice. Is economic inequality unjust? Ever? Always? Why?

Theories of Justice. Is economic inequality unjust? Ever? Always? Why? Fall 2016 Theories of Justice Professor Pevnick (rp90@nyu.edu) Office: 19 West 4 th St., #326 Office Hours: Tuesday 9:30-11:30am or by appointment Course Description Political life is rife with conflict

More information

4AANB006 Political Philosophy I Syllabus Academic year

4AANB006 Political Philosophy I Syllabus Academic year 4AANB006 Political Philosophy I Syllabus Academic year 2015-16 Basic information Credits: 15 Module Tutor: Dr Sarah Fine Office: 902 Consultation time: Tuesdays 12pm, and Thursdays 12pm. Semester: Second

More information

On Original Appropriation. Peter Vallentyne, University of Missouri-Columbia

On Original Appropriation. Peter Vallentyne, University of Missouri-Columbia On Original Appropriation Peter Vallentyne, University of Missouri-Columbia in Malcolm Murray, ed., Liberty, Games and Contracts: Jan Narveson and the Defence of Libertarianism (Aldershot: Ashgate Press,

More information

John Rawls. Cambridge University Press John Rawls: An Introduction Percy B. Lehning Frontmatter More information

John Rawls. Cambridge University Press John Rawls: An Introduction Percy B. Lehning Frontmatter More information John Rawls What is a just political order? What does justice require of us? These are perennial questions of political philosophy. John Rawls, generally acknowledged to be one of the most influential political

More information

Lahore University of Management Sciences. Phil 323/Pol 305 Contemporary Debates in Political Philosophy Fall

Lahore University of Management Sciences. Phil 323/Pol 305 Contemporary Debates in Political Philosophy Fall Phil 323/Pol 305 Contemporary Debates in Political Philosophy Fall 2013-14 Instructor Anwar ul Haq Room No. 219, new SS wing Office Hours TBA Email anwarul.haq@lums.edu.pk Telephone Ext. 8221 Secretary/TA

More information

Penalizing Public Disobedience*

Penalizing Public Disobedience* DISCUSSION Penalizing Public Disobedience* Kimberley Brownlee I In a recent article, David Lefkowitz argues that members of liberal democracies have a moral right to engage in acts of suitably constrained

More information

Volume 60, Issue 1 Page 241. Stanford. Cass R. Sunstein

Volume 60, Issue 1 Page 241. Stanford. Cass R. Sunstein Volume 60, Issue 1 Page 241 Stanford Law Review ON AVOIDING FOUNDATIONAL QUESTIONS A REPLY TO ANDREW COAN Cass R. Sunstein 2007 the Board of Trustees of the Leland Stanford Junior University, from the

More information

Why Does Inequality Matter? T. M. Scanlon. Chapter 8: Unequal Outcomes. It is well known that there has been an enormous increase in inequality in the

Why Does Inequality Matter? T. M. Scanlon. Chapter 8: Unequal Outcomes. It is well known that there has been an enormous increase in inequality in the Why Does Inequality Matter? T. M. Scanlon Chapter 8: Unequal Outcomes It is well known that there has been an enormous increase in inequality in the United States and other developed economies in recent

More information

Global Justice and Two Kinds of Liberalism

Global Justice and Two Kinds of Liberalism Global Justice and Two Kinds of Liberalism Christopher Lowry Dept. of Philosophy, Queen s University christopher.r.lowry@gmail.com Paper prepared for CPSA, June 2008 In a recent article, Nagel (2005) distinguishes

More information

-Capitalism, Exploitation and Injustice-

-Capitalism, Exploitation and Injustice- UPF - MA Political Philosophy Modern Political Philosophy Elisabet Puigdollers Mas -Capitalism, Exploitation and Injustice- Introduction Although Marx fiercely criticized the theories of justice and some

More information

Proceduralism and Epistemic Value of Democracy

Proceduralism and Epistemic Value of Democracy 1 Paper to be presented at the symposium on Democracy and Authority by David Estlund in Oslo, December 7-9 2009 (Draft) Proceduralism and Epistemic Value of Democracy Some reflections and questions on

More information

In his account of justice as fairness, Rawls argues that treating the members of a

In his account of justice as fairness, Rawls argues that treating the members of a Justice, Fall 2003 Feminism and Multiculturalism 1. Equality: Form and Substance In his account of justice as fairness, Rawls argues that treating the members of a society as free and equal achieving fair

More information

Last time we discussed a stylized version of the realist view of global society.

Last time we discussed a stylized version of the realist view of global society. Political Philosophy, Spring 2003, 1 The Terrain of a Global Normative Order 1. Realism and Normative Order Last time we discussed a stylized version of the realist view of global society. According to

More information

Justice As Fairness: A Restatement Books

Justice As Fairness: A Restatement Books Justice As Fairness: A Restatement Books This book originated as lectures for a course on political philosophy that Rawls taught regularly at Harvard in the 1980s. In time the lectures became a restatement

More information

Media Ethics, Class 3: What is The Media Doing, What should they do?

Media Ethics, Class 3: What is The Media Doing, What should they do? Media Ethics, Class 3: What is The Media Doing, What should they do? Today: A. Review B. Chomsky (the movie) A. Review Philosophy, and the accumulation of knowledge generally, is a collective undertaking

More information

INSTITUTIONAL ISSUES INVOLVING ETHICS AND JUSTICE Vol.I - Economic Justice - Hon-Lam Li

INSTITUTIONAL ISSUES INVOLVING ETHICS AND JUSTICE Vol.I - Economic Justice - Hon-Lam Li ECONOMIC JUSTICE Hon-Lam Li Chinese University of Hong Kong, Hong Kong Keywords: Analytical Marxism, capitalism, communism, complex equality, democratic socialism, difference principle, equality, exploitation,

More information

Comment on Véronique Zanetti. On Moral Compromise

Comment on Véronique Zanetti. On Moral Compromise Analyse & Kritik 02/2011 ( c Lucius & Lucius, Stuttgart) S. 441448 Timothy Waligore Comment on Véronique Zanetti. On Moral Compromise 1. Introduction The central topic of Véronique Zanetti's article is

More information

Though several factors contributed to the eventual conclusion of the

Though several factors contributed to the eventual conclusion of the Aporia vol. 24 no. 1 2014 Nozick s Entitlement Theory of Justice: A Response to the Objection of Arbitrariness Though several factors contributed to the eventual conclusion of the Cold War, one of the

More information

The Values of Liberal Democracy: Themes from Joseph Raz s Political Philosophy

The Values of Liberal Democracy: Themes from Joseph Raz s Political Philosophy : Themes from Joseph Raz s Political Philosophy Conference Program Friday, April 15 th 14:00-15:00 Registration and Welcome 15:00-16:30 Keynote Address Joseph Raz (Columbia University, King s College London)

More information

John Rawls's Difference Principle and The Strains of Commitment: A Diagrammatic Exposition

John Rawls's Difference Principle and The Strains of Commitment: A Diagrammatic Exposition From the SelectedWorks of Greg Hill 2010 John Rawls's Difference Principle and The Strains of Commitment: A Diagrammatic Exposition Greg Hill Available at: https://works.bepress.com/greg_hill/3/ The Difference

More information

Definition: Property rights in oneself comparable to property rights in inanimate things

Definition: Property rights in oneself comparable to property rights in inanimate things Self-Ownership Type of Ethics:??? Date: mainly 1600s to present Associated With: John Locke, libertarianism, liberalism Definition: Property rights in oneself comparable to property rights in inanimate

More information

AN EGALITARIAN THEORY OF JUSTICE 1

AN EGALITARIAN THEORY OF JUSTICE 1 AN EGALITARIAN THEORY OF JUSTICE 1 John Rawls THE ROLE OF JUSTICE Justice is the first virtue of social institutions, as truth is of systems of thought. A theory however elegant and economical must be

More information

Samaritanism and Political Obligation: A Response to Christopher Wellman s Liberal Theory of Political Obligation *

Samaritanism and Political Obligation: A Response to Christopher Wellman s Liberal Theory of Political Obligation * DISCUSSION Samaritanism and Political Obligation: A Response to Christopher Wellman s Liberal Theory of Political Obligation * George Klosko In a recent article, Christopher Wellman formulates a theory

More information

Justice and the Egalitarian Ethos

Justice and the Egalitarian Ethos Justice and the Egalitarian Ethos Enrico Biale* * University of Genova, Italy: ebiale@hotmail.com Abstract. In this paper I would like to present Cohen s attack to one of the crucial features of Rawls

More information

Commentary on Idil Boran, The Problem of Exogeneity in Debates on Global Justice

Commentary on Idil Boran, The Problem of Exogeneity in Debates on Global Justice Commentary on Idil Boran, The Problem of Exogeneity in Debates on Global Justice Bryan Smyth, University of Memphis 2011 APA Central Division Meeting // Session V-I: Global Justice // 2. April 2011 I am

More information

Jus in Bello through the Lens of Individual Moral Responsibility: McMahan on Killing in War

Jus in Bello through the Lens of Individual Moral Responsibility: McMahan on Killing in War (2010) 1 Transnational Legal Theory 121 126 Jus in Bello through the Lens of Individual Moral Responsibility: McMahan on Killing in War David Lefkowitz * A review of Jeff McMahan, Killing in War (Oxford

More information

Book Reviews. Julian Culp, Global Justice and Development, Palgrave Macmillan, Basingstoke, UK, 2014, Pp. xi+215, ISBN:

Book Reviews. Julian Culp, Global Justice and Development, Palgrave Macmillan, Basingstoke, UK, 2014, Pp. xi+215, ISBN: Public Reason 6 (1-2): 83-89 2016 by Public Reason Julian Culp, Global Justice and Development, Palgrave Macmillan, Basingstoke, UK, 2014, Pp. xi+215, ISBN: 978-1-137-38992-3 In Global Justice and Development,

More information

WHY NOT BASE FREE SPEECH ON AUTONOMY OR DEMOCRACY?

WHY NOT BASE FREE SPEECH ON AUTONOMY OR DEMOCRACY? WHY NOT BASE FREE SPEECH ON AUTONOMY OR DEMOCRACY? T.M. Scanlon * M I. FRAMEWORK FOR DISCUSSING RIGHTS ORAL rights claims. A moral claim about a right involves several elements: first, a claim that certain

More information

Libertarianism and the Justice of a Basic Income. Peter Vallentyne, University of Missouri at Columbia

Libertarianism and the Justice of a Basic Income. Peter Vallentyne, University of Missouri at Columbia Libertarianism and the Justice of a Basic Income Peter Vallentyne, University of Missouri at Columbia Abstract Whether justice requires, or even permits, a basic income depends on two issues: (1) Does

More information

The Conflict between Notions of Fairness and the Pareto Principle

The Conflict between Notions of Fairness and the Pareto Principle NELLCO NELLCO Legal Scholarship Repository Harvard Law School John M. Olin Center for Law, Economics and Business Discussion Paper Series Harvard Law School 3-7-1999 The Conflict between Notions of Fairness

More information

Could Present Laws Legitimately Bind Future Generations? A Normative Analysis of the Jeffersonian Model

Could Present Laws Legitimately Bind Future Generations? A Normative Analysis of the Jeffersonian Model Could Present Laws Legitimately Bind Future Generations? A Normative Analysis of the Jeffersonian Model by Shai Agmon A bstract: Thomas Jefferson s famous proposal, whereby a state s constitution should

More information

Balancing Procedures and Outcomes Within Democratic Theory: Core Values and Judicial Review

Balancing Procedures and Outcomes Within Democratic Theory: Core Values and Judicial Review POLITICAL STUDIES: 2005 VOL 53, 423 441 Balancing Procedures and Outcomes Within Democratic Theory: Core Values and Judicial Review Corey Brettschneider Brown University Democratic theorists often distinguish

More information

We recommend you cite the published version. The publisher s URL is:

We recommend you cite the published version. The publisher s URL is: Cole, P. (2015) At the borders of political theory: Carens and the ethics of immigration. European Journal of Political Theory, 14 (4). pp. 501-510. ISSN 1474-8851 Available from: http://eprints.uwe.ac.uk/27940

More information

S.L. Hurley, Justice, Luck and Knowledge, (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2003), 341 pages. ISBN: (hbk.).

S.L. Hurley, Justice, Luck and Knowledge, (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2003), 341 pages. ISBN: (hbk.). S.L. Hurley, Justice, Luck and Knowledge, (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2003), 341 pages. ISBN: 0-674-01029-9 (hbk.). In this impressive, tightly argued, but not altogether successful book,

More information

Business Ethics Journal Review

Business Ethics Journal Review Business Ethics Journal Review SCHOLARLY COMMENTS ON ACADEMIC BUSINESS ETHICS businessethicsjournalreview.com Do I Think Corporations Should Be Able to Vote Now? Kenneth Silver 1 A COMMENTARY ON John Hasnas

More information

The Forgotten Principles of American Government by Daniel Bonevac

The Forgotten Principles of American Government by Daniel Bonevac The Forgotten Principles of American Government by Daniel Bonevac The United States is the only country founded, not on the basis of ethnic identity, territory, or monarchy, but on the basis of a philosophy

More information

Introduction to Equality and Justice: The Demands of Equality, Peter Vallentyne, ed., Routledge, The Demands of Equality: An Introduction

Introduction to Equality and Justice: The Demands of Equality, Peter Vallentyne, ed., Routledge, The Demands of Equality: An Introduction Introduction to Equality and Justice: The Demands of Equality, Peter Vallentyne, ed., Routledge, 2003. The Demands of Equality: An Introduction Peter Vallentyne This is the second volume of Equality and

More information

Contract law as fairness: a Rawlsian perspective on the position of SMEs in European contract law Klijnsma, J.G.

Contract law as fairness: a Rawlsian perspective on the position of SMEs in European contract law Klijnsma, J.G. UvA-DARE (Digital Academic Repository) Contract law as fairness: a Rawlsian perspective on the position of SMEs in European contract law Klijnsma, J.G. Link to publication Citation for published version

More information

Chantal Mouffe On the Political

Chantal Mouffe On the Political Chantal Mouffe On the Political Chantal Mouffe French political philosopher 1989-1995 Programme Director the College International de Philosophie in Paris Professorship at the Department of Politics and

More information

A Liberal Defence of Compulsory Voting : Some Reasons for Scepticism.

A Liberal Defence of Compulsory Voting : Some Reasons for Scepticism. 1 A Liberal Defence of Compulsory Voting : Some Reasons for Scepticism. Annabelle Lever Department of Philosophy London School of Economics and Political Science (annabelle@alever.net) Justine Lacroix

More information

In his theory of justice, Rawls argues that treating the members of a society as. free and equal achieving fair cooperation among persons thus

In his theory of justice, Rawls argues that treating the members of a society as. free and equal achieving fair cooperation among persons thus Feminism and Multiculturalism 1. Equality: Form and Substance In his theory of justice, Rawls argues that treating the members of a society as free and equal achieving fair cooperation among persons thus

More information

CONTEXTUALISM AND GLOBAL JUSTICE

CONTEXTUALISM AND GLOBAL JUSTICE CONTEXTUALISM AND GLOBAL JUSTICE 1. Introduction There are two sets of questions that have featured prominently in recent debates about distributive justice. One of these debates is that between universalism

More information

Assignment to make up for missed class on August 29, 2011 due to Irene

Assignment to make up for missed class on August 29, 2011 due to Irene SS141-3SA Macroeconomics Assignment to make up for missed class on August 29, 2011 due to Irene Read pages 442-445 (copies attached) of Mankiw's "The Political Philosophy of Redistributing Income". Which

More information

Criminal Justice Without Moral Responsibility: Addressing Problems with Consequentialism Dane Shade Hannum

Criminal Justice Without Moral Responsibility: Addressing Problems with Consequentialism Dane Shade Hannum 51 Criminal Justice Without Moral Responsibility: Addressing Problems with Consequentialism Dane Shade Hannum Abstract: This paper grants the hard determinist position that moral responsibility is not

More information

STIPULATED JURY INSTRUCTIONS State v. Manny Rayfield Curr County Circuit Court Case No State of New Maine

STIPULATED JURY INSTRUCTIONS State v. Manny Rayfield Curr County Circuit Court Case No State of New Maine STIPULATED JURY INSTRUCTIONS State v. Manny Rayfield Curr County Circuit Court Case No. 09-3031 State of New Maine Instruction Number Instruction Description 1. Preliminary Instructions 2. Functions of

More information

Civil Disobedience and the Duty to Obey the Law: A Critical Assessment of Lefkowitz's View

Civil Disobedience and the Duty to Obey the Law: A Critical Assessment of Lefkowitz's View Georgia State University ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University Philosophy Theses Department of Philosophy 8-7-2018 Civil Disobedience and the Duty to Obey the Law: A Critical Assessment of Lefkowitz's

More information

Teacher lecture (background material and lecture outline provided); class participation activity; and homework assignment.

Teacher lecture (background material and lecture outline provided); class participation activity; and homework assignment. Courts in the Community Colorado Judicial Branch Office of the State Court Administrator Updated December 2010 Lesson: Objective: Activities: Outcome: The Rule of Law Provide students with background information

More information

MUST THE REJECTION OF AN OFFER BE COMMUNICATED TO THE OFFEROR?

MUST THE REJECTION OF AN OFFER BE COMMUNICATED TO THE OFFEROR? Yale Law Journal Volume 12 Issue 7 Yale Law Journal Article 2 1903 MUST THE REJECTION OF AN OFFER BE COMMUNICATED TO THE OFFEROR? Follow this and additional works at: http://digitalcommons.law.yale.edu/ylj

More information

MAJORITARIAN DEMOCRACY

MAJORITARIAN DEMOCRACY MAJORITARIAN DEMOCRACY AND CULTURAL MINORITIES Bernard Boxill Introduction, Polycarp Ikuenobe ONE OF THE MAJOR CRITICISMS of majoritarian democracy is that it sometimes involves the totalitarianism of

More information

LEGAL STUDIES RESEARCH PAPER SERIES

LEGAL STUDIES RESEARCH PAPER SERIES Are Constitutions Legitimate? Andrei Marmor USC Legal Studies Research Paper No. 06-9 LEGAL STUDIES RESEARCH PAPER SERIES University of Southern California Law School Los Angeles, CA 90089-0071 This paper

More information

Where does Confucian Virtuous Leadership Stand? A Critique of Daniel Bell s Beyond Liberal Democracy

Where does Confucian Virtuous Leadership Stand? A Critique of Daniel Bell s Beyond Liberal Democracy Nanyang Technological University From the SelectedWorks of Chenyang Li 2009 Where does Confucian Virtuous Leadership Stand? A Critique of Daniel Bell s Beyond Liberal Democracy Chenyang Li, Nanyang Technological

More information

John Rawls, Socialist?

John Rawls, Socialist? John Rawls, Socialist? BY ED QUISH John Rawls is remembered as one of the twentieth century s preeminent liberal philosophers. But by the end of his life, he was sharply critical of capitalism. Review

More information

When Does Equality Matter? 1. T. M. Scanlon. The first theme of this paper is that we have many different reasons for being

When Does Equality Matter? 1. T. M. Scanlon. The first theme of this paper is that we have many different reasons for being When Does Equality Matter? 1 T. M. Scanlon The first theme of this paper is that we have many different reasons for being opposed to inequality. Only some of these reasons are egalitarian that is to say,

More information

Procedure for Pretrial Conferences in the Federal Courts

Procedure for Pretrial Conferences in the Federal Courts Wyoming Law Journal Volume 3 Number 4 Article 2 January 2018 Procedure for Pretrial Conferences in the Federal Courts Edson R. Sunderland Follow this and additional works at: http://repository.uwyo.edu/wlj

More information