Upholding the Principle of Distinction in Counter-Terrorist Operations: A Dialogue

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Upholding the Principle of Distinction in Counter-Terrorist Operations: A Dialogue"

Transcription

1 Journal of Military Ethics, Vol. 9, No. 1, 322, 2010 Upholding the Principle of Distinction in Counter-Terrorist Operations: A Dialogue AVERY PLAW Political Science Department, University of Massachusetts Dartmouth, USA ABSTRACT Asa Kasher and Amos Yadlin have recently argued for a revised principle of distinction under which states should prioritize the protection of their own soldiers over that of noncombatants in certain combat scenarios. The situations that they envision are those in which a state s army is forced to fight terrorists on terrain which is not under the state s effective control. Kasher dramatizes the argument that the soldiers safety should be prioritized by setting up a hypothetical conversation between the state and a soldier who asks Why should my state prefer an enemy citizen over me? Kasher challenges his readers to offer the soldier a morally compelling answer. This article responds to Kasher s challenge by presenting a dialogue in which a commander (representing the state) offers the soldier four arguments which together provide a convincing answer. The commander grounds his arguments in differences in the amount of choice exercised by soldiers and civilians, the divergent ways the operation can be expected to impact on them, the different obligations they each have to the state, and the likely consequences of emphasizing the safety of soldiers over civilians. The dialogue provides support for the double intention reading of the principle of distinction championed by Michael Walzer. KEY WORDS: Principle of distinction, counter-terrorism, targeted killing, civilian immunity, double intention Introduction In a series of recent articles Professor Asa Kasher of Tel Aviv University and Major General Amos Yadlin of the Israel Defense Forces (IDF) have advanced a forceful argument for revising the humanitarian principle of distinction that lies at the core of both the law of armed conflict and just war theory (Kasher & Yadlin 2005a, 2005b, 2005c, 2009, Kasher 2007). Specifically, they challenge the adequacy of the crude conventional distinction between combatant and noncombatant in the context of current asymmetrical conflicts between states and terrorist groups, and the general obligation that follows from it to respect civilians immunity from combat operations even at an increased risk to soldiers. They focus in particular on the Correspondence Address: Avery Plaw, Political Science Department, University of Massachusetts Dartmouth, 285 Old Westport Road, North Dartmouth, MA , USA. aplaw@umassd.edu Print/ Online/10/ # 2010 Taylor & Francis DOI: /

2 4 A. Plaw exemplary case of what they call targeted preventions of terror but which are also sometimes referred to as targeted killings or assassinations. In regard to such operations, they argue for a more nuanced set of distinctions that take account of (a) whether civilians are under the effective control of the state carrying out counter-terror operations, and (b) whether the civilians are involved (directly or indirectly) in terrorism themselves. One important implication of Kasher and Yadlin s revised principle of distinction would be that in certain circumstances states would be warranted in prioritizing the safety of their own combatants over that of certain civilians. Although this is not necessarily inconsistent with some historical accounts of the principle of distinction, it does clash with standard contemporary interpretations of the principle, including the seminal double intention account championed by Michael Walzer. This article offers a critique of Kasher and Yadlin s proposed revision of the principle of distinction and a defense of Walzer s interpretation. The issue at stake whether to embrace or reject Kasher and Yadlin s revised principle of distinction in regard to counter-terror operations is of more than just scholarly interest. Both Kasher and Yadlin are closely connected with the IDF and their opinions may well be thought to influence its practice. In addition to holding the Laura Schwarz-Kipp Chair in Professional Ethics and the Philosophy of Practice at Tel Aviv University, Kasher is also a longstanding and influential advisor to the Israeli military who drafted the IDF ethical code of conduct in the mid-1990s. Major General Yadlin is not only the current head of Israeli Military Intelligence, but is also a former Commander of the IDF College of National Defense. Moreover, while Kasher and Yadlin assert that their views are not necessarily those of the IDF College of National Defense, the IDF or the State of Israel (Kasher & Yadlin 2005a: 41), this disclaimer does not tell the whole story. The military ethics of fighting terror that Kasher and Yadlin articulate and defend were developed and first presented in 2003 when they were members of a team at the IDF College of National Defense, and their recommendations were subsequently approved in principle and employed as training guidelines (Kasher & Yadlin 2005a: 45; Harel 2009). Following Israel s recent Operation Cast Lead in the Gaza Strip, Haaretz military correspondent Amos Harel and others charged that the guidelines suggested in the [2005 Kasher and Yadlin] article are indeed the ones that govern the IDF s conduct in battle (Margalit & Walzer 2009: 21; Harel 2009). Indeed, according to Harel, Kasher himself confirmed in an interview that the army operated during the Gaza operation in accordance with the code of conduct for counter-terror operations that he and Yadlin had helped to develop (Harel 2009). According to United Nations reports more than 1300 Palestinians were killed in the Gaza operation, in contrast with 13 Israelis (the IDF reported 1,166 Palestinian dead, at least 709 of whom were Hamas terror operatives ) (United Nations Radio 2003; Lappin 2009). The casualties connected with Operation Cast Lead have occasioned enormous controversy both within Israel and around the world over the rules of engagement employed by the IDF. Of course, not all of those casualties, and particularly not all of the

3 Principle of Distinction in Counter-Terrorist Operations 5 civilian ones, can be attributed to the IDF s interpretation and application of the principle of distinction. Nonetheless, it is highly plausible that the kinds of argument advanced by Kasher and Yadlin have influenced Israeli combat practices, and in at least some cases those practices have affected the numbers of combat casualties and civilian casualties in particular. So, grappling with Kasher and Yadlin s arguments is not only of scholarly interest, but also of urgent moral importance. In his most recent article advocating his revised principle of distinction, Kasher suggests an evocative thought experiment. He asks his readers to imagine a conversation between a state and one of its soldiers who is being sent on a dangerous mission that demonstrates a preference to risk him rather than risking [harm to] an enemy citizen (Kasher 2007: 166). The soldier asks the state why it is justified in unnecessarily risking his life in this way. Kasher challenges his readers to offer an answer. This article takes up Kasher s challenge and suggests four moral arguments that could be offered to justify the contemporary reading of the principle of distinction and so for rejecting Kasher and Yadlin s revision of the principle. In the spirit of his thought experiment, it proposes the arguments in the context of a dialogue between a state (in the person of a commander) and a soldier who has posed Kasher s question of justification. The commander attempts to satisfy the soldier. While not all of the commander s arguments are successful, this article suggests, contra Kasher, that a sufficient moral case can be offered to uphold standard contemporary interpretations of the principle of distinction such as that offered by Walzer. Before turning to the dialogue, however, a brief overview of the principle of distinction is provided with the intention of clarifying how the contemporary readings of the principle differ from traditional accounts and where Kasher and Yadlin s revision challenges these contemporary interpretations. The Principle of Distinction The principle of distinction has long been a central component of just war theory and comprises the core of the contemporary humanitarian law of armed conflict. The principle imposes an obligation on parties to a conflict to distinguish between combatants, who are legitimate targets of attack, and civilians, who are not. In essence, it forbids intentional attacks on noncombatants. The principle does not, however, preclude all harm to noncombatants. It has always been understood that the conduct of warfare will almost inevitably produce some harm to civilians. The key traditional issues in determining whether harm to civilians violates the principle of distinction have been intentionality and proportionality.in essence, harm to noncombatants could be justifiable under the principle of distinction if it arises (a) as a concomitant of an otherwise legal military operation intended solely against a legitimate military target (i.e. the doctrine of double effect) 1, and (b) if the target s importance is proportional to the foreseeable likely harm to noncombatants (i.e. the principle of proportionality). In many traditional accounts of the principle of distinction,

4 6 A. Plaw operations had only to meet these two criteria to be justifiable. One implication of such accounts is that so long as an operation was planned with right intention and the expected collateral damage was proportionate to the value of its military objectives, commanders were under no further obligation to employ tactics intended to reduce the danger to civilians. However, traditional accounts of this sort have long been subject to criticism as too vague and too lax. In particular, the calculus of proportionality seems dangerously obscure. How can civilian lives be measured against the importance of military objectives? Moreover, the question of intention is in large part subjective commanders can almost always point to some military objective of operations, even if their intention is deliberately to punish a civilian population (that is, even if the military objectives are in fact of secondary importance). Similarly, the matter of anticipated civilian casualties seems open to manipulation. Finally, as noted above, once the criteria are met, the principle of distinction on the traditional reading provides no further protection to civilians in the actual conduct of military operations. For these reasons, many contemporary commentators have sought to strengthen the principle of distinction (e.g. Lee 2004). The most influential attempt was made by Michael Walzer in his 1977 classic Just and Unjust Wars. Walzer (1977: 156) argues that noncombatants have a right that due care be taken not to subject them to unnecessary risk. This right emanates from the same source as the principle of distinction itself: life is precious and should be safeguarded as far as possible, consistent with the conduct of hostilities hence the immunity of those not directly involved in the war effort (ibid.: 146). Such people are innocent in the sense that they are not direct participants in the war effort and, therefore, themselves pose no direct threat to combatants. They are also defenseless in the sense that they lack the right to defend themselves by engaging in combat (or at least they retain their immunity only so long as they refrain from doing so). The principle of distinction thus serves the purpose of immunizing the innocent and defenseless from deliberate and unnecessary destruction. It thus restrains the destructive effects of war on those most vulnerable and least involved. The right of due care is a logical extension of the principle of distinction flowing from that same purpose. Walzer (1977: 156) therefore proposes that the principle of distinction be read as involving a positive commitment to save civilian lives. In essence, the state must not only intend that a legitimate military objective be achieved, but also that the unintended harms attendant on it be minimized it must demonstrate a double intention (ibid.: 155). One important implication of this reading is that where there is a tactical trade-off between increased danger to combatants and civilians, the increased risk must be borne by the combatants: if saving civilian lives means risking soldier s [sic] lives, the risk must be accepted (ibid.: 156). Indeed, Walzer (1977: 155) insists that the risk to civilians must be reduced as far as possible. Evidently, Walzer s extension of the principle of distinction primarily addresses the conduct of operations rather than their proportionality or the intention behind them, but the need

5 Principle of Distinction in Counter-Terrorist Operations 7 to shift risk primarily onto soldiers may also have the beneficial side-effect of restraining the willingness of commanders to undertake operations that would incur such obligations (and hence may supplement the restraints of double effect and proportionality). In sharp contrast with standard contemporary interpretations of the principle of distinction like Walzer s, however, Kasher and Yadlin argue that, in certain circumstances (in particular, when it comes to fighting terrorism), the state should privilege the safety of its own combatants over that of foreign civilians who are not under its effective control. They base this argument on what they term the Principle of Self-Defense Duty. This principle asserts that it is the prime duty of a democratic state to effectively defend its citizens against any danger posed to their lives and well being (Kasher & Yadlin 2005b: 8). At the moment, they argue that the defense of citizens from terror is the prime duty of the Israeli state since the danger posed by terror is new and is of a special nature. Moreover, they stress, soldiers are citizens. Therefore, the Principle of Self-Defense Duty establishes the priority of soldiers lives and well-being over those of persons who are neither citizens nor under the state s effective control (and hence under its protection, such as visitors or permanent residents) (ibid.: 13, 16). As noted above, the exemplary case that Kasher and Yadlin treat is that of Israeli targeted killings. In these contexts they additionally argue that the simple distinction between combatants and civilians, with a priority on protecting the latter, is too crude to do justice to the complexities of such operations. They stress that terrorists frequently hide among civilians and present themselves as civilians. Insofar as this occurs outside Israel s area of effective control, it can do little to prevent terrorists from hiding among civilians. This rather reflects a failure of local political authorities. By consequence, Israel does not have to shoulder responsibility for the fact that persons who are involved in terror operate in the vicinity of persons who are not (ibid.: 18). Israel, therefore, need not accept increased risk to its soldiers. In view of these considerations, Kasher and Yadlin offer instead a sixcategory scale running from those whom the state has the greatest obligation to protect to those to whom it owes the least such obligation. According to them, the state has a moral duty to pursue the following outcomes in order: (d.1) Minimum injury to the lives of one s own citizens who are not combatants during combat; (d.2) Minimum injury to the lives of other persons (outside the state) who are not involved in terror, when they are under the effective control of the state; (d.3) Minimum injury to the lives of the combatants of the state in the course of their combat operations; (d.4) Minimum injury to the lives of other persons (outside the state) who are not involved in terror, when they are not under the effective control of the state; (d.5) Minimum injury to the lives of other persons (outside the state) who are indirectly involved in terror acts or activities; (d.6) Injury as required to the liberties or lives of other persons (outside the state) who are directly involved in terrorist acts or activities. (Kasher & Yadlin 2005a: 49, 2005b: 15; Kasher 2007: 165, emphasis added)

6 8 A. Plaw A striking feature of this moral scale is that the state s moral duty to protect its own combatants (duty 3) is ranked above its duty to protect some (although not all) civilians (duties 4 and 5), including some civilians who are not involved in terror (duty 4). Kasher and Yadlin s scale can indeed be seen as applying the low traditional principle of distinction protections for civilians to those outside the state s effective control while at the same time accepting the higher contemporary standards of civilian protection (like Walzer s) for noncombatants within the state or subject to its effective control. One consequence of Kasher and Yadlin s moral scale is that if Israeli officials are compelled, in order to prevent a terrorist attack, to carry out a targeted killing operation outside their area of effective control (such as in Gaza, Lebanon, or parts of the West Bank, presumably), and there are two plans before them, one of which imposes more danger on their own combatants and one of which imposes more danger on foreign civilians, then they should choose the latter. Kasher and Yadlin s primary justification for this is that the IDF is compelled to carry out the operation amidst a hostile population at a location not of its own choosing. It is the terrorist group that has chosen to operate in the midst of vulnerable civilians. In such circumstances, to ask Israeli soldiers to shoulder a highly elevated degree of risk in order to minimize the danger to foreign civilians (not under Israel s effective control) would violate the state s primary obligation to protect its own citizens (Kasher and Yadlin 2005a: 5153, 2005b: 18). Kasher and Yadlin thus argue that the principle of distinction should be revised to take account of such cases. The Thought Experiment In support of his case for revising the principle of distinction, Kasher offers the following thought experiment: Let us imagine a conversation between a state and one of its combatants. Being sent on a mission that involves risking his life, the combatant asks his state, actually [in the person of] his commander, why it is justified, on the moral grounds of the basic principles of democracy and military ethics, to send him on such a mission. (Kasher 2007: ) This is a credible and important challenge, and the remainder of this article takes it up in the form of a dialogue within Kasher s thought experiment. It offers a defense of Walzer s reading of the principle of distinction. For the purposes of the subsequent dialogue, Kasher s thought experiment is elaborated as follows. State officials have credible intelligence that a terrorist attack is imminent. They have determined that a targeted killing is the only plausible means of preventing what could be a devastating attack. However, the only place that they can be sure of pre-empting those preparing to carry out the attack is on the outskirts of city X located across their border, but in a territory which is not formally recognized as sovereign. 2 They can either (a) hit the location with an air strike, or (b) send troops in on the ground. Both plans have an equal chance of success, but plan a is believed to involve a significantly higher danger to local civilians, while plan b involves

7 Principle of Distinction in Counter-Terrorist Operations 9 a significantly higher risk to the state s soldiers. 3 State officials have opted for plan b in coherence with the standard contemporary understanding of the principle of distinction. The Commander has just briefed the soldiers being sent in first in the operation. Before proceeding, however, he invites anyone who has concerns to raise them. A soldier assigned to the operation raises his hand and politely suggests that the operation poses too high a risk to himself and his fellow soldiers. He suggests that it is morally wrong to send men on such a mission given the availability of an equally plausible alternative that would avoid the risk to them (i.e. plan a the air strike). Why, he asks the Commander, is it justified on the moral grounds of the basic principles of democracy and military ethics, to send me and my comrades on such a mission? The Dialogue Commander: Well, for one thing, the rules of war as currently understood require us to distinguish between combatants and civilians and to protect the latter over the former. You are a combatant. Most of the people living in the city are civilians. We are therefore required to design our mission so that the burden of risk is borne primarily by you and your comrades. Soldier: I understand that. But that answer only begs the question, sir. I am not asking you what the conventional rule is, but what the moral justification behind it is. Fighting against terrorists, who do not wear uniforms and hide among civilians, is clearly different from conventional wars, so it may be that different rules should apply. If we are forced to fight terrorists in the midst of civilian populations because they have chosen this field of battle, then I don t see why we must take responsibility for the fact that civilians may be exposed. Why are we morally bound to follow the conventional rule under such unconventional circumstances? Commander: But even in conventional wars, it s not as if the army always gets to pick and choose its fields of battle. Sometimes concentrations of enemy forces are in the vicinity of civilian centers, maybe even deliberately. The fact that they are does not warrant us in discounting civilians lives in relation to those of our soldiers. We are still required to distinguish between soldiers and civilians and to direct our military operations solely against the former. As you know, in those circumstances the principle of proportionality would permit us to undertake operations that pose some danger to civilians, provided that it is a necessary corollary to the pursuit of a legitimate military objective which is proportional to the danger of collateral damage, and that we take appropriate precautions to minimize the danger to civilians including assuming more risk to soldiers. So the circumstances you describe are not so unconventional, and it makes sense to adhere to the conventional laws. Soldier: Now we re back to quoting conventional laws of war. My point is that I m not sure why they apply. And that is not simply a matter of not choosing the

8 10 A. Plaw battlefield. It s a whole new constellation of factors including terrorists wholesale and systematic defiance of the rules of war. Why should I die, and leave my family unprotected, to uphold rules that they flout with impunity? Commander: Well, terrorism is hardly new. In the first century CE the sicarii murdered their enemies on the streets of Jerusalem. And even the deliberate use of military-scale force against civilians is hardly new think of Hitler s Blitz. The standards of just war and humanitarian law were formulated to distinguish and discourage such crimes. So I m still not convinced that there is a compelling reason to assume that the conventional rules of war do not apply to an armed struggle with enemies who employ terror. Because an enemy violates the rules of war, it does not justify us in doing so. Consider, if an enemy killed some POWs, would we be justified in killing an equal number? No. What we would be justified in doing would be bringing the war criminals to justice. The moral imperatives and corresponding laws are not, and never were intended to be, conditional on reciprocity. Each side is independently bound to uphold them. So I m not sure that either the question of the choice of battlefield or the question of breaches of law throws the authority of the core principles of just war or humanitarian law into question. Still, we don t need a specific trigger to justify examining the moral bases of the laws. They should always withstand scrutiny. So let s consider the challenge you raise. As I understand it, you want to know if the state can offer you compelling moral reasons for putting your life at higher risk in order to reduce the risk to civilians (not under its effective control) in the course of the targeted killing operation we ve planned. Soldier: I don t have my case exclusively in mind, but it can serve as a good case study. Commander: Alright. I will offer you four such reasons. They can be described as (i) choice, (ii) benefit, (iii) obligation, and (iv) effect. I hope that you ll find at least one of them convincing although I think you will be moved by more than one. Soldier: I m listening, sir. Commander: Let s begin with the first argument choice. You chose to serve, while those civilians in the targeted city did not choose to be in the line of fire. You therefore bear a moral responsibility for your choice that they do not share. As a result, it would be unjust to discount their risk in relation to yours. You must bear the consequences of your choice, they should not. So we should accept the danger of sending in soldiers on the ground and forego the airstrike option. Soldier: I did not choose. I am performing my mandatory service, sir. I have a wife and children. All things considered, I would prefer to be at home running my business. Of course, I m willing to fight for my country if

9 Principle of Distinction in Counter-Terrorist Operations 11 necessary. But before I undertake this hazardous mission, and put the welfare of my family at stake, I want to be convinced that the state has the right to risk me in preference to people who are not citizens and indeed who may be supporters of terrorism. Insofar as they support terrorist activities, are they not making a choice, and contributing to the creation of the situation that places them at risk? Commander: Well, I think we can agree that people who we know beyond reasonable doubt are systematically carrying out attacks on our civilians may be treated as combatants, and are subject to attack. Yet even in those cases we are committed to arresting them if we can, for practical, moral and legal reasons (after all, we haven t actually established their combat status through a judicial process). You re also right that some apparent civilians make a moral choice by directly and substantially supporting terrorists activities without fighting themselves or becoming actual targets. For example, they may supply terrorists with guns or bombs, knowing how these are going to be used. And if we are able to identify such persons with certainty and specificity, then we can examine the seriousness of their involvement and decide whether it is sufficiently direct and substantial to justify treating them as combatants. But I don t agree that because some such people exist that we have a moral warrant to disregard the immunity of all civilians in city X. After all, I m sure that you won t want to say that civilians surrender their immunity simply because they happen to be nearby to, or even because they may sympathize with, terrorist groups. And, of course, some among the local civilian population may be wholly opposed to terrorist groups. Surely we are not morally warranted in discounting their immunity and opting for dangerous airstrikes in order to maximize the safety of our own soldiers. Wouldn t that give them a serious moral grievance against us? Soldier: Perhaps, if they were uninvolved. But even if they merely cheer acts of terror, shouldn t they bear some of the consequences of what they encourage? Commander: Well, I think that we must assume that people in the city X are civilians unless we have specific and persuasive evidence to the contrary. Correspondingly, we must assume that they have made no choice that would justify stripping them of their immunity and unnecessarily endangering them unless we have evidence to the contrary and I don t think evidence of sympathy is sufficient after all, people shouldn t lose their immunity for what they feel or think. To be a combatant they must pose a direct threat. At the same time, your point that many soldiers are doing mandatory service and have also not chosen to expose themselves to danger is well-taken. It provides a good reason for asking for volunteers to undertake the most hazardous operations, at least wherever possible. But I wonder if the point is as decisive as it seems. After all, you and other conscripts have exercised a degree of choice: you have chosen to remain in this country knowing the wellpublicized requirements for national service. In that sense you could be said to have chosen to serve.

10 12 A. Plaw Soldier: So the choice that you think I have is to abandon my home, family, nation and state and immigrate to a foreign land to begin life anew. I don t consider that much of a choice. Commander: Well, it can certainly be seen as a pretty constrained choice. But it s worth remembering that that may also be the kind of choice facing civilians who find themselves living in areas in which terrorist groups operate. They may be able to move away (or, given the scope of terrorist activities and the difficulties of immigration they may not), but at best only at some of the same kinds of costs. They may not consider that much of a choice either. So I guess this argument from choice ends in a loose stalemate, neither providing a strong basis for preferring danger to soldiers or to civilians. It is safest to assume that neither has fully chosen their roles (although I still think that this argument would have real bite in relation to volunteer soldiers and armies). Soldier: I ll accept that provisionally. But this first result can t help you. You re making a positive claim for endangering soldiers rather than civilians, and that s what you re doing with this plan you propose. I m still waiting for a convincing moral rationale for doing this. Commander: Let s consider my second argument, which involves benefits. It goes like this: the operation is being undertaken to improve the security of your country, and so of your family, friends and co-citizens. It is you and they who stand to gain not the civilians in city X. It is therefore citizens like you who should bear the risk of the operation not the civilians in the target zone; so we should go in on the ground and not rely on airstrikes. Soldier: But people in the combat zone may well benefit from the elimination of the terrorists. Terrorists often tyrannize the local population. Certainly, they frequently expose them to dangerous retaliations. So the people in the target city will also gain if the terrorists are removed from their midst. Commander: At best, improvements in local security would be an unintended by-product of our operations. We don t carry out military operations to improve the security of non-citizens. Moreover, it is in many cases doubtful that locals would perceive the elimination of some terrorists as actually contributing to their security. Indeed, many locals will not perceive our targets as terrorists at all. They are often seen as heroes of resistance (think, for example, of Hezbollah in the eyes of many Lebanese, especially in the South). In a case like Gaza, Hamas is assuming the role of government and providing some public order and goods. Correspondingly, the elimination of their people will be perceived to diminish rather than improve security and in fact in some cases it may well do so. It is experienced then as a serious harm. Of course, you may argue that in spite of the subjective harm the condition of the local citizens is nonetheless objectively improved, but such an argument would be at best very difficult in the face of a strong subjective

11 perception of harm. And indeed, in at least some cases we clearly do an objective harm, especially when we end up injuring or killing civilians in the course of an operation. Now, if we are acting to protect ourselves, even at the risk of doing harm to civilians there, it stands to reason that we should bear the brunt of the risk in undertaking such operations. So once again we should go in on the ground and not rely on airstrikes. Soldier: Well, I m not convinced that what we re doing represents a moral harm. After all, we re trying to prevent acts of terrorism. Yes, these acts are generally directed against us, and so preventing them is mainly intended to protect us. But we didn t create the situation in which such acts are being carried out. It s the civilians over there who are supporting acts of terror, even if it s only in spirit, and therefore creating an environment conducive to such acts. So they are responsible for bringing about the whole circumstance or at least they are more responsible than me. So I ask again, why should my life be put at risk rather than theirs? Commander: For one thing, many of the civilians in question are not going to accept your view that they are responsible for creating conditions conducive to acts of terrorism. They think we are. I suspect in fact that it is rather a shared responsibility, but the question of historical responsibility for current circumstances is vast, hugely complicated, and unlikely to be resolved to everyone s satisfaction. Still, I think that you will agree with the much narrower point that the immediate purpose of operations is to improve our security, and the further claim that if that is our purpose then we are morally obligated to assume some of the risk to our combatants that goes with that. Still, you may understandably be dissatisfied with the level of risk that we are assuming, and may want to know why you are morally obligated to assume that degree of risk, while the risk to civilians in the operational zone is correspondingly diminished. So let me offer you a third line of argument that may help. This argument concerns obligation. Soldier: Alright. Principle of Distinction in Counter-Terrorist Operations 13 Commander: The argument goes like this: you benefit from the membership in the political community that we work to protect. You benefit from its laws, institutions, programs, and the civil society that these support. Indeed, as a citizen in a liberal-democratic political community, you are assured of a voice in shaping these institutions. But this favorable environment is not maintained without cost. And insofar as you are a beneficiary of it, and a participant in shaping it, the state has a moral basis to call upon you to share in the burdens of its maintenance and protection, including serving in the armed forces, and discharging the ethical obligations that come with that public service, including assuming appropriate risk. Notice, none of this is true of civilians who are not under the state s effective control. They have not generally shared in the benefits of citizenship, and are therefore under no moral obligation to undertake risk in its name. So the state is in a position to call upon you to

12 14 A. Plaw take risks on its behalf, but not on them. Accordingly, if there is a risk that must be allocated between parties, the state not only can, but should, ask you to assume the greater bulk of the risk. It therefore has a moral case for upholding the contemporary understanding of the principle of distinction and for sending soldiers like you in on the ground rather than relying on airstrikes. Soldier: But I m not arguing that I shouldn t have to assume any risk. As I ve said, I fully acknowledge the obligation to defend my country when necessary. I understand that assuming risk is part of being a soldier. My question is why I must assume risk that is not strictly necessary on behalf of foreign civilians. Commander: Well, I ve tried to show why the state not only has good moral reasons to ask you to defend it as a soldier, but also why it has grounds for asking you to share a greater degree of risk in executing its operations than non-citizen noncombatants (that is, more of what you term unnecessary risk ). But perhaps I can reinforce this argument by pointing out that assuming such risk is widely understood as part of what it means to be a soldier today. For example, the IDF s own ethical code, the Spirit of the IDF, provides, under its value of Purity of Arms, that IDF soldiers will not use their weapons and force to harm human beings who are not combatants... and will do all in their power to avoid causing harm to their lives, bodies, dignities and property (IDF 2009, emphasis added). Here, all in their power may certainly include assuming some additional risk (although property obviously warrants less risk than life). This commitment in turn reflects one of the IDF s three Basic Values, specifically Human Dignity Every human being is of value regardless or his or her origin, religion, nationality, gender, status or position. And this commitment is by no means unique. According to the current U.S. Army & Marine Corps Counterinsurgency Field Manual, the standard of moral and ethical conduct obligates soldiers and Marines to accept some risk to minimize harm to noncombatants (U.S. Army & Marine Corps 2007: 244). Specifically, it asserts that Proportionality and Discrimination require combatants not only to minimize the harm to noncombatants but also to make positive commitments to... assume additional risk to minimize potential harms (ibid.: 247, emphasis added). So, I m arguing that the state has the right to ask you to defend it as a soldier, and that part of the ethics of soldiering, of what it properly means to be a soldier today, is to be prepared to assume some additional risk where possible to reduce harms to noncombatants. Soldier: Well, that seems an unreasonably high ethical standard to impose on soldiers. I mean, what if the strategy that best protects civilians is effectively suicidal for soldiers? Are you seriously saying that soldiers would be ethically required to march into certain death? Commander: A fair question. And the answer is no. Here the US Manual again puts it well: At the same time, combatants are not required to take so

13 Principle of Distinction in Counter-Terrorist Operations 15 much risk that they fail in their mission or forfeit their lives (U.S. Army & Marine Corps 2007: 245). As this suggests, the ethical requirement for due care cannot require a choice of means that is effectively suicidal or impossible. In essence, I take this to mean that we are required to design missions, where possible, so that the majority of risk is borne by soldiers where this substantially reduces risk to civilians and does not render the operation unviable (for example, by making it suicidal or impossible). Obviously, these standards require a degree of judgment. But in our estimate of the current operation before us, the chances for success on the ground and with the airstrike are equally good, and while the risk to soldiers like yourself will be increased with the ground operation, it will not be unreasonably high, and the result will be to substantially reduce the danger to local civilians. Soldier: I fear that our estimates both of the risks involved here, and of what qualifies as reasonable, differ. Commander: Fair enough. But let s lay our differing estimates aside for just a moment. Do you agree that the state has a case in principle for asking you to assume some risk on behalf of civilians who are not under its effective control? Soldier: No, not yet. But I ll admit that there is something in the argument about an obligation to serve and an ethics of service. Commander: Good. Now let me offer you a final argument of a more consequential nature. This is what I ve called the argument from effect. It goes like this: if the state were to offload the risk of targeting operations onto the local civilians, it would produce two bad outcomes (and maybe a third and fourth): (a) it would sow hostility within the populations subjected to risk; and (b) it would muddy the distinction between terrorist acts; and legitimate counter-terrorist operations. A further related effect is that it might (c) make it more difficult to eventually move towards a peaceful resolution to the political situation although this is admittedly a more distant and controversial effect. Another thing that worries me is that (d) if the army could rationalize collateral harm to civilians simply by appeal to the necessity to maximize the security of its own soldiers, it might be tempted to undertake a great many more operations that pose a serious threat to civilians not under its effective control. It might then end up doing a lot more harm a result which is not only bad in itself, but would feed back into the first two harms ((a) and (b)). Anyway, I won t say more about the latter two concerns ((c) and (d)) because they are somewhat speculative. But let me explain what I mean by the first two ((a) and (b)). There seems little room for doubt that targeting operations that seem reckless in relation to civilian injuries will generate increased local hostility. This will especially be the case if, as is likely, the result of such recklessness is increased civilian casualties. Now, I want to suggest that growing hostility and distrust are bad in and of themselves. But

14 16 A. Plaw they are even worse if, as seems likely, they lead to increased support for, and cooperation with, the very terrorist groups we are trying to combat. In that case, our targeting operations may well prove counter-productive. Moreover, the increased support effect is likely to be exacerbated if the distinction between terrorist and counter-terrorist operations becomes more blurred. Although there is a great deal of controversy around what defines terrorist actions, they are most conventionally understood to involve the deliberate harming of civilians in pursuit of a political agenda. Counter-terror operations are understood as directed exclusively against terrorists with the intention of preventing attacks and thereby protecting civilians. However, if we privilege the safety of combatants over civilians not under our effective control, then we open ourselves to the moral charge that we are no different from the terrorists: we are deliberately putting civilians at risk, and in some cases harming them, in pursuit of a political agenda improving our own domestic security, not negotiating over our political policies, etc. I m not saying that we would become terrorists. I think that there would still be distinctions worth defending. I m just saying that the distinctions would be much finer and, in many cases, difficult to defend to the world and to ourselves it s much better if we can sincerely say that terrorist attacks are intended to kill as many civilians as possible whereas counter-terrorist operations are ultimately devoted to the protection of civilians. Soldier: That s all very well, but I notice that you yourself don t even maintain that there would be a complete collapse of the distinction between terrorism and counter-terrorist operations. You re just saying that from the perspective of publicity it would be more convenient to maintain the sharpest of distinctions. And you speculate on the impact these distinctions would have on the psychology of civilians in the zones of operation, and on the world community as a whole. But I don t find your speculations terribly persuasive. I think that the civilian populations in question are implacably hostile to us anyway, and that we are unlikely to find much support for our preventive operations among our allies or indeed the world community anyway. Most importantly, all of these considerations seem to me weak and doubtful when compared with the immediate prospect of losing my life and leaving my family bereft through absolutely no choice of my own. Commander: So, am I right then in thinking that you do see some of the negative consequences I see in privileging combatants over civilians but you don t think that they re as serious as I do, and certainly not as serious as the increased risk to you? But still, aren t these consequential concerns at least an additional contributor to the arguments from benefit and obligation? Soldier: The arguments from effect may add something but not much. And I d like to remind you that some of your attempted arguments, like the one from choice, really went nowhere at all. But more to the point: I think that you may be exaggerating the force even of your remaining arguments. In particular, there is something that you may have overlooked in your argument

15 Principle of Distinction in Counter-Terrorist Operations 17 from obligation. If the soldier, even the conscripted soldier, has an obligation to the state that nurtured him or her which includes risking life and limb, then doesn t the state also have an obligation to the soldier to continue to nurture him or her by, among other things, minimizing the risk to life and limb? This is not an obligation the state has to foreign citizens (not under its effective control), who are not obligated to fight its wars, pay its taxes, or comply with its laws. In short, the state owes something to its own citizens (including its citizen soldiers) that it does not owe to citizens or residents of other political jurisdictions. So when the state commits to protect citizens over soldiers, shouldn t it be only its own citizens it commits to protect rather than foreign citizens? Commander: That s a strong point, but I think it is a little too simplistic. Of course, states have a very basic obligation to protect their own citizens. (Obviously soldiers present a special case, because the state is permitted to put them at risk to increase the safety of civilian citizens.) But the state also has external obligations, to other states and the world community. These include the obligation to uphold two forms of international rules, what is sometimes termed jus gentium (the general law of nations or basic norms of the international system), and jus inter gentes (the law between the peoples or the particular international treaties, conventions and agreements to which the state is party). There is no doubt that the core of the principle of distinction the idea of civilian immunity is deeply embedded in both the general law of nations and the specific treaties to which virtually all states, including Israel, are party (including the Geneva Conventions). My point here is that the state s obligation to protect its own citizens, although extremely important, cannot function as a trump here, overwhelming all other considerations. It is rather one of a number of fundamental duties that states must carefully balance in the light of the kinds of moral and practical considerations we ve been discussing. Indeed, I think that the principles of military necessity and proportionality, and more recently the principle of double intention, are best thought of as ways of trying to balance internal obligations (such as the safety of the state s own citizens, especially noncombatants) with external obligations (to respect the immunity of foreign civilians). Thus, states may defend their citizens with military force, but only insofar as its actions are necessary and proportionate and designed with an eye to protecting foreign civilians (thus minimizing harm). Over time these principles have also become international norms. Moreover, I just don t think that it s intuitively believable that states are generally obligated to always prioritize the safety of their own citizens or citizen-soldiers. If, for example, states were obligated to always prioritize the safety of their own citizens then wouldn t they be obligated when at war to bomb an enemy s cities into oblivion if that might end the war faster (and therefore improve the security of their own citizens, including soldiers)? That is obviously unacceptable. Even critics of the principle of double intention don t generally question whether we are bound by the general principles of distinction and proportionality, even when they interfere with the optimal

16 18 A. Plaw protection of a state s own citizens. In other words, virtually everyone accepts that states have multiple and potentially conflicting moral obligations and must seek for a stable and effective balance. The upshot of these multiple obligations for present purposes is that in cases where the protection of the state s own citizens requires that foreign civilians (not under its effective control) are placed at risk, the state may take forceful action but is obligated to seek to reduce that risk to noncombatants even at the cost of significantly increasing the risk to its own soldiers. Do you agree? Soldier: Well, I m not entirely convinced. It does not sound to me like there is any logical necessity in the way the principle of distinction is framed today. It is simply a point of compromise. But it could as easily be agreed that in situations where civilians are necessarily at risk, we should equally balance the security of civilians and soldiers, or do so slightly in favor of soldiers. Commander: Well, you re perfectly right that there is something crude and artificial about the reduction of the entire world into two opposed categories of combatants and civilians, and that in at least some circumstances the general principle of always protecting civilians may raise difficult moral issues. States could agree, and indeed historically have agreed, to different definitions of the two categories and to different ways of properly balancing risk between them. But the contemporary rules we commonly recognize today, such as the standard of double intention, do nonetheless seem commonsensical and therefore carry a force beyond simply having marked a point of compromise. Consider, for example, that it is states that finally authorize military operations, and these states have an obvious and strong interest, as you note, in the preservation of their own soldiers. They don t have nearly as strong an immediate interest in the protection of foreign civilians (especially when not under their effective control). So if one wants to retain an equilibrium of interests, then states need to be pushed hard to carefully consider and protect the interests of foreign civilians. If we were to allow states to prioritize the protection of their own soldiers, then we would be courting the danger of allowing the competing interest of foreigners outside the state s own effective control to be swept away entirely. On the other hand, by setting high standards for the protection of foreign civilians, states gain the expectation that their own citizens will benefit from restraints on enemy exercises of military force (just as by agreeing to treat enemy POWs well they improve the prospects for their own soldiers when captured). Soldier: I m not entirely satisfied with the manner in which you ve just shifted from talking about ways to fulfill fundamental moral obligations, to commonsensical calculations about likely results. I still see a state s obligation to the security of its own citizens as primary, although perhaps in balance with other things including obligations to other states. And I m not satisfied with your pragmatic rationale for always favoring the protection of civilians. If you re going to focus on pragmatics, why not say that the agreement is limited to states (who may be expected to behave reciprocally), but not to

Conventional Deterrence: An Interview with John J. Mearsheimer

Conventional Deterrence: An Interview with John J. Mearsheimer Conventional Deterrence: An Interview with John J. Mearsheimer Conducted 15 July 2018 SSQ: Your book Conventional Deterrence was published in 1984. What is your definition of conventional deterrence? JJM:

More information

Jus in Bello through the Lens of Individual Moral Responsibility: McMahan on Killing in War

Jus in Bello through the Lens of Individual Moral Responsibility: McMahan on Killing in War (2010) 1 Transnational Legal Theory 121 126 Jus in Bello through the Lens of Individual Moral Responsibility: McMahan on Killing in War David Lefkowitz * A review of Jeff McMahan, Killing in War (Oxford

More information

THE IRAQ WAR OF 2003: A RESPONSE TO GABRIEL PALMER-FERNANDEZ

THE IRAQ WAR OF 2003: A RESPONSE TO GABRIEL PALMER-FERNANDEZ THE IRAQ WAR OF 2003: A RESPONSE TO GABRIEL PALMER-FERNANDEZ Judith Lichtenberg University of Maryland Was the United States justified in invading Iraq? We can find some guidance in seeking to answer this

More information

Oxford Handbooks Online

Oxford Handbooks Online Oxford Handbooks Online Proportionality and Necessity in Jus in Bello Jeff McMahan The Oxford Handbook of Ethics of War Edited by Seth Lazar and Helen Frowe Online Publication Date: Apr 2016 Subject: Philosophy,

More information

Democracy, and the Evolution of International. to Eyal Benvenisti and George Downs. Tom Ginsburg* ... National Courts, Domestic

Democracy, and the Evolution of International. to Eyal Benvenisti and George Downs. Tom Ginsburg* ... National Courts, Domestic The European Journal of International Law Vol. 20 no. 4 EJIL 2010; all rights reserved... National Courts, Domestic Democracy, and the Evolution of International Law: A Reply to Eyal Benvenisti and George

More information

Bridging Between Law, Life and Assassinations

Bridging Between Law, Life and Assassinations Bridging Between Law, Life and Assassinations By Marwan Dalal 1 Overtime without Penalty Kicks The Israeli Supreme Court s ruling delivered in December 2006 on Israel s policy of assassinations in the

More information

INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF RESEARCH AND ANALYSIS VOLUME 4 ISSUE 2 ISSN

INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF RESEARCH AND ANALYSIS VOLUME 4 ISSUE 2 ISSN THE LEGALITY OF ASSASSINATION OF OSAMA BIN LADEN UNDER INTERNATIONAL HUMANITARIAN LAW INTRODUCTION On 2 nd * ROMMYEL RAJ May 2011, the U.S Navy Seal Team 6 undertook a covert operation, Operation Geronimo

More information

Foreword to Killing by Remote Control (edited by Bradley Jay Strawser, Oxford University Press, 2012) Jeff McMahan

Foreword to Killing by Remote Control (edited by Bradley Jay Strawser, Oxford University Press, 2012) Jeff McMahan Foreword to Killing by Remote Control (edited by Bradley Jay Strawser, Oxford University Press, 2012) Jeff McMahan There is increasing enthusiasm in government circles for remotely controlled weapons.

More information

The human rights implications of targeted killings. Christof Heyns, UN Special Rapporteur on extrajudicial, summary or arbitrary executions

The human rights implications of targeted killings. Christof Heyns, UN Special Rapporteur on extrajudicial, summary or arbitrary executions The human rights implications of targeted killings Geneva 21 June 2012 Christof Heyns, UN Special Rapporteur on extrajudicial, summary or arbitrary executions I would like to look at the current issue

More information

Review. Michael Walzer s Arguing about War New Haven: Yale University Press, 2004

Review. Michael Walzer s Arguing about War New Haven: Yale University Press, 2004 Review Michael Walzer s Arguing about War New Haven: Yale University Press, 2004 reviewed by Ori Lev M ichael Walzer s new book assembles eleven articles published over the last 25 years, the latest in

More information

Obligations of International Humanitarian Law

Obligations of International Humanitarian Law Obligations of International Humanitarian Law Knut Doermann It is an understatement to say that armed conflicts fought in densely populated areas can and do cause tremendous human suffering. Civilians

More information

Arguments by First Opposition Teams

Arguments by First Opposition Teams Chapter 7 Arguments by First Opposition Teams Chapter Outline Role of Leader of Opposition Provide a Clear Statement of the Opposition Stance in the Debate Refutation of the Case of the Prime Minister

More information

AMBASSADOR THOMAS R. PICKERING DECEMBER 9, 2010 Subcommittee on the Constitution, Civil Rights, and Civil Liberties of the House Committee on the

AMBASSADOR THOMAS R. PICKERING DECEMBER 9, 2010 Subcommittee on the Constitution, Civil Rights, and Civil Liberties of the House Committee on the AMBASSADOR THOMAS R. PICKERING DECEMBER 9, 2010 Subcommittee on the Constitution, Civil Rights, and Civil Liberties of the House Committee on the Judiciary Hearing on Civil Liberties and National Security

More information

Chapter 8: The Use of Force

Chapter 8: The Use of Force Chapter 8: The Use of Force MULTIPLE CHOICE 1. According to the author, the phrase, war is the continuation of policy by other means, implies that war a. must have purpose c. is not much different from

More information

PROPORTIONALITY AND NECESSITY. Just war theory, the traditional theory of the morality of war, is not a consequentialist

PROPORTIONALITY AND NECESSITY. Just war theory, the traditional theory of the morality of war, is not a consequentialist PROPORTIONALITY AND NECESSITY 1. Consequence Conditions Just war theory, the traditional theory of the morality of war, is not a consequentialist theory, since it does not say a war or act in war is permissible

More information

Moral Dilemmas of Modern War

Moral Dilemmas of Modern War Moral Dilemmas of Modern War Torture, Assassination, and Blackmail in an Age of Asymmetric Conflict Asymmetric conflict is changing the way that we practice and think about war. Torture, rendition, assassination,

More information

Proportionality in Warfare Keith Pavlischek

Proportionality in Warfare Keith Pavlischek Proportionality in Warfare The last two times Israel went to war, international commentators criticized the country s use of force as disproportionate. During the Israel- Hezbollah war in 2006, officials

More information

Resolved: United Nations peacekeepers should have the power to engage in offensive operations.

Resolved: United Nations peacekeepers should have the power to engage in offensive operations. Resolved: United Nations peacekeepers should have the power to engage in offensive operations. Keith West After the tragedy of World War II and the ineffectiveness of the League of Nations, the world came

More information

The Protection of the Civilian Population and NATO Bombing on Yugoslavia: Comments on a Report to the Prosecutor of the ICTY

The Protection of the Civilian Population and NATO Bombing on Yugoslavia: Comments on a Report to the Prosecutor of the ICTY EJIL 2001... The Protection of the Civilian Population and NATO Bombing on Yugoslavia: Comments on a Report to the Prosecutor of the ICTY Michael Bothe* Abstract A report to the Prosecutor of the ICTY

More information

[on official letterhead of the Ministry of Foreign Affairs Jerusalem, Office of the Director General]

[on official letterhead of the Ministry of Foreign Affairs Jerusalem, Office of the Director General] [on official letterhead of the Ministry of Foreign Affairs Jerusalem, Office of the Director General] Disclaimer: The following is a non-binding translation of the original Hebrew document. It is provided

More information

Press Release learning these lessons and actually implementing them are the most implication of the conclusions of the Commission.

Press Release learning these lessons and actually implementing them are the most implication of the conclusions of the Commission. Press Release 1. On September 17 th 2006 The Government of Israel decided, under section 8A of The Government Act 2001, to appoint a governmental commission of examination To look into the preparation

More information

CCPA Analysis Of Bill C-36 An Act To Combat Terrorism

CCPA Analysis Of Bill C-36 An Act To Combat Terrorism research analysis solutions CCPA Analysis Of Bill C-36 An Act To Combat Terrorism INTRODUCTION The Canadian government has a responsibility to protect Canadians from actual and potential human rights abuses

More information

Politics between Philosophy and Democracy

Politics between Philosophy and Democracy Leopold Hess Politics between Philosophy and Democracy In the present paper I would like to make some comments on a classic essay of Michael Walzer Philosophy and Democracy. The main purpose of Walzer

More information

Public Schools and Sexual Orientation

Public Schools and Sexual Orientation Public Schools and Sexual Orientation A First Amendment framework for finding common ground The process for dialogue recommended in this guide has been endorsed by: American Association of School Administrators

More information

SECRET. 2. As I have previously advised, there are generally three possible bases for the use of force:

SECRET. 2. As I have previously advised, there are generally three possible bases for the use of force: SECRET PRIME MINISTER IRAQ: RESOLUTION 1441 1. You have asked me for advice on the legality of military action against Iraq without a further resolution of the Security- Council, This is, of course, a

More information

Resolution adopted by the General Assembly. [on the report of the Third Committee (A/65/456/Add.2 (Part II))]

Resolution adopted by the General Assembly. [on the report of the Third Committee (A/65/456/Add.2 (Part II))] United Nations A/RES/65/221 General Assembly Distr.: General 5 April 2011 Sixty-fifth session Agenda item 68 (b) Resolution adopted by the General Assembly [on the report of the Third Committee (A/65/456/Add.2

More information

Week # 2 Targeting Principles & Human Shields

Week # 2 Targeting Principles & Human Shields Week # 2 Targeting Principles & Human Shields MILITARY NECESSITY UNNECESSARY SUFFERING PROPORTIONALITY Military Advantage Collateral Damage DISTINCTION Civilian-Combatant Military Objective v. Civilian

More information

Israel, Military Prosecutor v. Kassem and Others

Israel, Military Prosecutor v. Kassem and Others Published on How does law protect in war? - Online casebook (https://casebook.icrc.org) Home > Israel, Military Prosecutor v. Kassem and Others Israel, Military Prosecutor v. Kassem and Others [Source:

More information

Bill of Rights. 1. Meet the Source (2:58) Interview with Whitman Ridgway (Professor, University of Maryland, College Park)

Bill of Rights. 1. Meet the Source (2:58) Interview with Whitman Ridgway (Professor, University of Maryland, College Park) Interview with Whitman Ridgway (Professor, University of Maryland, College Park) Bill of Rights 1. Meet the Source (2:58) Well, the Bill of Rights, in my opinion, is a very remarkable document because

More information

THE ANDREW MARR SHOW 24 TH APRIL 2016 THERESA MAY. AM: Good morning to you, Home Secretary. TM: Good morning, Andrew.

THE ANDREW MARR SHOW 24 TH APRIL 2016 THERESA MAY. AM: Good morning to you, Home Secretary. TM: Good morning, Andrew. 1 THE ANDREW MARR SHOW 24 TH APRIL 2016 THERESA MAY AM: Good morning to you, Home Secretary. TM: Good morning, Andrew. AM: If we stay in the EU will immigration go up or down? TM: Well, first of all nobody

More information

The armed group calling itself Islamic State (IS) has reportedly claimed responsibility. 2

The armed group calling itself Islamic State (IS) has reportedly claimed responsibility. 2 AI Index: ASA 21/ 8472/2018 Mr. Muhammad Syafii Chairperson of the Special Committee on the Revision of the Anti-Terrorism Law of the House of Representatives of the Republic of Indonesia House of People

More information

The first affirmation of the Center s Guideline ( on

The first affirmation of the Center s Guideline (  on October-December, 2007 Vol. 30, No. 4 Security and Defense Guideline #7 for Government and Citizenship by James W. Skillen The first affirmation of the Center s Guideline (www.cpjustice.org/guidelines)

More information

United States defense strategic guidance issued

United States defense strategic guidance issued The Morality of Intervention by Waging Irregular Warfare Col. Daniel C. Hodne, U.S. Army Col. Daniel C. Hodne, U.S. Army, serves in the U.S. Special Operations Command. He holds a B.S. from the U.S. Military

More information

The University of Edinburgh. From the SelectedWorks of Ray Barquero. Ray Barquero, Mr., University of Edinburgh. Fall October, 2012

The University of Edinburgh. From the SelectedWorks of Ray Barquero. Ray Barquero, Mr., University of Edinburgh. Fall October, 2012 The University of Edinburgh From the SelectedWorks of Ray Barquero Fall October, 2012 International Humanitarian Law Essay: A concise assessment of the interplay between the various sources of international

More information

Responsible Victims and (Partly) Justified Offenders

Responsible Victims and (Partly) Justified Offenders Responsible Victims and (Partly) Justified Offenders R. A. Duff VERA BERGELSON, VICTIMS RIGHTS AND VICTIMS WRONGS: COMPARATIVE LIABILITY IN CRIMINAL LAW (Stanford University Press 2009) If you negligently

More information

Attacks on Medical Units in International Humanitarian and Human Rights Law

Attacks on Medical Units in International Humanitarian and Human Rights Law Attacks on Medical Units in International Humanitarian and Human Rights Law September 2016 MSF-run hospital in Ma arat al-numan, Idleb Governorate, 15 February 2016 (Photo MSF - www.msf.org) The Syrian

More information

Interview with Philippe Kirsch, President of the International Criminal Court *

Interview with Philippe Kirsch, President of the International Criminal Court * INTERNATIONAL CRIMINAL TRIBUNALS Interview with Philippe Kirsch, President of the International Criminal Court * Judge Philippe Kirsch (Canada) is president of the International Criminal Court in The Hague

More information

Explosive weapons in populated areas - key questions and answers

Explosive weapons in populated areas - key questions and answers BACKGROUND PAPER JUNE 2018 Explosive weapons in populated areas - key questions and answers The International Network on Explosive Weapons (INEW) is an NGO partnership calling for immediate action to prevent

More information

The failure of logic in the US Israeli Iranian escalation

The failure of logic in the US Israeli Iranian escalation The failure of logic in the US Israeli Iranian escalation Alasdair Hynd 1 MnM Commentary No 15 In recent months there has been a notable escalation in the warnings emanating from Israel and the United

More information

An Analysis of Traditional Chinese Strategic Thought. This paper will examine traditional Chinese strategic thought, as represented in

An Analysis of Traditional Chinese Strategic Thought. This paper will examine traditional Chinese strategic thought, as represented in 1 17.407 Midterm An Analysis of Traditional Chinese Strategic Thought This paper will examine traditional Chinese strategic thought, as represented in the works of Sun Tzu, the Chinese military classics,

More information

RESOLVING THE ETHICAL CHALLENGES OF IRREGULAR WAR

RESOLVING THE ETHICAL CHALLENGES OF IRREGULAR WAR RESOLVING THE ETHICAL CHALLENGES OF IRREGULAR WAR A Dissertation Submitted to the Faculty of the Graduate School of Arts and Sciences Of Georgetown University in partial fulfillment of the requirements

More information

Comment to the Guidelines on Consent under Regulation 2016/679 by Article 29 Working Party

Comment to the Guidelines on Consent under Regulation 2016/679 by Article 29 Working Party Comment to the Guidelines on Consent under Regulation 2016/679 by Article 29 Working Party Finnish Social Science Data Archive (FSD) welcomes the high priority Article 29 Working Party has placed on updating

More information

Ethics Handout 18 Rawls, Classical Utilitarianism and Nagel, Equality

Ethics Handout 18 Rawls, Classical Utilitarianism and Nagel, Equality 24.231 Ethics Handout 18 Rawls, Classical Utilitarianism and Nagel, Equality The Utilitarian Principle of Distribution: Society is rightly ordered, and therefore just, when its major institutions are arranged

More information

A Necessary Discussion About International Law

A Necessary Discussion About International Law A Necessary Discussion About International Law K E N W A T K I N Review of Jens David Ohlin & Larry May, Necessity in International Law (Oxford University Press, 2016) The post-9/11 security environment

More information

Conflating Terrorism and Insurgency

Conflating Terrorism and Insurgency Page 1 of 6 MENU FOREIGN POLICY ESSAY Conflating Terrorism and Insurgency By John Mueller, Mark Stewart Sunday, February 28, 2016, 10:05 AM Editor's Note: What if most terrorism isn t really terrorism?

More information

Chapter 37. Just War

Chapter 37. Just War Chapter 37 Just War jeff mcmahan There are three broadly defined positions on the morality of war. The first is pacifism, which holds that it is always wrong for a state to resort to war and always wrong

More information

Exploring Civilian Protection: A Seminar Series

Exploring Civilian Protection: A Seminar Series Exploring Civilian Protection: A Seminar Series (Seminar #1: Understanding Protection: Concepts and Practices) Tuesday, September 14, 2010, 9:00 am 12:00 pm The Brookings Institution, Saul/Zilkha Rooms,

More information

PHI 1700: Global Ethics

PHI 1700: Global Ethics PHI 1700: Global Ethics Session 17 April 5 th, 2017 O Neill (continue,) & Thomson, Killing, Letting Die, and the Trolley Problem Recap from last class: One of three formulas of the Categorical Imperative,

More information

Challenges Facing the Asian-African States in the Contemporary. Era: An Asian-African Perspective

Challenges Facing the Asian-African States in the Contemporary. Era: An Asian-African Perspective Challenges Facing the Asian-African States in the Contemporary Era: An Asian-African Perspective Prof. Dr. Rahmat Mohamad At the outset I thank the organizers of this event for inviting me to deliver this

More information

INTERNATIONAL CONVENTION ON THE SAFETY AND INDEPENDENCE OF JOURNALISTS AND OTHER MEDIA PROFESSIONALS PREAMBLE

INTERNATIONAL CONVENTION ON THE SAFETY AND INDEPENDENCE OF JOURNALISTS AND OTHER MEDIA PROFESSIONALS PREAMBLE INTERNATIONAL CONVENTION ON THE SAFETY AND INDEPENDENCE OF JOURNALISTS AND OTHER MEDIA PROFESSIONALS The States Parties to the present Convention, PREAMBLE 1. Reaffirming the commitment undertaken in Article

More information

Women, armed conflict and international law

Women, armed conflict and international law Women, armed conflict and international law HELEN DURHAM* IHL takes a particular male perspective on armed conflict, as a norm against which to measure equality. In a world where women are not equals of

More information

29. Security Council action regarding the terrorist attacks in Buenos Aires and London

29. Security Council action regarding the terrorist attacks in Buenos Aires and London Repertoire of the Practice of the Security Council 29. Security Council action regarding the terrorist attacks in Buenos Aires and London Initial proceedings Decision of 29 July 1994: statement by the

More information

Nuremberg Tribunal. London Charter. Article 6

Nuremberg Tribunal. London Charter. Article 6 Nuremberg Tribunal London Charter Article 6 The following acts, or any of them, are crimes coming within the jurisdiction of the Tribunal for which there shall be individual responsibility: CRIMES AGAINST

More information

THE ICRC'S CLARIFICATION PROCESS ON THE NOTION OF DIRECT PARTICIPATION IN HOSTILITIES UNDER INTERNATIONAL HUMANITARIAN LAW NILS MELZER

THE ICRC'S CLARIFICATION PROCESS ON THE NOTION OF DIRECT PARTICIPATION IN HOSTILITIES UNDER INTERNATIONAL HUMANITARIAN LAW NILS MELZER THE ICRC'S CLARIFICATION PROCESS ON THE NOTION OF DIRECT PARTICIPATION IN HOSTILITIES UNDER INTERNATIONAL HUMANITARIAN LAW NILS MELZER Dr. Nils Melzer is legal adviser for the International Committee of

More information

THE PRESIDENT OF THE UNITED STATES

THE PRESIDENT OF THE UNITED STATES 1 106TH CONGRESS 1st Session " SENATE! TREATY DOC. 106 1 THE HAGUE CONVENTION AND THE HAGUE PROTOCOL MESSAGE FROM THE PRESIDENT OF THE UNITED STATES TRANSMITTING THE HAGUE CONVENTION FOR THE PROTECTION

More information

Negotiating with Terrorists an Option Not to Be Forgone

Negotiating with Terrorists an Option Not to Be Forgone KOMMENTARE /COMMENTS Negotiating with Terrorists an Option Not to Be Forgone MICHAEL DAUDERSTÄDT I t is very tempting, in the wake of the many shocking terrorist attacks of recent times such as those in

More information

Press Conference March Dr Sima Samar, Chairperson of Afghan Independent Human Rights Commission (AIHRC)

Press Conference March Dr Sima Samar, Chairperson of Afghan Independent Human Rights Commission (AIHRC) Press Conference PRESS CONFERENCE (near verbatim transcript) Ivan Simonovic, UN Assistant Secretary-General for Human Rights Dr Sima Samar, Chairperson of Afghan Independent Human Rights Commission (AIHRC)

More information

AN ESSAY AND COMMENT ON OREN GROSS, THE NEW WAY OF WAR: IS THERE A DUTY TO USE DRONES? Winston P. Nagan * Megan E. Weeren **

AN ESSAY AND COMMENT ON OREN GROSS, THE NEW WAY OF WAR: IS THERE A DUTY TO USE DRONES? Winston P. Nagan * Megan E. Weeren ** AN ESSAY AND COMMENT ON OREN GROSS, THE NEW WAY OF WAR: IS THERE A DUTY TO USE DRONES? Winston P. Nagan * Megan E. Weeren ** Professor Oren Gross has written a remarkably strong article in defense of the

More information

Objectives To explore the meanings of conflict and war. To make deductions and practise reasoning skills.

Objectives To explore the meanings of conflict and war. To make deductions and practise reasoning skills. H Oxfam Education www.oxfam.org.uk/education Making Sense of World Conflicts Lesson plan 5: Is it war? Age group: 14 17 Objectives To explore the meanings of conflict and war. To make deductions and practise

More information

ANNEX I: APPLICABLE INTERNATIONAL LEGAL FRAMEWORK

ANNEX I: APPLICABLE INTERNATIONAL LEGAL FRAMEWORK ANNEX I: APPLICABLE INTERNATIONAL LEGAL FRAMEWORK The legal framework applicable to the targeting of schools and universities, and the use of schools and universities in support of the military effort,

More information

1/13/ What is Terrorism? The Globalization of Terrorism. What is Terrorism? Geography of Terrorism. Global Patterns of Terrorism

1/13/ What is Terrorism? The Globalization of Terrorism. What is Terrorism? Geography of Terrorism. Global Patterns of Terrorism What is Terrorism? The Globalization of Terrorism Global Issues 621 Chapter 23 Page 364 1/13/2009 Terrorism 2 Unfortunately, the term terrorism is one that has become a part of our everyday vocabulary

More information

Prosecutor Trial Preparation: Preparing the Victim of Human Trafficking to Testify

Prosecutor Trial Preparation: Preparing the Victim of Human Trafficking to Testify This guide is a gift of the United States Government PRACTICE GUIDE Prosecutor Trial Preparation: Preparing the Victim of Human Trafficking to Testify AT A GLANCE Intended Audience: Prosecutors working

More information

10/15/2013. The Globalization of Terrorism. What is Terrorism? What is Terrorism?

10/15/2013. The Globalization of Terrorism. What is Terrorism? What is Terrorism? The Globalization of Terrorism Global Issues 621 Chapter 23 Page 364 What is Terrorism? 10/15/2013 Terrorism 2 What is Terrorism? Unfortunately, the term terrorism is one that has become a part of our

More information

Counter-terrorism Laws, Offences and Other Provisions

Counter-terrorism Laws, Offences and Other Provisions Counter-terrorism Laws, Offences and Other Provisions CHAPTER CONTENTS Introduction 2 What is a Terrorist Act? 2 Preparatory and Group-based Terrorism Offences 2 Coercive Powers to Investigate and Prevent

More information

Proportionality and Necessity in Jus in Bello

Proportionality and Necessity in Jus in Bello Proportionality and Necessity in Jus in Bello 1 Introduction In the traditional theory of the just war, the requirements of proportionality and necessity appear twice, once among the principles governing

More information

Opening Statement Secretary of State John Kerry Senate Committee on Foreign Relations December 9, 2014

Opening Statement Secretary of State John Kerry Senate Committee on Foreign Relations December 9, 2014 Opening Statement Secretary of State John Kerry Senate Committee on Foreign Relations December 9, 2014 Mr. Chairman, Ranking Member Corker Senators good afternoon, thank you for having me back to the Foreign

More information

Committee Name Legal Political

Committee Name Legal Political Hilton Hilton 2017 2017 Committee Name Committee Overview Government Targeted Killings Drug Trafficking and Funding of Terrorism Legal Frameworks of Combatting Sexual Violence in Conflict Zones Role of

More information

Questions. Hobbes. Hobbes s view of human nature. Question. What justification is there for a state? Does the state have supreme authority?

Questions. Hobbes. Hobbes s view of human nature. Question. What justification is there for a state? Does the state have supreme authority? Questions Hobbes What justification is there for a state? Does the state have supreme authority? What limits are there upon the state? 1 2 Question Hobbes s view of human nature When you accept a job,

More information

Hobbes. Questions. What justification is there for a state? Does the state have supreme authority? What limits are there upon the state?

Hobbes. Questions. What justification is there for a state? Does the state have supreme authority? What limits are there upon the state? Hobbes 1 Questions What justification is there for a state? Does the state have supreme authority? What limits are there upon the state? 2 Question When you accept a job, you sign a contract agreeing to

More information

Palestinian Refugees. ~ Can you imagine what their life? ~ Moe Matsuyama, No.10A F June 10, 2011

Palestinian Refugees. ~ Can you imagine what their life? ~ Moe Matsuyama, No.10A F June 10, 2011 Palestinian Refugees ~ Can you imagine what their life? ~ Moe Matsuyama, No.10A3145003F June 10, 2011 Why did I choose this Topic? In this spring vacation, I went to Israel & Palestine. There, I visited

More information

The 1954 Hague Convention for the Protection of Cultural Property in the Event of Armed Conflict and the notion of military necessity by Jan Hladík

The 1954 Hague Convention for the Protection of Cultural Property in the Event of Armed Conflict and the notion of military necessity by Jan Hladík The 1954 Hague Convention for the Protection of Cultural Property in the Event of Armed Conflict and the notion of military necessity by Jan Hladík The review of the 1954 Convention and the adoption of

More information

GUIDELINES FOR HUMANITARIAN ORGANISATIONS ON INTERACTING WITH MILITARY AND OTHER SECURITY ACTORS IN IRAQ A) INTRODUCTION: B) DEFINITION OF KEY TERMS:

GUIDELINES FOR HUMANITARIAN ORGANISATIONS ON INTERACTING WITH MILITARY AND OTHER SECURITY ACTORS IN IRAQ A) INTRODUCTION: B) DEFINITION OF KEY TERMS: GUIDELINES FOR HUMANITARIAN ORGANISATIONS ON INTERACTING WITH MILITARY AND OTHER SECURITY ACTORS IN IRAQ 20 OCTOBER 2004 A) INTRODUCTION: This set of guidelines was developed by the Office of the Deputy

More information

CHAPTER 4, On Liberty. Does Mill Qualify the Liberty Principle to Death? Dick Arneson For PHILOSOPHY 166 FALL, 2006

CHAPTER 4, On Liberty. Does Mill Qualify the Liberty Principle to Death? Dick Arneson For PHILOSOPHY 166 FALL, 2006 1 CHAPTER 4, On Liberty. Does Mill Qualify the Liberty Principle to Death? Dick Arneson For PHILOSOPHY 166 FALL, 2006 In chapter 1, Mill proposes "one very simple principle, as entitled to govern absolutely

More information

Art. 61. Troops that give no quarter have no right to kill enemies already disabled on the ground, or prisoners captured by other troops.

Art. 61. Troops that give no quarter have no right to kill enemies already disabled on the ground, or prisoners captured by other troops. Criminalizing War (1) Discovering crimes in war (2) Early attempts to regulate the use of force in war (3) International Military Tribunal (Nuremberg trial) (4) International Military Tribunal for the

More information

Sixty years of the Geneva Conventions: learning from the past to better face the future

Sixty years of the Geneva Conventions: learning from the past to better face the future Published on How does law protect in war? - Online casebook (https://casebook.icrc.org) Home > Sixtieth Anniversary of the Geneva Conventions [Source: ICRC, Sixty years of the Geneva Conventions: learning

More information

In search of moral leadership

In search of moral leadership By Jeton Mehmeti World Assembly of Youth 10 th Melaka International Youth dialogue Youth Leadership Power and its Influence to the Society 24-26 June 2010 Melaka, Malaysia Morality, ethics and leadership

More information

Srictly embargoed until 24 April h00 CET

Srictly embargoed until 24 April h00 CET Prevention, Promotion and Protection: Our Shared Responsibility Address by Mr. Kofi Annan Lund University, Sweden 24 April 2012 --------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------

More information

Human Rights: From Practice to Policy

Human Rights: From Practice to Policy Human Rights: From Practice to Policy Proceedings of a Research Workshop Gerald R. Ford School of Public Policy University of Michigan October 2010 Edited by Carrie Booth Walling and Susan Waltz 2011 by

More information

HOSTILITIES UNDER INTERNATIONAL LAW

HOSTILITIES UNDER INTERNATIONAL LAW An Open Access Journal from The Law Brigade (Publishing) Group 447 HOSTILITIES UNDER INTERNATIONAL LAW Written by Dr. Yeshwant Naik Post-Doctoral Research Fellow, Muenster University, Germany The interrelation

More information

Measures undertaken by the Government of Romania in order to disseminate and implement the international humanitarian law

Measures undertaken by the Government of Romania in order to disseminate and implement the international humanitarian law Measures undertaken by the Government of Romania in order to disseminate and implement the international humanitarian law Romania is party to most of the international humanitarian law treaties, including

More information

An Introduction to Stakeholder Dialogue

An Introduction to Stakeholder Dialogue An Introduction to Stakeholder Dialogue The reciprocity of moral rights, stakeholder theory and dialogue Ernst von Kimakowitz The Three Stepped Approach of Humanistic Management Stakeholder dialogue in

More information

Getting a Handle on the Super PAC Problem. Bob Bauer. Stanford Law Symposium. February 5, 2016

Getting a Handle on the Super PAC Problem. Bob Bauer. Stanford Law Symposium. February 5, 2016 Getting a Handle on the Super PAC Problem Bob Bauer Stanford Law Symposium February 5, 2016 The Super PACs are the bêtes noires of campaign finance reform, except for those who are quite keen on them,

More information

TARGETED KILLING AND THE LAW: Who is a Legitimate Target and When is the Target Legitimate? By Amos N. Guiora

TARGETED KILLING AND THE LAW: Who is a Legitimate Target and When is the Target Legitimate? By Amos N. Guiora November 2013 TARGETED KILLING AND THE LAW: Who is a Legitimate Target and When is the Target Legitimate? By Amos N. Guiora Amos Guiora is Professor of Law and Co-Director of the Center for Global Justice

More information

Human Rights Council. Protection of human rights and fundamental freedoms while countering terrorism

Human Rights Council. Protection of human rights and fundamental freedoms while countering terrorism Human Rights Council Resolution 7/7. Protection of human rights and fundamental freedoms while countering terrorism The Human Rights Council, Recalling its decision 2/112 and its resolution 6/28, and also

More information

PIPA-Knowledge Networks Poll: Americans on Iraq & the UN Inspections II. Questionnaire

PIPA-Knowledge Networks Poll: Americans on Iraq & the UN Inspections II. Questionnaire PIPA-Knowledge Networks Poll: Americans on Iraq & the UN Inspections II Questionnaire Dates of Survey: Feb 12-18, 2003 Margin of Error: +/- 2.6% Sample Size: 3,163 respondents Half sample: +/- 3.7% [The

More information

PEOPLE ON WAR PERSPECTIVES FROM 16 COUNTRIES

PEOPLE ON WAR PERSPECTIVES FROM 16 COUNTRIES PEOPLE ON WAR PERSPECTIVES FROM 16 COUNTRIES Alongside the global People on War initiative undertaken by the International Committee of the Red Cross (ICRC) in 16 countries, several smaller-scale People

More information

Issue: Measures to ensure continued protection of civilians in war zones

Issue: Measures to ensure continued protection of civilians in war zones Forum: Human Rights Council II Issue: Measures to ensure continued protection of civilians in war zones Student Officer: Adam McMahon Position: Deputy Chair 1 Introduction The matter of protecting civilians

More information

All is Fair in War? Just War Theory and American Applications. Chris Sabolcik GSW Area II

All is Fair in War? Just War Theory and American Applications. Chris Sabolcik GSW Area II All is Fair in War? Just War Theory and American Applications Chris Sabolcik GSW Area II Quickchat with Colleagues Brainstorm a military conflict that you consider to be justified, if one exists. Also,

More information

PROBLEMS OF CREDIBLE STRATEGIC CONDITIONALITY IN DETERRENCE by Roger B. Myerson July 26, 2018

PROBLEMS OF CREDIBLE STRATEGIC CONDITIONALITY IN DETERRENCE by Roger B. Myerson July 26, 2018 PROBLEMS OF CREDIBLE STRATEGIC CONDITIONALITY IN DETERRENCE by Roger B. Myerson July 26, 2018 We can influence others' behavior by threatening to punish them if they behave badly and by promising to reward

More information

Opinions adopted by the Working Group on Arbitrary Detention at its seventy-ninth session, August 2017

Opinions adopted by the Working Group on Arbitrary Detention at its seventy-ninth session, August 2017 Advance Edited Version Distr.: General 2 October 2017 Original: English Human Rights Council Working Group on Arbitrary Detention Opinions adopted by the Working Group on Arbitrary Detention at its seventy-ninth

More information

GENERAL CLOSING INSTRUCTIONS. Members of the jury, it is now time for me to tell you the law that applies to

GENERAL CLOSING INSTRUCTIONS. Members of the jury, it is now time for me to tell you the law that applies to GENERAL CLOSING INSTRUCTIONS Members of the jury, it is now time for me to tell you the law that applies to this case. As I mentioned at the beginning of the trial, you must follow the law as I state it

More information

Policy regarding China and Tibet 1. Jawaharlal Nehru. November, 18, 1950

Policy regarding China and Tibet 1. Jawaharlal Nehru. November, 18, 1950 Policy regarding China and Tibet 1 Jawaharlal Nehru November, 18, 1950 1. The Chinese Government having replied to our last note, 2 we have to consider what further steps we should take in this matter.

More information

Special meeting in observance of the. International Day of Solidarity with the Palestinian People

Special meeting in observance of the. International Day of Solidarity with the Palestinian People International Progress Organization Organisation Internationale pour le Progrès Special meeting in observance of the International Day of Solidarity with the Palestinian People held by the Committee on

More information

Current Developments in Middle Eastern Politics and Religion

Current Developments in Middle Eastern Politics and Religion Current Developments in Middle Eastern Politics and Religion A Conversation with Shai Feldman BOISI CENTER FOR RELIGION AND AMERICAN PUBLIC LIFE BOSTON COLLEGE, CHESTNUT HILL, MASSACHUSETTS APRIL 18, 2007

More information

THE ANDREW MARR SHOW INTERVIEW: MICHAEL FALLON, MP DEFENCE SECRETARY OCTOBER 26 th 2014

THE ANDREW MARR SHOW INTERVIEW: MICHAEL FALLON, MP DEFENCE SECRETARY OCTOBER 26 th 2014 PLEASE NOTE THE ANDREW MARR SHOW MUST BE CREDITED IF ANY PART OF THIS TRANSCRIPT IS USED THE ANDREW MARR SHOW INTERVIEW: MICHAEL FALLON, MP DEFENCE SECRETARY OCTOBER 26 th 2014 Now, as we ve been hearing

More information

Attorney General Sessions Delivers Remarks to the National Sheriffs Association Annual Conference. New Orleans, LA ~ Monday, June 18, 2018

Attorney General Sessions Delivers Remarks to the National Sheriffs Association Annual Conference. New Orleans, LA ~ Monday, June 18, 2018 JUSTICE NEWS Attorney General Sessions Delivers Remarks to the National Sheriffs Association Annual Conference New Orleans, LA ~ Monday, June 18, 2018 Remarks as prepared for delivery Thank you, Jonathan,

More information

Do we have a strong case for open borders?

Do we have a strong case for open borders? Do we have a strong case for open borders? Joseph Carens [1987] challenges the popular view that admission of immigrants by states is only a matter of generosity and not of obligation. He claims that the

More information

Briefing on Sixth Committee of the United Nations General Assembly 1. History of the Sixth Committee

Briefing on Sixth Committee of the United Nations General Assembly 1. History of the Sixth Committee Briefing on Sixth Committee of the United Nations General Assembly 1 History of the Sixth Committee The Sixth Committee of the United Nations General Assembly is primarily concerned with the formulation

More information

DEVELOPING A COLLECTION PLAN FOR GATHERING VIDEO EVIDENCE

DEVELOPING A COLLECTION PLAN FOR GATHERING VIDEO EVIDENCE DEVELOPING A COLLECTION PLAN FOR GATHERING VIDEO EVIDENCE Filming for human rights can be dangerous. It can put you, the people you are filming and the communities you are filming in at risk. Carefully

More information

The Permissibility of Aiding and Abetting Unjust Wars

The Permissibility of Aiding and Abetting Unjust Wars The Permissibility of Aiding and Abetting Unjust Wars Saba Bazargan Department of Philosophy UC San Diego Abstract Common sense suggests that if a war is unjust, then there is a strong moral reason not

More information