Public Sector Economics

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Public Sector Economics"

Transcription

1 Public Sector Economics Munich, 4 April 08 Preference Divergence between the Electorate and their Elected Representatives Didier Laussel and Ngo Van Long

2 Preference Divergence Between the Electorate and Their Elected Representatives Didier Laussel y Aix-Marseille University Ngo Van Long z McGill University 3 February 08 Correspondence: y Aix-Marseille University, CNRS, EHESS, Centrale Marseille, AMSE. didier.laussel@outlook.fr z Department of Economics, McGill University. ngo.long@mcgill.ca

3 Preference Divergence Between the Electorate and Their Elected Representatives Abstract: The citizen candidates models of democracy assume that politicians have their own preferences that are not fully revealed at the time of elections. We study the optimal delegation problem which arises between the median voter (the writer of the constitution) and the (future) incumbent politician when not only the state of the world and but also the politician s type (preferred policy) are the policy-maker s private information. We show that it is optimal to tie the hands of the politician by imposing both a policy oor and a policy cap and delegating him/her the policy choice only in between the cap and the oor. The delegation interval is shown to be the smaller the greater is the uncertainty about the politician s type.these results are also applicable to settings outside the speci c problem that our model addresses. JEL-Classi cation: D8;H0 Keywords:Representative democracy; optimal delegation; political uncertainty; policy caps; policy oors; citizen candidates.

4 Introduction Representative democracy may be best de ned as a political system in which the power to choose public policies is delegated to elected representatives (which we will call here politicians for short). It is traditionally opposed to direct democracy, a system in which the general public determines itself the laws and policies. The evaluation of the costs and bene ts of delegation is then central in the old debate between the two systems. The main alleged advantage of representative democracy is that representatives are able to specialize in policy-making. This allows them to devote more time to study the state of the world than ordinary citizens and thus to make better informed decisions. Benjamin Constant (89, p.6) put it very neatly when he wrote: The representative system is nothing but an organization by means of which a nation charges a few individuals to do what it cannot or does not wish to do herself. Poor men look after their own business; rich men hire stewards. This is the history of ancient and modern nations. The representative system is a proxy given to a certain number of men by the mass of the people who wish their interests to be defended and who nevertheless do not have the time to defend them themselves. Edmund Burke (854) said the same when writing that it is the duty of the representative to sacri ce his repose, his pleasures, his satisfactions, to those of the constituents. The debate on the relative merits of delegating decisions to politicians versus direct democracy has recently been revived after the Brexit referendum, and questions are raised concerning (i) whether it is a good thing to accept as binding the verdict of a relatively narrow majority of voters (most of whom were not well informed about the question on which they were voting), and more generally, (ii) to what extent should the The idea that elections may be a screening process allowing to delegate the policy choices to policymakers who are deemed more competent than the general population is more controversial. Le système representatif n est autre chose qu une organisation à l aide de laquelle une nation se décharge sur quelques individus de ce qu elle ne peut ou ne veut pas faire elle-même. Les individus pauvres font euxmêmes leurs a aires: les hommes riches prennent des intendants. C est l histoire des nations anciennes et des nations modernes. Le système représentatif est une procuration donnée à un certain nombre d hommes par la masse du peuple, qui veut que ses intérêts soient defendus, et qui néanmoins n a pas le temps de les défendre toujours lui-même. The above English translation appeared in Fontana (988). 3

5 citizens of a democracy be able to make decisions directly? (See, for example, Peter Singer (06), among others). Given the number and the complexity of public decisions to be taken in a modern society, the advantages of representative democracy are so important that in one way or another all modern democracies are basically representative democracies, with sometimes some elements of direct or participative democracy like referendums and/or popular initiatives. It has however long been recognized that this system has costs of its own. The main drawback of representative democracy is that representatives are free, once elected, to promote their own interests. This was expressed forcefully by Jean-Jacques Rousseau (76) who thought that even if it is possible that there exists a coincidence between what the constituency and their representatives want at the time the former delegates their power to the latter, there is nothing to ensure that this coincidence will continue. 3 When legislators are citizen candidates, their actions in o ce follow their own preferences. The sources of divergence between the preferred policies of the median voter and those of the elected representatives are indeed numerous, even when they have the same information about the state of the world. In the rst place, representatives cannot be bound by a binding mandate; indeed they cannot commit to implement speci c policies once elected because it is impossible to write complete contracts describing what the representatives should do in each of the multitude of circumstances that could occur during their term of o ce. In the second place, even if the representatives could commit, as assumed for instance by Downs (957) and Stokes (963), this does not eliminate ex ante political uncertainty, i.e., the uncertainty (prior to and up to the time of the election) about the elected politician s type. On one hand, it is indeed well known that even if the election is a single issue one (one-dimensional policy space) there may be multiple voting equilibria as soon as there are more than two candidates. On the other hand, when the policy space is multi-dimensional, the voters have to choose between 3 Le souverain peut bien dire : Je veux actuellement ce que veut un tel homme, ou du moins ce qu il dit vouloir ; mais il ne peut pas dire : Ce que cet homme voudra demain, je le voudrai encore. Du Contrat Social, chapter VII,. 4

6 packages: there is nothing to ensure that on each issue the elected representative s proposed policies are the ones preferred by a majority. Two recent examples are relevant. In France, although President Macron was recently elected by a large majority, the elimination of the wealth tax (Impôt de Solidarité sur la Fortune), although present in his election platform, is, according to all polls, opposed by a majority of French voters. Similarly, US President Trump s project of repealing Obamacare is opposed by a majority of US voters. More generally, McKelvey (976, p. 47) has shown that in the case of multi-dimensional policy spaces it is theoretically possible to design voting procedures which, starting from any given point, will end up at any other point in the space of alternatives, even at Pareto dominated ones. The purpose of the present paper is to study the optimal design of a representative democracy system as a speci c delegation problem which belongs to a class of delegation problems dealing with settings in which, according to Amador and Bagwell (03) a principal faces an informed but biased agent, and contingent transfers between the principal and the agent are infeasible. 4 Indeed, political settings are highly relevant examples of this kind of problems where legal rules limit or even completely forbid transfers to elected representatives. Compared to the existing theoretical models of delegation, the type of delegation problem we analyze in our paper has a novel feature. While our model and the existing models share a common feature, namely, the agent (the incumbent politician) has private information about the state of the world, and her preference is generally biased with respect to that of the principal s 5, we depart from the existing models by assuming that the principal does not know the direction and magnitude of the agent s bias. The representative s type as determined by the electoral process is a random variable. 6 Throughout this paper we restrict attention 4 The bias is also referred to as the preference divergence between the agent and the principal; see Alonso and Matouschek (008). An example of preference divergence is Angela Merkel s unwillingness to put a ceiling on the number of refugees to be admitted into Germany. 5 The principal is here the writer of the constitution. Throughout the paper we call him/her the median voter though this coincidence may be true only initially. 6 We do not model the electoral process here; we simply treat it a black box, in order to focus on the delegation problem. 5

7 to the case where there is more uncertainty about the state of the world than about the politician s preferences. 7 For the sake of simplicity, we suppose that the voting procedure is unbiased, in the sense that the expected representative s type is the median voter s type. Before analyzing in full our more general model, we consider two benchmark cases. In the rst benchmark, we assume that the median voter, not knowing the direction and magnitude of bias in the politician s preference, must choose one of the following alternatives: (i) giving the elected politician the full freedom to choose policy, versus (ii) requiring that policy must be decided by voters (who are uninformed about the state of the world). We show that in this case, as long as the median voter s uncertainty about the politician s bias is less than the uncertainty about the state of the world, the median voter s expected utility is higher under (i) than under (ii). In our second benchmark scenario, we assume that the politician s bias is known. In this case we obtain results which are in line with Amador and Bagwell (03): the principal sets a policy cap when the politician is known to have a rightist bias, and a policy oor is set when the politician is known to have a leftist bias. We obtain novel results in the more general case where interval delegation is possible, in a scenario where the representative s bias is random while the electoral process is unbiased. We show that the policy choice should then be delegated to the elected representative only within bounds: an upper bound (policy cap) and a lower bound (policy oor). Cap and oor are imposed to avoid extreme policy choices under delegation. Our main result is that the writer of the constitution always nds it optimal to tie the hands of future politicians in this way. Furthermore, we show that the interval of parameter values over which delegation occurs shrinks when the political uncertainty increases. There are several strands of literature on policy choice that are related to our model. Starting from Osborne and Slivinski (996) and Besley and Coate (997), the economic literature has developed an alternative theory of policy choice in representative democra- 7 As will be shown below, this assumption implies that the median voter strictly prefers unfettered representative democracy (i.e. full delegation to the politician) to direct democracy. 6

8 cies, 8 i.e., models in which citizen candidates run for election 9. These models depart from the traditional Hotelling model of electoral competition (Downs (957)) in two important respects: (i) the citizens-candidates have policy preferences instead of being exclusively o ce-motivated, 0 and (ii) they cannot commit to implement any policy other than their most preferred one. Under free entry, the number and types of the candidates are determined at equilibrium. Whereas the initial models assumed complete information, they have been subsequently extended to a setting where each candidate s ideal point is his/her private information. While this literature focuses on the electoral process - which in our model is simply treated as a black box with random outcomes- its conclusions con rm the existence of political uncertainty: there are generally multiple equilibria and the type of the elected representative cannot be predicted with certainty. Indeed, this literature shows that the elected politician s type almost always di ers from the median voter s type. 3 Our model is closer to the political agency models, as surveyed in Besley (006), which also deal with the relationship between citizens/voters (the principals) and the politicians/government (the agent). The agents are generally better informed than the former. This literature encompasses moral hazard models where politicians may use their o ce to extract rents (Ferejohn, 986; Hillman, 08; Persson and Tabellini, 000), and adverse selection models where the issue is to select the good politicians (Besley and Prat, 004). There are also models which combine moral hazard and adverse selection (Besley and Case,995; Coate and Morris,995; 8 Besley and Coate (997, p. 85). 9 See for instance Hamlin and Hjortlund (000) for the proportional representation case, and Mattozzi and Snowberg (08) for an application of the citizen candidates model to taxation and redistribution. 0 Angela Merkel s preference regarding the number of refugees to be admitted is arguably di erent from that of the median voter. She might have been motivated by ethical considerations, or possibly by the prospect of a Nobel Peace Prize. See Peace-Prize-opening-country-s-doors-desperate-refugees.html In the models of Osborne and Slivinski (996) and Besley and Coate (997), candidates are completely informed about the ideal policies of all others. See Großer and Palfrey (009, 04) for theoretical analyses. For an experimental study, see Großer and Palfrey (07). 3 Großer and Palfrey (07, p. ) report that, both theoretically and experimentally, candidate entry is from the extremes of the policy space. 7

9 Fearon,999; among others). The basic element of these models is the idea that politicians may be made accountable 4 to the citizens via electoral competition. 5 While a politician s concern for reelection does act as a discipline device, these models nd that it does not ensure full accountability. Indeed, Fearon (999) nds that voters are better o using elections to select types, rather than disciplining incumbents, and Besley (006, p. ) concludes that the reelection mechanism is imperfect since it is unable to always eliminate dissonant politicians. 6 This is clearly in line with our assumptions about the existence and persistence of political uncertainty. Finally, our paper has much in common with the papers on optimal delegation problem (e.g., Holmström,977 and 984) that focus on interval delegation, i.e., the set over which the policy choice is delegated to the agent is a single interval. 7 Other papers have provided conditions for the optimality of interval delegation under various settings: Amador, Werning and Angeletos (006) when money burning is allowed; Alonso and Matouschek (008) when money burning is not allowed; Ambrus and Egorov (009) for uniform distributions and quadratic utility functions. A recent paper by Amador and Bagwell (03) provides necessary and su cient conditions which encompass previous results as special cases. Our paper departs from all this literature by analyzing the case when the agent s bias is a random variable whose realized value is private information of the agent. 8 We show that when the uncertainty about the state of the world is greater than the political uncertainty and when 4 On political accountability, see Przeworski et al. (999), For a review of recent theoretical and empirical research on electoral accountability, see Ashworth (0). Of note is the array of various alternative approaches to explaining why an incumbent might have incentives to act contrary to voters interests. These include signaling models and multi-task models. In contrast to the two-period models surveyed by Ashworth, there is also a strand of literature that assumes repeated electoral competition: see, for example, Duggan and Feys (006) and Banks and Duggan (008). 5 The voters hold the incumbent politician responsible for the consequences of his/her actions while in o ce, and the politician takes this into account. 6 In the same way, Coate and Morris (995) nd that political competition does not prevent ine cient methods of redistribution to be employed. 7 Interval delegation models are di erent from strategic delegation models, which explore strategic motives for voters to elect politicians di erent from themselves. For strategic delegation motives in election, see Harstad (00) and Christiansen (03). Besley and Coate (997) study the desirability of limiting the set of politician types to whom voters can strategically delegate. 8 Koessler and Martimort (0) have instead studied the case when the decision space is two-dimensional. They assume quadratic utility functions and uniform distribution of the agent s type. 8

10 the political process is not biased, interval delegation holds with both a policy cap and a policy oor. A further result is that the delegation interval gets smaller when the political uncertainty increases. These results clearly apply to many other contexts, and not just to the speci c problem studied in our model. The rest of this paper is organized as follows. Section outlines the model. Section 3 analyzes two benchmark cases. Section 4 characterizes the equilibria. Section 5 concludes. The Model A policy x has to be chosen from a set X = [x L ; x H ] which is a closed interval of the real line. There is a continuum of voters, uniformly distributed along the real interval [ ; ]; we refer to t [ ; ] as the type of voter. The population mass is normalized to unity. The utility of the voter of type t is (B + + t)x where B is a technology parameter, and is the state of the world representing random deviation from B. We assume that the realization is unknown to the voter at the time when a decision on x must be made. To x ideas, one can think of x as the amount of a public good to be provided (e.g., defence expenditure), B + is the productivity (or e ectiveness) of the public good, t is the voter s preference parameter, and (=)x is the per capita cost of nancing the public good (including deadweight losses due to nancing it by means of distortionary taxes 9 ). The voter with t = 0 is called the median voter. Denote by () the probability density function for. Assume that () is strictly positive only for belonging to the real interval [ "; "]. Since voters do not have information about the realized value of, under direct democracy, the median voter would choose x to maximize his expected utility, Bx x, that is, he would vote for x = B. Following the insight of Benjamin Constant, we assume that x politicians, thanks to their specialization, are informed about. 9 In this paper, we do not model these costs. 9

11 We consider a problem where the median voter is the principal and the politician as the agent. At the time when the decision on x must be taken, is not known to the voters, but it is known to the incumbent politician. A politician of type t [ ; ] has the utility function (B + + t)x x Following the political economy approach (see, e.g. Hillman s book, 08), we suppose that politicians are motivated only by self-interest. If the incumbent politician were unconstrained in her decision making, then, given that she has private information about the realized, she would choose x to maximize her own utility, knowing her type is t. This means that she would choose x = B + + t () while the interest of the median voter is best served if x = B +. If t 6= 0, we say that the politician is biased (relative to the median voter s preference). 0 A positive t means the politician s bias is toward the right (e.g., she would like to spend more on defence than the median voter would want). Similarly, a negative t means that the politician s bias is toward the left.. The median voter s problem The politician knows her type t, but the voters do not: they only know that t is distributed with a probability density function (t), where t [ ; ]. At the time when the decision on x must be made, + t is the politician s private information. De ne = + t Then the density function for, denoted by f(), is the convolution ( )(), i.e., f() = ( )() () ( )d () 0 For example, when a politician is of type t = (the most extreme right-wing type), upon observing that = ", she will choose the defence spending level x = B + " + if she is unconstrained in her choice. But any spending level greater than B + " would never be in the best interest of the median voter. 0

12 In what follows, we assume that and are uniform density functions, i.e., 8 < 0 8 < " () = 8 [ "; "] : " 0 8 > " 8 < (t) = : 0 8t < 8t [ ; ] 0 8t > Given the uniform density functions and, the convolution () can be computed as follows. For any given [ " ; " + ], let us denote by D() the set of values that are consistent with t [ ; ], i.e., D() f [ "; "] j g : (3) Then f() = D() d (4) 4" Using (4), we nd that has the following trapezoid-shaped density function 8 "++ < ; 8 [ " ; "] 4" f() = ; 8 [ "; " ] ; (5) : " "+ 8 [" ; " + ] 4" and consequently, the corresponding cumulative distribution function is 8 >< F () = >: ("++) ; 8 [ " ; "] 8" +" ; 8 [ "; " ] : (6) " +(+") " +6" ; 8 [" ; " + ] 8" Given any prescribed schedule x(:) that associates to each + t an action x(), the expected utility of the median voter is W M = " " (B + )x ( + t) (x ( + t)) " d dt (7) This expected utility may be conveniently rewritten as W M = E [(B + )x] E x (8)

13 where and E x "+ x() f()d x() f()d (9) " E [(B + )x] where D() is given by eq. (3). = "+ " " (B + )x ( + t) " " d dt (0) (B + ) d d 4" x() D() Since is the politician s private information, the median voter s problem of expected utility maximization is a principal-agent problem. The median voter must design a schedule x(:) that is incentive-compatible to the agent. Applying the revelation principle, the median voter s optimization problem can be formulated as follows. Problem : Choose a function x(:) that maximizes (8), subject to the incentivecompatibility constraint: an agent that has private information will choose action x() in preference to any other action x(b), i.e., = arg max (B + )x(b) b (x(b)) (). Properties of incentive-compatible schedules in the absence of transfers Before fully characterizing the solution of Problem, we must state a number of properties that any incentive-compatible scheme x(:) must satisfy, given that transfers are not feasible. The median voter, as principal, o ers the elected politician a schedule x(). To x ideas, suppose the median voter writes a constitution which in e ect tells the elected politician the following message: Here is the schedule (the function) x(:) de ned over the set of possible values of [ " ; " + ]. You must report a value b belonging to this set. If your report Unlike the standard (text-book) principal agent model with transfers between the principal and the agent (e.g., La ont and Martimore, 00), here the principal does not receive any transfer from the agent. Her only payo is her personal expected utility derived from x. This is in line with the observation made by Amador and Bagwell (03), that contingent transfers between the principal and the agent are often infeasible.

14 is b, you will be required to take action x(b). Clearly, a schedule x(:) is able to induce the agent to report truthfully if and only if under that schedule, the agent cannot obtain a better payo by reporting a false value b 6= : Let A (b; ) denote the agent s payo, where is the true value and b is the reported value: A (b; ) = (B + )x(b) x(b) () A schedule x(:) induces truth telling if and only if for each ; we have W A () A (; ) A (b; ) for all b [ " ; " + ] : That is, W A () = (B + )x() x() (B + )x(b) x(b) (3) By a standard revealed preference argument, any incentive-compatible schedule x() is nondecreasing and almost everywhere di erentiable for all [ " ; " + ]. In addition, by Berge s maximum theorem, we know that W A () is a continuous function. Over any interval ( ; ) where x() is di erentiable, since A (b; ) is maximized at b =, the following rst order condition must hold, where x(b) is evaluated at b =, [(B + ) x ()] dx d = 0 (4) that is, either x() B = or dx=d = 0 on ( ; ). We report this result as Fact : Fact : Schedules that are incentive-compatible to the politician must be non-decreasing and almost everywhere di erentiable. Over any interval of di erentiability [ 0 ; ], the graph of x() B against is either horizontal (i.e., x() B = constant), or coincides with a segment of the 45 degree ray through the origin, i.e., x() B = for all [ 0 ; ]. Applying the envelope theorem to (), we nd that dw A d (b; It follows from (5) that the following two equations hold: W A () = W A () + = x(b) where b = (5) dw A ( 0 ) d 0 d 0 = W A () + x( 0 )d 0 (6) A politician that observes a higher will want to choose a higher x. Therefore any schedule that is decreasing in over some range of will not be able to induce the politician to report the true. 3

15 W A () = W A () dw A ( 0 ) d 0 = W A () d 0 x( 0 )d 0 (7) where ", and " +. It is important to note that we cannot treat W A () and W A () as constant. We will determine these values endogenously, as part of the optimization problem of the median voter. 3 In general, any incentive-compatible schedule x(:) B, while being non-decreasing and a.e. di erentiable, may exhibit an upward jump discontinuity. At any point e ( " ; "+) where there is an upward jump, we will use the following notation: lim x() x (e) < x + (e) lim x() (8) "e #e Since W A () is continuous, the following relationship holds W A (e) = (B + e)x (e) x (e) = (B + e)x + (e) x+ (e) It follows that h x + (e) x (e) i = (B + e) x + (e) From this equation, we deduce the following Fact: x (e) Fact : At any point ea of upward jump discontinuity of an incentive-compatible schedule x() B, it holds that e = (x+ (e) B) + (x (e) B) : (9) As a consequence of Fact and Fact, we deduce Fact 3: Fact 3: Under incentive compatibility, if a schedule x() B has an upward jump of discontinuity at some e (from the value x (e) B to the value x + (e) B) it must hold that x() B = x (e) B for all ( 0 ; e), and x() B = x + (e) B for all (e; 00 ), where 0 x (e) B and 00 x + (e) B. In other words, a jump must be from one horizontal segment to another. It follows from Fact, Fact, and Fact 3 that there are potentially four di erent types of incentive-compatible schedules: 3 See the proof of Proposition. 4

16 (i) First, the fully exible schedule, x() B = for all [ "; + "]. That is, the politician is unconstrained in her choice of x. (Being unconstrained, the politician will choose x B = because this maximizes her utility.) (ii) Second, semi- exible schedules : x() B = for all in some interval [ 0 ; ], with a policy cap (i.e., x B is not permitted to exceed < " + ), or a policy oor (i.e., x B is not permitted to be below the level 0 > " ), or both a cap and a oor. (iii) Third, step schedules : x() is a step function. There are possibly n intervals, [ 0 ; ), [ ; ),..., [ n ; n ] and over each interval i, x is a constant, x i, where x < x < ::: < x n = x n : (iv) Fourth, hybrid schedules : a hybrid schedule may include several exible segments, and several step-wise discontinuities. Due to the incentive-compatibility constraint () and the presence of the double integral (0), the solution of Problem is not straightforward. We must proceed using a number of steps before reaching our main results. 4 Before solving Problem, in order to aid our intuition, it will be instructive to consider two simpler scenarios, which also serve as useful benchmarks for comparison with our main results. 3 Two benchmark scenarios In this section, we consider two benchmark scenarios. 3. The rst benchmark: choice between unfettered representative democracy and direct democracy In the rst benchmark case, we assume that the median voter, while facing uncertainty about both and t, is restricted to making a choice between two extreme alternatives: (i) Giving 4 Our main results are that (i) it is optimal to impose restrictions on the politician s range of actions, in the form of a policy cap x and a policy oor, x, and (ii) the greater is the uncertainty about the politician s type, as measured by the length of the support of the (uniform) distribution of t, the smaller is the length of the interval [x; x]. 5

17 the politician complete freedom to choose any action x she wants (this extreme scenario is called the unfettered representative democracy case); and (ii) Direct democracy : the voters decide on the policy level x by voting, even though they are completely uninformed about the realized state of the world. Under alternative (i), the elected politician, having observed + t, is free to choose any x. She will then choose the policy level that maximizes her own self-interest, i.e., x( + t) = B + + t. In this case, the median voter s resulting expected utility can be computed as follows: " (B + )(B + + t) " (B + + t) " d d dt = B + 6 " Under alternative (ii), the decision on x is made under direct democracy (the voters directly decide on x). Since voters do not observe, and since E[] = 0, the median voter will choose x to maximize Bx x, resulting in the constant policy, i.e. x = B always. His expected utility is B. Thus we have obtained the following result for our rst benchmark scenario: Result (choice between unfettered representative democracy and direct democracy) Unfettered representative democracy would give rise to a higher welfare level to the median voter, as compared with direct democracy, if and only if < " (i.e., i the uncertainty about the politician s type is smaller than the uncertainty about the state of the world, ). In choosing between unfettered representative democracy (with an informed, but possibly biased politician) and uninformed direct democracy, the median voter faces the trade-o between, on one hand, the bene ts of relying on a politician who has access to information about, and on the other hand, the costs of (i) letting the politician set an x that may exceed the upper bound on what the median voter would ever want, B + " (as the politician may have a rightist bias, and may choose x > B + "), and (ii) letting the politician set an x that falls below what the median voter would ever want (as the politician may have a leftist bias). If < ", these costs are not too large relative to the bene ts, and therefore unfettered 6

18 representative democracy is superior to direct democracy. Remark : In considering the rst benchmark scenario, we have assumed that the expected value of t is zero, i.e., on average, the politician s bias is zero. It is easy to consider the modi ed assumption that t is uniformly distributed over some interval [ + ; + ], where 6= 0. Then the expected value of the politician bias is. In this case even though we maintain the assumption that < ", it can be shown that direct democracy is better than unfettered representative democracy if the politician s bias is expected to be su ciently large, in the sense that 3 > (" ). 3. The second benchmark scenario: the politician s bias is known We now turn to the second benchmark scenario. Here, we assume that the bias t is known, but it is not too large. Speci cally, we suppose that " < t < ". This assumption rules out (i) the existence of a politician with a right-wing bias t > "; such a politician would choose an action x > B + " if > 0, while the median voter would never want x > B + ", whatever the realization of [ "; "], and (ii) the existence of a politician with a left-wing bias t < ". Under this benchmark scenario, the optimal delegation in our model is simply a special case of a more general model of delegation under a known bias, which has been considered in Amador and Bagwell (03). Since the distribution of is uniform over [ "; "], it follows that, given that t is a known constant, the distribution of is uniform over [ " + t; " + t]. With only one source of randomness, the solution of Problem can be characterized relatively easily. We can prove the following results, for the case of a rightist bias, i.e., t > 0. (A symmetric argument applies for the case of a leftist bias.) Result : Given a known rightist bias t > 0, the optimal incentive-compatible schedule x() B has the properties that: (i) for all < " t, the politician is given the freedom to choose her self-interest-maximizing choice, namely, x() B =, and (ii) for all " t (i.e., for all " t), x() B must be equal to the cap value " t. 7

19 Similarly, given a known leftist bias t < 0, the optimal incentive-compatible schedule x() B has the properties that (i) for all > " t, the politician is given the freedom to choose her self-interest-maximizing choice, namely, x() B =, and (ii) for all " t (i.e., < " t), x() B must equal the oor value " t > ". In the case of a known rightist bias, imposing a policy cap serves to rule out extreme-right policies. The greater is the bias, the lower is the optimal cap. Similarly, in the case of a known leftist bias, imposing a policy oor rules out extreme left policies. The greater is the bias, the higher is the oor. Remark : Result above may be generalized to the case where the distribution of is not necessarily uniform. Assume simply a strictly positive continuous density function f() over the set [ "; "]. It may be shown, using the approach of Amador and Bagwell (03), that if F () + tf() is non-decreasing, 5 then: (a) In the case of a known rightist bias t > 0, the optimal schedule x() B consists of (i) a exible policy x() B = for all < y (i.e., all y t), and (ii) for all y (i.e., all y t), x() B must equal the cap y, where y is the solution of the following equation 6 " y ( y)f()d = 0: t (b) In the case of a known leftist bias t < 0, the optimal schedule x() B consists of (i) a exible policy x() B = for all z t, (ii) for all z t, x() B must equal the oor value z, where z is the solution of the following equation z " t ( z)f()d = 0: 5 This is the condition (c), of Amador and Bagwell (03, p. 550). An alternative and simpler proof is possible, along the lines of Laussel and Resende (08). 6 For the uniform distribution, we can see that y = " t. 8

20 4 Optimal cap and oor: The case where the politician s bias is private information We now solve for the optimal schedule x() B when voters do not know the politician s bias, t. We assume that the variance of the distribution of t is smaller than the variance of the distribution of the state of the world,, i.e., we assume < ". Proposition : It is optimal for the median voter to set both a policy cap and a policy oor, and to delegate the policy choice to the politician only for intermediate values of : The cap is x = B + ", that is, x() B = " for all " ; " +. The oor is x() = B " + for all " ; " +. And, for all " + ; ", the politician is free to choose her x, and her choice is x() = B +. The length of this delegation interval is ". Thus, the greater is the uncertainty about political bias, the smaller is the delegation interval. Before proving Proposition, it is useful to state the following Lemma: Lemma : For any incentive-compatible schedule x() B, the median voter s expected utility is given by W M = W A () + or, equivalently, by W M = W A () + "+ " "+ " x() [() (B + ) + h()] f()d (0) x() [() (B + ) ()] f()d () where = ", = " +, and where (i) () is the expected value of + B conditional on the sum + t being equal to, where t [ ; ] : It is given by () f() D() ( + B) d 4" (ii) h() [ F ()] =f(), and () F ()= f() where f() and F () are given by equations (5) and (6). Note that h() is the inverse of the hazard rate. 9

21 Proofs of Lemma and Proposition : See the Appendix. According to Proposition, for a given level " of the state-of-the-world uncertainty, the length of the delegation interval (over which the policy choice is fully delegated to a politician) is " + ; ". This length is decreasing in the level of political uncertainty,. Full delegation, i.e. unfettered representative democracy, is optimal i there is no political uncertainty at all ( = 0 ). The optimal policy is pictured in Figure, where we set B = 0; " = and = : The cap x() = :5 applies for [:5; 3] and the oor x() = :5 applies for [ 3; :5]: The exible policy x() = is preferred when [ :5; :5] : The dashed line indicates what would be a exible policy outside the range in which it is optimal. 5 Conclusion In this paper we have analyzed a novel optimal delegation game between the median voter (the writer of the constitution) and the elected representative (the incumbent politician) in which the latter is privately informed of the state of the world and the former is uninformed about both the state of the world and the politician s type. The politician s type is seen as the exogenous random outcome of an electoral process which is not analyzed here. Our game may be considered to take place before the politician is elected, for instance when the constitution or, more generally the fundamental laws, are written. The main result is that, in that setting, it is optimal for the writer of the constitution, presumably the median voter, to impose an upper and a lower bound to the policies which the incumbent politician is allowed to implement, i.e. to tie the hands of future politicians. This interval delegation result was already obtained in delegation models with known agent s type but is new in a model where the politician s type is private information. Moreover, the form taken here by the interval delegation, with an upper and a lower limit, is itself new compared with the results obtained in applied delegation models with known agent s type. The most prominent example is optimal trade agreements between two governments 0

22 that face private political pressures as studied by Bagwell and Staiger (005) or Amador and Bagwell ((03), Section 4) where the main result is a simple tari cap. 7 Another example is the existence of a simple oor (minimum) equilibrium output in public intrinsic common agency games (Martimort, Semenov and Stole (06)). More generally, Amador and Bagwell (03, Proposition 3) specialize their results on interval delegation to the case where the agent s bias is not a ected by the state of the world, and they give su cient conditions for the interval allocation to take the form of a simple cap. In contrast, from the present model, where not only the state of the world but also the agent s type are private information, it seems that the interval allocation is taking the form of a delegation interval between a oor and a cap. We are rather con dent that these results would extend to the case of more general distribution functions. More speci cally, we conjecture that three natural assumptions may be su cient to entail the optimality of an interval delegation with a cap and a oor: (i) a nonincreasing hazard rate; h 0 () 0; (ii) a derivative 0 () and (iii) a symmetric density function f() that is non-decreasing between " and 0 and non-increasing between 0 and " + : Obviously, these conditions are satis ed when the distributions of and t are uniform as assumed here. We hope to establish a proof of this more general result in a future technical note. Are our results likely to be substantially changed when the incumbent must periodically run for reelection? Clearly not if politicians are primarily policy-motivated: a pure screening e ect of reelection reduces but does remove ex ante political uncertainty. In the opposite polar case, if the incumbent rst and foremost wants to be reelected, the writer of the constitution has to explicitly account for this constraint in the incumbent s program. 8 This will be the subject of further research. Finally, it would certainly be interesting to consider the case where the political process 7 See also Beshkar, Bond and Ro (0), and Amador and Bagwell (0). 8 More precisely the incumbent will never report a value b such that, conditional on this observation, the median voter would prefer to pick randomly a next politician.

23 is not only random but also biased, i.e. when the writer of the constitution rationally expects the politician s type to di er from his/her own one for a variety of reasons. 9 Very likely, the symmetry between the oor and the cap would be lost, the writer of the constitution willing to tie more the hands of future politicians in the direction in which they are more likely to be biased. 9 A possible reason is an external reward (e.g., the prospect of a Nobel Peace Prize). Other reasons include the in uence of pressure groups, and the possibly greater in uence of a uent people on the politicians decisions. See for instance Gilens (04), and Gilens and Page (08).

24 Appendix Proof of Result The proof is given for the case of a rightist bias (t > 0). A similar argument applies in the case of a leftist bias. The proof proceeds in three steps. Step : With a known bias t, it is never optimal for the median voter to set a discontinuous schedule x() B involving a step function over an interval [ 0 ; ] [ " + t; " t]. Proof: In view of Facts, and 3, without loss of generality, consider a schedule x() B that has a discontinuity at point e = ( 0 + )=, with x (e) B = 0 and x + (e) B =. Then x() B = 0 for all [ 0 ; e) and x() B = for all [e; ]. We now show that we can construct an alternative schedule x # () B that dominates x() B. Let x # () B = x() B for all outside [ 0 ; ], and x # () B = for all [ 0 ; ]. Then the median voter s expected utility under schedule x # () B exceeds his expected utility under x() B by the amount given below: 30 " Write 0 ( t) d " e 0 ( t) 0 0 d ( t) " e d x = 0 ; u = e = x + y ; y = > x The terms that have t as a multiplicative factor cancel each other out. The remaining terms are " u x ( + x x)d + " y u ( + y y)d = 48" (y x)3 > 0 Step : If t > 0, any schedule x() B with a oor, i.e., x() B = 0 for all [ " + t; 0 ] is not optimal. Proof: Consider an alternative schedule x # () which is identical to x() outside the interval [ " + t; 0 ], and x # () B = for all in the interval [ " + t; 0 ] : 30 The expression below does not contain B because it can be veri ed that the terms involving B in the three integrals cancel each other out. 3

25 The excess of the median voter s expected utility under x # (:) over his expected utility under x(:) is = " 0 "+t ( t) d 0 ( t) 0 " "+t 0 d Let x = " + t and y = 0 > " + t. Then y ( t) d = y Thus " = y t x x ( t)y y y d = y x y x 3 6 y t x y y x y yt (y x) x x 3 6 yt (y x) y (y x) y (y x) = 6 (y x) (3t x + y) = 6 ( 0 + " t) (t + " + 0 ) > 0 if t > 0: Step 3: From Step and Step, the only remaining possibilities are (i) a fully exible schedule, and (ii) a semi- exible schedule with a cap that applies for all [ ; " + t], for some " + t. Note that a fully exible policy is equivalent to a semi- exible policy, with a cap that applies only at = " + t. Therefore, to prove Result, it su ces to show that the optimal cap must be operative for all " t, and at = " t, x(" t) = " t. To prove this, we compute the median voter s expected utility under a semi- exible policy and show that it attains its maximum at = " t. The median voter s expected utility is computed as follows. Let x = B " + t and v = B + " + t. Let y =. Then the median voter seeks to maximize the sum of following integrals, by choosing y y v (B + t)(b + ) (B + ) d + (B + t)(b + y) x y (B + y) d Di erentiating the above integrals with respect to y, using Leibnitz s rule, we obtain the rst order condition for a maximum: (v y) (t v + y) = 0 4

26 The solution y = v t satis es both the FOC and SOC. 3 Proof of Lemma From (3) and (6), and de ning = " and = " + x() = (B + )x() + W A () = (B + )x() + W A () + (B + )x() + W A () + K() x( 0 )d 0 with K 0 () x(). Then x() f()d = W A () (B + )x()f()d + K()f()d Integrating K()f() by parts gives Then K()f()d = [K()F () K()F ()] = x()d x()h()f()d x() f()d = W A () + x()f ()d = x()f ()d x() F () f()d f() x() [h() (B + )] f()d (A.) Using (8), (9), (0) and (A.), the expected utility of the median voter can be written as W M = x(a) [() + h() (B + )] f()d + W A () where () f() D() (B + ) d: 4" This establishes (0). A similar argument establishes (). As a veri cation, note that if we subtract equation () from (0), we get 0 = W () W () + "+ " x()d = W () W () + "+ " dw d d 3 The other solution to the FOC does not satisfy the SOC, and corresponds to a local minimum. 5

27 which is correct. Proof of Proposition The proof consists of three steps. The rst is to show that a exible policy is always better than any discontinuous incentive-compatible policy when " ; " + ;. The second one is to prove that (i) it is better to have some policy cap (resp. policy oor) and that (ii) the optimal policy cap (resp. policy oor) is such that x() B = " " for all ; " + (resp. such that x() B = " + for all " ; " + ). Then, in step 3, we prove that discontinuous policies are also dominated at the two extremes of the interval. Step : Consider any incentive-compatible schedule x() B that has a jump discontinuity at some e, where e = 0+ and " + < 0 < < ". We will show that such a schedule is dominated by a similar schedule that does not have a jump. In fact, let x (e) B = 0 and x + (e) B =. Then x() B = 0 for all [ 0 ; e) and x() B = for all [e; ]. We now show that we can construct an alternative schedule x # () B that dominates x() B. Let x # () B be the same as x() B except over the interval [ 0 ; ] ; where x # () B =. Note that x() B is a step function over the interval [ 0 ; ] and the discontinuity occurs at e = ( 0 + )=, with B + 0 = lim "e x() x (e) < x + (e) lim #e x() = B + > B + e We must show that the excess of the median voter s expected utility under the schedule x # (:) B over his expected utility under the schedule x(:) B is strictly positive. Using (0), and de ning g() = [() (B + ) + h()] f(), this excess is given ( 0 ; ) = = 0 g()d e 0 0 g()d + e g()d 0 g()d f [G( ) G(e)] + 0 [G(e) G( 0 )]g where G() "+ g()d 6

28 Notice that ( 0 ; 0 ) = 0. Thus, if we can show 0 ; )=@ > 0 then we can conclude that ( 0 ; ) > 0 or all > 0. To show 0 ; )=@ > 0, note 0 ; )=@ = G(e) G( ) + g(e)( e) (A.) If g 0 () < 0 (which implies that G(:) is a strictly concave function), then clearly the RHS of (A.) is indeed strictly positive,. We now prove that g 0 () < 0. Recall that by de nition, g() [ F ()] (B + )f() + D() ( + B) d 4" and f() and F () are given by (5) and (6). Then direct computation shows that 8 < g() = : +(+") 3"+" ; 8 [ " ; "] 4" " ; 8 [ "; " ] " ; 8 [" ; " + ] 4" (" )("+ ) It is easy to see that g 0 () < 0; 8 ( " ; " + ): : (A.3) Step : Having shown that it is not optimal to have a discontinuous schedule x() B, we now show that, among all the continuous semi- exible schedules x() B, setting a policy cap is always optimal, and, moreover, the best policy cap is x() B = " " ; " +. for all Let us consider an arbitrary incentive-compatible schedule x() with a policy cap x B = for some, i.e., x() B = for all [ ; " + ]. Using (0), we compute the di erence between the median voter s expected utility obtained from this schedule, and his/her expected utility obtained from an alternative schedule x y () such that (i) x y () B is identical 3 to x() B for all [ " ; ] and (ii) for all [ ; " + ] we have x y () B = (i.e., it is exible in this interval). The di erence in expected utility levels obtained from x() and x y () is W ( ) = "+ ( )g()d; (A.4) where g() is given by (A.3). Direct computation shows that 3 This implies, in particular, that x() = x y (), so that W A () has the same value under the two schedules. 7

29 8 >< " 3 (++ ) 3 ( " ) < 0; if [ " ; "] 6 48" W ( ) = ( ")( ")( + ") 0; if " [ "; " ] : >: ( 48" + ")( + " ) 3 ; if [" ; " + ] Thus, W ( ) is equal to 0 at the value = " + and also at the value = " ; and it is strictly positive for all (" ; " + ) and strictly negative if < ". In particular, W ( ) attains its maximum value at = " cap is to set the cap x = B + " : It follows that the best policy ; that is, x() = B + " for all " ; " + : With the optimal cap, we nd that the endogenously determined W A () is given by W A () =. (B + ) B + " B + " Step 3: We now show that any schedule x() B that has a discontinuous jump to a cap, where the discontinuity occurs at some e in the interior of the interval " ; " + with the cap being set such that x B = where " + > e (i.e., x() B = for all (e; " + ]) is dominated by the schedule x # () B which is identical to x() B for all 0 where + 0 = e, and which has a cap x # B = 0, i.e. x # () B = 0 for all [ 0 ; " + ]. Indeed the expected median voter s utility under x # (:) exceeds the one under x(:) by "+ 0 + ( 0 ) g()d = 96" ( 0 )( 0 + " + )( + 0 (" + )) > 0: Remark: By an argument symmetrical to Step, a policy oor is always optimal. In fact, using equation () to compute the di erence between the median voter s expected utility obtained from a schedule x() B with a oor, and an alternative schedule x y () B without a oor, we can show that the best policy oor is x() = B " + for all " ; " + : By an argument symmetrical to Step 3, one can show that any schedule with a discontinuity at some e in the interior of the interval " ; " + is dominated by a continuous schedule. With the optimal oor, we nd that the endogenously determined W A () is given by W A () = (B + ) B " + B " +. 8

Decentralization via Federal and Unitary Referenda

Decentralization via Federal and Unitary Referenda Decentralization via Federal and Unitary Referenda First Version: January 1997 This version: May 22 Ben Lockwood 1 Department of Economics, University of Warwick, Coventry CV4 7AL UK. email: b.lockwood@warwick.ac.uk

More information

Policy Reversal. Espen R. Moen and Christian Riis. Abstract. We analyze the existence of policy reversal, the phenomenon sometimes observed

Policy Reversal. Espen R. Moen and Christian Riis. Abstract. We analyze the existence of policy reversal, the phenomenon sometimes observed Policy Reversal Espen R. Moen and Christian Riis Abstract We analyze the existence of policy reversal, the phenomenon sometimes observed that a certain policy (say extreme left-wing) is implemented by

More information

Decision Making Procedures for Committees of Careerist Experts. The call for "more transparency" is voiced nowadays by politicians and pundits

Decision Making Procedures for Committees of Careerist Experts. The call for more transparency is voiced nowadays by politicians and pundits Decision Making Procedures for Committees of Careerist Experts Gilat Levy; Department of Economics, London School of Economics. The call for "more transparency" is voiced nowadays by politicians and pundits

More information

Policy Reputation and Political Accountability

Policy Reputation and Political Accountability Policy Reputation and Political Accountability Tapas Kundu October 9, 2016 Abstract We develop a model of electoral competition where both economic policy and politician s e ort a ect voters payo. When

More information

Diversity and Redistribution

Diversity and Redistribution Diversity and Redistribution Raquel Fernández y NYU, CEPR, NBER Gilat Levy z LSE and CEPR Revised: October 2007 Abstract In this paper we analyze the interaction of income and preference heterogeneity

More information

Political Economics II Spring Lectures 4-5 Part II Partisan Politics and Political Agency. Torsten Persson, IIES

Political Economics II Spring Lectures 4-5 Part II Partisan Politics and Political Agency. Torsten Persson, IIES Lectures 4-5_190213.pdf Political Economics II Spring 2019 Lectures 4-5 Part II Partisan Politics and Political Agency Torsten Persson, IIES 1 Introduction: Partisan Politics Aims continue exploring policy

More information

Authoritarianism and Democracy in Rentier States. Thad Dunning Department of Political Science University of California, Berkeley

Authoritarianism and Democracy in Rentier States. Thad Dunning Department of Political Science University of California, Berkeley Authoritarianism and Democracy in Rentier States Thad Dunning Department of Political Science University of California, Berkeley CHAPTER THREE FORMAL MODEL 1 CHAPTER THREE 1 Introduction In Chapters One

More information

Enriqueta Aragones Harvard University and Universitat Pompeu Fabra Andrew Postlewaite University of Pennsylvania. March 9, 2000

Enriqueta Aragones Harvard University and Universitat Pompeu Fabra Andrew Postlewaite University of Pennsylvania. March 9, 2000 Campaign Rhetoric: a model of reputation Enriqueta Aragones Harvard University and Universitat Pompeu Fabra Andrew Postlewaite University of Pennsylvania March 9, 2000 Abstract We develop a model of infinitely

More information

Political Parties and Network Formation

Political Parties and Network Formation ömmföäflsäafaäsflassflassflas ffffffffffffffffffffffffffffffffffff Discussion Papers Political Parties and Network Formation Topi Miettinen University of Helsinki, RUESG and HECER and University College

More information

The Immigration Policy Puzzle

The Immigration Policy Puzzle MPRA Munich Personal RePEc Archive The Immigration Policy Puzzle Paolo Giordani and Michele Ruta UISS Guido Carli University, World Trade Organization 2009 Online at https://mpra.ub.uni-muenchen.de/23584/

More information

Optimal Gerrymandering in a Competitive. Environment

Optimal Gerrymandering in a Competitive. Environment Optimal Gerrymandering in a Competitive Environment John N. Friedman and Richard T. Holden December 9, 2008 Abstract We analyze a model of optimal gerrymandering where two parties receive a noisy signal

More information

Political Agency in Democracies and Dictatorships. Georgy Vladimirovich Egorov

Political Agency in Democracies and Dictatorships. Georgy Vladimirovich Egorov Political Agency in Democracies and Dictatorships A dissertation presented by Georgy Vladimirovich Egorov to The Department of Economics in partial ful llment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor

More information

Lobbying and Elections

Lobbying and Elections Lobbying and Elections Jan Klingelhöfer RWTH Aachen University April 15, 2013 Abstract analyze the interaction between post-election lobbying and the voting decisions of forward-looking voters. The existing

More information

Weak States And Steady States: The Dynamics of Fiscal Capacity

Weak States And Steady States: The Dynamics of Fiscal Capacity Weak States And Steady States: The Dynamics of Fiscal Capacity Timothy Besley London School of Economics and CIFAR Ethan Ilzetzki London School of Economics Torsten Persson IIES, Stockholm University and

More information

policy-making. footnote We adopt a simple parametric specification which allows us to go between the two polar cases studied in this literature.

policy-making. footnote We adopt a simple parametric specification which allows us to go between the two polar cases studied in this literature. Introduction Which tier of government should be responsible for particular taxing and spending decisions? From Philadelphia to Maastricht, this question has vexed constitution designers. Yet still the

More information

1 Electoral Competition under Certainty

1 Electoral Competition under Certainty 1 Electoral Competition under Certainty We begin with models of electoral competition. This chapter explores electoral competition when voting behavior is deterministic; the following chapter considers

More information

Coalition Governments and Political Rents

Coalition Governments and Political Rents Coalition Governments and Political Rents Dr. Refik Emre Aytimur Georg-August-Universität Göttingen January 01 Abstract We analyze the impact of coalition governments on the ability of political competition

More information

Classical papers: Osborbe and Slivinski (1996) and Besley and Coate (1997)

Classical papers: Osborbe and Slivinski (1996) and Besley and Coate (1997) The identity of politicians is endogenized Typical approach: any citizen may enter electoral competition at a cost. There is no pre-commitment on the platforms, and winner implements his or her ideal policy.

More information

Mauricio Soares Bugarin Electoral Control en the Presence of Gridlocks

Mauricio Soares Bugarin Electoral Control en the Presence of Gridlocks Mauricio Soares Bugarin Electoral Control en the Presence of Gridlocks Electoral control in the presence of gridlocks Mauricio Soares Bugarin y University of Brasilia April 2001 Abstract This article presents

More information

Information, Polarization and Term Length in Democracy

Information, Polarization and Term Length in Democracy Information, Polarization and Term Length in Democracy Christian Schultz y July 2007 Abstract This paper considers term lengths in a representative democracy where the political issue divides the population

More information

A Role for Sunspots in Explaining Endogenous Fluctutations in Illegal Immigration 1

A Role for Sunspots in Explaining Endogenous Fluctutations in Illegal Immigration 1 A Role for Sunspots in Explaining Endogenous Fluctutations in Illegal Immigration 1 Mark G. Guzman Research Department Federal Reserve Bank of Dallas Joseph H. Haslag Department of Economics University

More information

Social Networks, Achievement Motivation, and Corruption: Theory and Evidence

Social Networks, Achievement Motivation, and Corruption: Theory and Evidence Social Networks, Achievement Motivation, and Corruption: Theory and Evidence J. Roberto Parra-Segura University of Cambridge September, 009 (Draft, please do not cite or circulate) We develop an equilibrium

More information

A Role for Government Policy and Sunspots in Explaining Endogenous Fluctuations in Illegal Immigration 1

A Role for Government Policy and Sunspots in Explaining Endogenous Fluctuations in Illegal Immigration 1 A Role for Government Policy and Sunspots in Explaining Endogenous Fluctuations in Illegal Immigration 1 Mark G. Guzman 2 Research Department Federal Reserve Bank of Dallas Joseph H. Haslag Department

More information

Reputation and Rhetoric in Elections

Reputation and Rhetoric in Elections Reputation and Rhetoric in Elections Enriqueta Aragonès Institut d Anàlisi Econòmica, CSIC Andrew Postlewaite University of Pennsylvania April 11, 2005 Thomas R. Palfrey Princeton University Earlier versions

More information

Sending Information to Interactive Receivers Playing a Generalized Prisoners Dilemma

Sending Information to Interactive Receivers Playing a Generalized Prisoners Dilemma Sending Information to Interactive Receivers Playing a Generalized Prisoners Dilemma K r Eliaz and Roberto Serrano y February 20, 2013 Abstract Consider the problem of information disclosure for a planner

More information

Public and Private Welfare State Institutions

Public and Private Welfare State Institutions Public and Private Welfare State Institutions A Formal Theory of American Exceptionalism Kaj Thomsson, Yale University and RIIE y November 15, 2008 Abstract I develop a formal model of di erential welfare

More information

Sampling Equilibrium, with an Application to Strategic Voting Martin J. Osborne 1 and Ariel Rubinstein 2 September 12th, 2002.

Sampling Equilibrium, with an Application to Strategic Voting Martin J. Osborne 1 and Ariel Rubinstein 2 September 12th, 2002. Sampling Equilibrium, with an Application to Strategic Voting Martin J. Osborne 1 and Ariel Rubinstein 2 September 12th, 2002 Abstract We suggest an equilibrium concept for a strategic model with a large

More information

Distributive Politics and Economic Ideology

Distributive Politics and Economic Ideology MPRA Munich Personal RePEc Archive Distributive Politics and Economic Ideology David Lopez-Rodriguez Columbia University, Department of Economics 2011 Online at https://mpra.ub.uni-muenchen.de/44145/ MPRA

More information

Nomination Processes and Policy Outcomes

Nomination Processes and Policy Outcomes Nomination Processes and Policy Outcomes Matthew O. Jackson, Laurent Mathevet, Kyle Mattes y Forthcoming: Quarterly Journal of Political Science Abstract We provide a set of new models of three di erent

More information

Rational Voters and Political Advertising

Rational Voters and Political Advertising Rational Voters and Political Advertising Andrea Prat London School of Economics November 9, 2004 1 Introduction Most political scholars agree that organized groups play a key role in modern democracy.

More information

HOTELLING-DOWNS MODEL OF ELECTORAL COMPETITION AND THE OPTION TO QUIT

HOTELLING-DOWNS MODEL OF ELECTORAL COMPETITION AND THE OPTION TO QUIT HOTELLING-DOWNS MODEL OF ELECTORAL COMPETITION AND THE OPTION TO QUIT ABHIJIT SENGUPTA AND KUNAL SENGUPTA SCHOOL OF ECONOMICS AND POLITICAL SCIENCE UNIVERSITY OF SYDNEY SYDNEY, NSW 2006 AUSTRALIA Abstract.

More information

POLITICAL EQUILIBRIUM SOCIAL SECURITY WITH MIGRATION

POLITICAL EQUILIBRIUM SOCIAL SECURITY WITH MIGRATION POLITICAL EQUILIBRIUM SOCIAL SECURITY WITH MIGRATION Laura Marsiliani University of Durham laura.marsiliani@durham.ac.uk Thomas I. Renström University of Durham and CEPR t.i.renstrom@durham.ac.uk We analyze

More information

July, Abstract. Keywords: Criminality, law enforcement, social system.

July, Abstract. Keywords: Criminality, law enforcement, social system. Nontechnical Summary For most types of crimes but especially for violent ones, the number of o enses per inhabitant is larger in the US than in Europe. In the same time, expenditures for police, courts

More information

Collective Decision with Costly Information: Theory and Experiments

Collective Decision with Costly Information: Theory and Experiments Collective Decision with Costly Information: Theory and Experiments Alexander Elbittar 1, Andrei Gomberg 2, César Martinelli 2 and Thomas R. Palfrey 3 1 CIDE, 2 ITAM, 3 Caltech University of Technology

More information

14.770: Introduction to Political Economy Lectures 8 and 9: Political Agency

14.770: Introduction to Political Economy Lectures 8 and 9: Political Agency 14.770: Introduction to Political Economy Lectures 8 and 9: Political Agency Daron Acemoglu MIT October 2 and 4, 2018. Daron Acemoglu (MIT) Political Economy Lectures 8 and 9 October 2 and 4, 2018. 1 /

More information

Corruption and Political Competition

Corruption and Political Competition Corruption and Political Competition Richard Damania Adelaide University Erkan Yalçin Yeditepe University October 24, 2005 Abstract There is a growing evidence that political corruption is often closely

More information

Intertwined Federalism: Accountability Problems under Partial Decentralization

Intertwined Federalism: Accountability Problems under Partial Decentralization Groupe de Recherche en Économie et Développement International Cahier de recherche / Working Paper 08-22 Intertwined Federalism: Accountability Problems under Partial Decentralization Marcelin Joanis Intertwined

More information

The Provision of Public Goods Under Alternative. Electoral Incentives

The Provision of Public Goods Under Alternative. Electoral Incentives The Provision of Public Goods Under Alternative Electoral Incentives Alessandro Lizzeri and Nicola Persico March 10, 2000 American Economic Review, forthcoming ABSTRACT Politicians who care about the spoils

More information

"Efficient and Durable Decision Rules with Incomplete Information", by Bengt Holmström and Roger B. Myerson

Efficient and Durable Decision Rules with Incomplete Information, by Bengt Holmström and Roger B. Myerson April 15, 2015 "Efficient and Durable Decision Rules with Incomplete Information", by Bengt Holmström and Roger B. Myerson Econometrica, Vol. 51, No. 6 (Nov., 1983), pp. 1799-1819. Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/1912117

More information

Polarization and Income Inequality: A Dynamic Model of Unequal Democracy

Polarization and Income Inequality: A Dynamic Model of Unequal Democracy Polarization and Income Inequality: A Dynamic Model of Unequal Democracy Timothy Feddersen and Faruk Gul 1 March 30th 2015 1 We thank Weifeng Zhong for research assistance. Thanks also to John Duggan for

More information

The Robustness of Herrera, Levine and Martinelli s Policy platforms, campaign spending and voter participation

The Robustness of Herrera, Levine and Martinelli s Policy platforms, campaign spending and voter participation The Robustness of Herrera, Levine and Martinelli s Policy platforms, campaign spending and voter participation Alexander Chun June 8, 009 Abstract In this paper, I look at potential weaknesses in the electoral

More information

Ambiguity and Extremism in Elections

Ambiguity and Extremism in Elections Ambiguity and Extremism in Elections Alberto Alesina Harvard University Richard Holden Massachusetts Institute of Technology June 008 Abstract We analyze a model in which voters are uncertain about the

More information

3 Electoral Competition

3 Electoral Competition 3 Electoral Competition We now turn to a discussion of two-party electoral competition in representative democracy. The underlying policy question addressed in this chapter, as well as the remaining chapters

More information

Tax Competition and Migration: The Race-to-the-Bottom Hypothesis Revisited

Tax Competition and Migration: The Race-to-the-Bottom Hypothesis Revisited Tax Competition and Migration: The Race-to-the-Bottom Hypothesis Revisited Assaf Razin y and Efraim Sadka z January 2011 Abstract The literature on tax competition with free capital mobility cites several

More information

Preferential votes and minority representation in open list proportional representation systems

Preferential votes and minority representation in open list proportional representation systems Soc Choice Welf (018) 50:81 303 https://doi.org/10.1007/s00355-017-1084- ORIGINAL PAPER Preferential votes and minority representation in open list proportional representation systems Margherita Negri

More information

Veto Players, Policy Change and Institutional Design. Tiberiu Dragu and Hannah K. Simpson New York University

Veto Players, Policy Change and Institutional Design. Tiberiu Dragu and Hannah K. Simpson New York University Veto Players, Policy Change and Institutional Design Tiberiu Dragu and Hannah K. Simpson New York University December 2016 Abstract What institutional arrangements allow veto players to secure maximal

More information

Con rmation Bias and Electoral Accountability

Con rmation Bias and Electoral Accountability Con rmation Bias and Electoral Accountability Ben Lockwood y University of Warwick First version: 8 February 2015 This version: 7 April 2016 Abstract This paper considers the implications of an important

More information

ON IGNORANT VOTERS AND BUSY POLITICIANS

ON IGNORANT VOTERS AND BUSY POLITICIANS Number 252 July 2015 ON IGNORANT VOTERS AND BUSY POLITICIANS R. Emre Aytimur Christian Bruns ISSN: 1439-2305 On Ignorant Voters and Busy Politicians R. Emre Aytimur University of Goettingen Christian Bruns

More information

Ideology and Competence in Alternative Electoral Systems.

Ideology and Competence in Alternative Electoral Systems. Ideology and Competence in Alternative Electoral Systems. Matias Iaryczower and Andrea Mattozzi July 9, 2008 Abstract We develop a model of elections in proportional (PR) and majoritarian (FPTP) electoral

More information

Immigration and Conflict in Democracies

Immigration and Conflict in Democracies Immigration and Conflict in Democracies Santiago Sánchez-Pagés Ángel Solano García June 2008 Abstract Relationships between citizens and immigrants may not be as good as expected in some western democracies.

More information

Good Politicians' Distorted Incentives

Good Politicians' Distorted Incentives Good Politicians' Distorted Incentives Margherita Negri School of Economics and Finance Online Discussion Paper Series issn 2055-303X http://ideas.repec.org/s/san/wpecon.html info: econ@st-andrews.ac.uk

More information

Party Platforms with Endogenous Party Membership

Party Platforms with Endogenous Party Membership Party Platforms with Endogenous Party Membership Panu Poutvaara 1 Harvard University, Department of Economics poutvaar@fas.harvard.edu Abstract In representative democracies, the development of party platforms

More information

Bipartisan Gerrymandering

Bipartisan Gerrymandering Bipartisan Gerrymandering Hideo Konishi y Chen-Yu Pan z February 15, 2016 Abstract In this paper we propose a tractable model of partisan gerrymandering followed by electoral competitions in policy positions

More information

Decentralization, Vertical Fiscal Imbalance, and Political Selection

Decentralization, Vertical Fiscal Imbalance, and Political Selection Decentralization, Vertical Fiscal Imbalance, and Political Selection Massimo Bordignon Department of Economics and Public Finance Catholic University, Milan & CESifo massimo.bordignon@unicatt.it Matteo

More information

Information, polarization and delegation in democracy

Information, polarization and delegation in democracy Information, polarization and delegation in democracy Christian Schultz 12 October 2003 1 Institute of Economics, University of Copenhagen, Studiestraede 6, DK 1455 Copenhagen K, Denmark. e-mail: cs@econ.ku.dk

More information

Intro Prefs & Voting Electoral comp. Voter Turnout Agency. Political Economics. Ludwig-Maximilians University Munich. Summer term / 62

Intro Prefs & Voting Electoral comp. Voter Turnout Agency. Political Economics. Ludwig-Maximilians University Munich. Summer term / 62 1 / 62 Political Economics Ludwig-Maximilians University Munich Summer term 2010 4 / 62 Table of contents 1 Introduction(MG) 2 Preferences and voting (MG) 3 Voter turnout (MG) 4 Electoral competition (SÜ)

More information

ESSAYS ON STRATEGIC VOTING. by Sun-Tak Kim B. A. in English Language and Literature, Hankuk University of Foreign Studies, Seoul, Korea, 1998

ESSAYS ON STRATEGIC VOTING. by Sun-Tak Kim B. A. in English Language and Literature, Hankuk University of Foreign Studies, Seoul, Korea, 1998 ESSAYS ON STRATEGIC VOTING by Sun-Tak Kim B. A. in English Language and Literature, Hankuk University of Foreign Studies, Seoul, Korea, 1998 Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of the Kenneth P. Dietrich

More information

The E ects of Identities, Incentives, and Information on Voting 1

The E ects of Identities, Incentives, and Information on Voting 1 The E ects of Identities, Incentives, and Information on Voting Anna Bassi 2 Rebecca Morton 3 Kenneth Williams 4 July 2, 28 We thank Ted Brader, Jens Grosser, Gabe Lenz, Tom Palfrey, Brian Rogers, Josh

More information

Chapter 2: The Anatomy of Government Failure

Chapter 2: The Anatomy of Government Failure Chapter 2: The Anatomy of Government Failure Contents 1 Introduction 3 2 Three notions of Government Failure 5 2.1 Pareto Ine ciency..................... 6 2.2 Distributional Failures...................

More information

Should We Tax or Cap Political Contributions? A Lobbying Model With Policy Favors and Access

Should We Tax or Cap Political Contributions? A Lobbying Model With Policy Favors and Access Should We Tax or Cap Political Contributions? A Lobbying Model With Policy Favors and Access Christopher Cotton Published in the Journal of Public Economics, 93(7/8): 831-842, 2009 Abstract This paper

More information

Melting Pot vs. Cultural Mosaic Dynamic Public Finance Perspective

Melting Pot vs. Cultural Mosaic Dynamic Public Finance Perspective Melting Pot vs. Cultural Mosaic Dynamic Public Finance Perspective Gurgen Aslanyan CERGE-EI y, Prague April 2013 Abstract The traditional immigrant countries can be characterised as either supporting a

More information

SKILLED MIGRATION: WHEN SHOULD A GOVERNMENT RESTRICT MIGRATION OF SKILLED WORKERS?* Gabriel Romero

SKILLED MIGRATION: WHEN SHOULD A GOVERNMENT RESTRICT MIGRATION OF SKILLED WORKERS?* Gabriel Romero SKILLED MIGRATION: WHEN SHOULD A GOVERNMENT RESTRICT MIGRATION OF SKILLED WORKERS?* Gabriel Romero WP-AD 2007-25 Correspondence: Departamento de Fundamentos del Análisis Económico, Universidad de Alicante,

More information

The E ects of Political Competition on the Feasibility of Economic Reform

The E ects of Political Competition on the Feasibility of Economic Reform The E ects of Political Competition on the Feasibility of Economic Reform David Pinto November 17, 2008 Abstract This paper explores the e ects of political competition on reform feasibility. Rent preservation

More information

Quorum Rules and Shareholder Power

Quorum Rules and Shareholder Power Quorum Rules and Shareholder Power Patricia Charléty y, Marie-Cécile Fagart z and Saïd Souam x February 15, 2016 Abstract This paper completely characterizes the equilibria of a costly voting game where

More information

Voter Participation with Collusive Parties. David K. Levine and Andrea Mattozzi

Voter Participation with Collusive Parties. David K. Levine and Andrea Mattozzi Voter Participation with Collusive Parties David K. Levine and Andrea Mattozzi 1 Overview Woman who ran over husband for not voting pleads guilty USA Today April 21, 2015 classical political conflict model:

More information

I will be presenting the theory of this paper along with current research that tests the theoretical predictions.

I will be presenting the theory of this paper along with current research that tests the theoretical predictions. Brandice Canes-Wrone Presidential Pandering and Leadership NYU Presentation, January 22, 2002 I will be presenting the theory of this paper along with current research that tests the theoretical predictions.

More information

Political Institutions as Robust Control: Theory and Application to Economic Growth

Political Institutions as Robust Control: Theory and Application to Economic Growth Political Institutions as Robust Control: Theory and Application to Economic Growth Timothy Besley LSE and CIFAR Hannes Mueller IAE (CSIC), MOVE and Barcelona GSE July 15, 2015 Abstract This paper develops

More information

The Role of the Trade Policy Committee in EU Trade Policy: A Political-Economic Analysis

The Role of the Trade Policy Committee in EU Trade Policy: A Political-Economic Analysis The Role of the Trade Policy Committee in EU Trade Policy: A Political-Economic Analysis Wim Van Gestel, Christophe Crombez January 18, 2011 Abstract This paper presents a political-economic analysis of

More information

Handcuffs for the Grabbing Hand? Media Capture and Government Accountability by Timothy Besley and Andrea Prat (2006)

Handcuffs for the Grabbing Hand? Media Capture and Government Accountability by Timothy Besley and Andrea Prat (2006) Handcuffs for the Grabbing Hand? Media Capture and Government Accountability by Timothy Besley and Andrea Prat (2006) Group Hicks: Dena, Marjorie, Sabina, Shehryar To the press alone, checkered as it is

More information

The Citizen-Candidate Model with Imperfect Policy Control

The Citizen-Candidate Model with Imperfect Policy Control The Citizen-Candidate Model with Imperfect Policy Control R. Emre Aytimur, Georg-August University Gottingen Aristotelis Boukouras, University of Leicester Robert Schwagerz, Georg-August University Gottingen

More information

'Wave riding' or 'Owning the issue': How do candidates determine campaign agendas?

'Wave riding' or 'Owning the issue': How do candidates determine campaign agendas? 'Wave riding' or 'Owning the issue': How do candidates determine campaign agendas? Mariya Burdina University of Colorado, Boulder Department of Economics October 5th, 008 Abstract In this paper I adress

More information

Candidate Citizen Models

Candidate Citizen Models Candidate Citizen Models General setup Number of candidates is endogenous Candidates are unable to make binding campaign promises whoever wins office implements her ideal policy Citizens preferences are

More information

Should rational voters rely only on candidates characteristics?

Should rational voters rely only on candidates characteristics? Should rational voters rely only on candidates characteristics? Sergio Vicente. IDEA, Universitat Autònoma de Barcelona. February 006. Abstract This paper analyzes the role of information in elections

More information

Candidate Quality. Panu Poutvaara University of Helsinki and HECER. Tuomas Takalo Bank of Finland. Discussion Paper No. 74 August 2005 ISSN

Candidate Quality. Panu Poutvaara University of Helsinki and HECER. Tuomas Takalo Bank of Finland. Discussion Paper No. 74 August 2005 ISSN ömmföäflsäafaäsflassflassflas ffffffffffffffffffffffffffffffffffff Discussion Papers Candidate Quality Panu Poutvaara University of Helsinki and HECER Tuomas Takalo Bank of Finland Discussion Paper No.

More information

On Public Opinion Polls and Voters Turnout

On Public Opinion Polls and Voters Turnout On Public Opinion Polls and Voters Turnout Esteban F. Klor y and Eyal Winter z September 2006 We are grateful to Oriol Carbonell-Nicolau, Eric Gould, Dan Levin, Bradley Ru e and Moses Shayo for very helpful

More information

WORKING PAPER NO. 256 INFORMATION ACQUISITION AND DECISION MAKING IN COMMITTEES: A SURVEY

WORKING PAPER NO. 256 INFORMATION ACQUISITION AND DECISION MAKING IN COMMITTEES: A SURVEY EUROPEAN CENTRAL BANK WORKING PAPER SERIES E C B E Z B E K T B C E E K P WORKING PAPER NO. 256 INFORMATION ACQUISITION AND DECISION MAKING IN COMMITTEES: A SURVEY BY KERSTIN GERLING, HANS PETER GRÜNER,

More information

On Public Opinion Polls and Voters Turnout

On Public Opinion Polls and Voters Turnout On Public Opinion Polls and Voters Turnout Esteban F. Klor y and Eyal Winter z March 2014 We are grateful to Oriol Carbonell-Nicolau, Eric Gould, Dan Levin, Rebecca Morton, Bradley Ru e and Moses Shayo

More information

Extended Abstract: The Swing Voter s Curse in Social Networks

Extended Abstract: The Swing Voter s Curse in Social Networks Extended Abstract: The Swing Voter s Curse in Social Networks Berno Buechel & Lydia Mechtenberg January 20, 2015 Summary Consider a number of voters with common interests who, without knowing the true

More information

Compulsory versus Voluntary Voting Mechanisms: An Experimental Study

Compulsory versus Voluntary Voting Mechanisms: An Experimental Study Compulsory versus Voluntary Voting Mechanisms: An Experimental Study Sourav Bhattacharya John Duffy Sun-Tak Kim January 31, 2011 Abstract This paper uses laboratory experiments to study the impact of voting

More information

Let the Experts Decide? Asymmetric Information, Abstention, and Coordination in Standing Committees 1

Let the Experts Decide? Asymmetric Information, Abstention, and Coordination in Standing Committees 1 Let the Experts Decide? Asymmetric Information, Abstention, and Coordination in Standing Committees 1 Rebecca Morton 2 Jean-Robert Tyran 3 November 2, 2008 1 We appreciate greatly the work of Michael Rudy

More information

VOTING ON INCOME REDISTRIBUTION: HOW A LITTLE BIT OF ALTRUISM CREATES TRANSITIVITY DONALD WITTMAN ECONOMICS DEPARTMENT UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA

VOTING ON INCOME REDISTRIBUTION: HOW A LITTLE BIT OF ALTRUISM CREATES TRANSITIVITY DONALD WITTMAN ECONOMICS DEPARTMENT UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA 1 VOTING ON INCOME REDISTRIBUTION: HOW A LITTLE BIT OF ALTRUISM CREATES TRANSITIVITY DONALD WITTMAN ECONOMICS DEPARTMENT UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA SANTA CRUZ wittman@ucsc.edu ABSTRACT We consider an election

More information

Median voter theorem - continuous choice

Median voter theorem - continuous choice Median voter theorem - continuous choice In most economic applications voters are asked to make a non-discrete choice - e.g. choosing taxes. In these applications the condition of single-peakedness is

More information

Supporting Information Political Quid Pro Quo Agreements: An Experimental Study

Supporting Information Political Quid Pro Quo Agreements: An Experimental Study Supporting Information Political Quid Pro Quo Agreements: An Experimental Study Jens Großer Florida State University and IAS, Princeton Ernesto Reuben Columbia University and IZA Agnieszka Tymula New York

More information

Media Bias and Electoral Competition

Media Bias and Electoral Competition Media Bias and Electoral Competition Archishman Chakraborty y Parikshit Ghosh z November 010 Abstract We introduce mass media in a one-dimensional Downsian model of electoral competition in order to address

More information

THE EFFECT OF OFFER-OF-SETTLEMENT RULES ON THE TERMS OF SETTLEMENT

THE EFFECT OF OFFER-OF-SETTLEMENT RULES ON THE TERMS OF SETTLEMENT Last revision: 12/97 THE EFFECT OF OFFER-OF-SETTLEMENT RULES ON THE TERMS OF SETTLEMENT Lucian Arye Bebchuk * and Howard F. Chang ** * Professor of Law, Economics, and Finance, Harvard Law School. ** Professor

More information

THE POLITICS OF PUBLIC PROVISION OF EDUCATION 1. Gilat Levy

THE POLITICS OF PUBLIC PROVISION OF EDUCATION 1. Gilat Levy THE POLITICS OF PUBLIC PROVISION OF EDUCATION 1 Gilat Levy Public provision of education is usually viewed as a form of redistribution in kind. However, does it arise when income redistribution is feasible

More information

On the influence of extreme parties in electoral competition with policy-motivated candidates

On the influence of extreme parties in electoral competition with policy-motivated candidates University of Toulouse I From the SelectedWorks of Georges Casamatta October, 005 On the influence of extreme parties in electoral competition with policy-motivated candidates Georges Casamatta Philippe

More information

MULTIPLE VOTES, MULTIPLE CANDIDACIES AND POLARIZATION ARNAUD DELLIS

MULTIPLE VOTES, MULTIPLE CANDIDACIES AND POLARIZATION ARNAUD DELLIS MULTIPLE VOTES, MULTIPLE CANDIDACIES AND POLARIZATION ARNAUD DELLIS Université Laval and CIRPEE 105 Ave des Sciences Humaines, local 174, Québec (QC) G1V 0A6, Canada E-mail: arnaud.dellis@ecn.ulaval.ca

More information

Notes on Strategic and Sincere Voting

Notes on Strategic and Sincere Voting Notes on Strategic and Sincere Voting Francesco Trebbi March 8, 2019 Idea Kawai and Watanabe (AER 2013): Inferring Strategic Voting. They structurally estimate a model of strategic voting and quantify

More information

The Military, Wealth and Strategic Redistribution

The Military, Wealth and Strategic Redistribution The Military, Wealth and Strategic Redistribution Gabriel J. Leon London School of Economics Preliminary and Incomplete September 2007 Abstract Why do some developing world democracies redistribute too

More information

THE CITIZEN-CANDIDATE MODEL WITH IMPERFECT POLICY CONTROL

THE CITIZEN-CANDIDATE MODEL WITH IMPERFECT POLICY CONTROL Number 240 April 2015 THE CITIZEN-CANDIDATE MODEL WITH IMPERFECT POLICY CONTROL R. Emre Aytimur Aristotelis Boukouras Robert Schwager ISSN: 1439-2305 The Citizen-Candidate Model with Imperfect Policy Control

More information

Game theory and applications: Lecture 12

Game theory and applications: Lecture 12 Game theory and applications: Lecture 12 Adam Szeidl December 6, 2018 Outline for today 1 A political theory of populism 2 Game theory in economics 1 / 12 1. A Political Theory of Populism Acemoglu, Egorov

More information

Rent seekers in rentier states: When greed brings peace

Rent seekers in rentier states: When greed brings peace Rent seekers in rentier states: When greed brings peace Kjetil Bjorvatn y, Alireza Naghavi z December 2, 2009 Abstract Are natural resources a source of con ict or stability? Empirical studies demonstrate

More information

Nominations for Sale. Silvia Console-Battilana and Kenneth A. Shepsle y. 1 Introduction

Nominations for Sale. Silvia Console-Battilana and Kenneth A. Shepsle y. 1 Introduction Nominations for Sale Silvia Console-Battilana and Kenneth A. Shepsle y Abstract Models of nomination politics in the US often nd "gridlock" in equilibrium because of the super-majority requirement in the

More information

Comparative Politics with Endogenous Intra-Party Discipline 1

Comparative Politics with Endogenous Intra-Party Discipline 1 Comparative Politics with Endogenous Intra-Party Discipline 1 July 2009 Comments welcome. Micael Castanheira ECARES, Université Libre de Bruxelles and Benoit S Y Crutzen Erasmus Universiteit Rotterdam

More information

An Overview Across the New Political Economy Literature. Abstract

An Overview Across the New Political Economy Literature. Abstract An Overview Across the New Political Economy Literature Luca Murrau Ministry of Economy and Finance - Rome Abstract This work presents a review of the literature on political process formation and the

More information

Abstract This paper presents a positive theory of centralization of political decisions in an international union. My central claim is that lobbies

Abstract This paper presents a positive theory of centralization of political decisions in an international union. My central claim is that lobbies EUROPEAN CENTRAL BANK WORKING PAPER SERIES WORKING PAPER NO 220 THE ALLOCATION OF COMPETENCIES IN AN INTERNATIONAL UNION: A POSITIVE ANALYSIS BY MICHELE RUTA April 2003 EUROPEAN CENTRAL BANK WORKING PAPER

More information

Disasters and Incumbent Electoral Fortunes: No Implications for Democratic Competence

Disasters and Incumbent Electoral Fortunes: No Implications for Democratic Competence Disasters and Incumbent Electoral Fortunes: No Implications for Democratic Competence Scott Ashworth Ethan Bueno de Mesquita February 1, 2013 Abstract A recent empirical literature shows that incumbent

More information

E ciency, Equity, and Timing of Voting Mechanisms 1

E ciency, Equity, and Timing of Voting Mechanisms 1 E ciency, Equity, and Timing of Voting Mechanisms 1 Marco Battaglini Princeton University Rebecca Morton New York University Thomas Palfrey California Institute of Technology This version November 29,

More information

Document de treball de l IEB 2009/30

Document de treball de l IEB 2009/30 Document de treball de l IEB 2009/30 SUGGESTING AN ALTENATIVE ELECTOAL POPOTIONAL SYSTEM. BLANK VOTES COUNT Orestis Troumpounis Fiscal Federalism Documents de Treball de l IEB 2009/30 SUGGESTING AN ALTENATIVE

More information