Veto Players, Policy Change and Institutional Design. Tiberiu Dragu and Hannah K. Simpson New York University

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Veto Players, Policy Change and Institutional Design. Tiberiu Dragu and Hannah K. Simpson New York University"

Transcription

1 Veto Players, Policy Change and Institutional Design Tiberiu Dragu and Hannah K. Simpson New York University December 2016

2 Abstract What institutional arrangements allow veto players to secure maximal welfare when they all agree on the need for and direction of policy change? To answer this question, we conduct a mechanism design analysis. We focus on a system with two veto players, each with incomplete information about the other s policy preferences. We show that the unique welfare-optimizing mechanism is the mechanism that implements the preferred policy of the player whose ideal policy is closer to the status quo. We provide examples of institutional structures under which the unique equilibrium outcome of this two-player incomplete information game is the policy outcome implemented by this mechanism, and argue that our result can be used as a normative benchmark to assess the optimality of veto player institutions. Keywords: veto players; veto bargaining; mechanism design; institutional design

3 Veto players are a common feature of democracies. Generally, veto player institutions are studied in the context of their role in maintaining policy stability: increasing the number of veto players in a political system is thought to weakly increase policy stability because any one veto player with opposing preferences can block policy change (Tsebelis 2002). There is thus an extensive scholarship on the optimal number of veto institutions under different political and economic conditions: for example, more veto players may impede government adaptability to changing economic circumstances when society is divided (Cox and McCubbins 2001), but may facilitate policy change if special interests are weak (Gelbach and Malesky 2010) or (in the case of unanimity vs. majority voting rules) when there is no external policy enforcement mechanism (Maggi and Morelli 2006). Our paper asks a different question: what institutional arrangements allow veto players to secure maximal attainment of their welfare under circumstances where all veto players agree on the need for and direction of policy change? Often, shocks to the state of the world, like terrorist attacks or natural disasters, can shift all veto players preferences in the same direction, e.g., towards increasing security spending or disaster relief. In such cases, all veto players would have a common interest in changing the status quo, but their preferences might diverge regarding which policy reform is desirable. Under these circumstances, the institutional arrangement that structures the players interactions will affect the policy outcome, with important implications for the players welfare. To answer this question, we conduct a mechanism design analysis. A mechanism, for our purposes, is an institution that governs the process by which veto players decide on policy changes. We focus on a system with two veto players, each with incomplete information about the other s policy preferences. Our main result is that the mechanism that yields the best (expected) payoff to each player in such a setting is the mechanism that implements the preferred policy of the player whose ideal policy is closer to the status quo. We provide examples of institutional structures (formalized as non-cooperative games) under which the unique equilibrium outcome of this two-player incomplete information game is the policy 1

4 outcome implemented by this mechanism. We also discuss the usefulness of our analysis as a normative benchmark to assess a variety of veto player institutions: those institutions that yield a result other than the players less-extreme preferred policy are inefficient from a welfare perspective. Our analysis contributes to scholarship on veto players (Tsebelis 2002; Cox and McCubbins 2001; Gelbach and Malesky 2010) and veto bargaining (Romer and Rosenthal 1978; Bueno de Mesquita and Stephenson 2007; Fox and Van Weelden 2010; Fox and Stephenson 2011; Callander and Krehbiel 2014; Dragu and Board 2015). There is an extensive literature on the policy and welfare implications of various political-institutional structures under which multiple players must agree to effect policy change (e.g., Matthews 1989; Cameron 2000; Cameron and McCarthy 2004; Crombez et al. 2006). The general method of assessing the welfare implications of these institutions has been the following: formalize different institutions (usually two or three) as non-cooperative games, derive their equilibrium outcome(s) and then assess the players equilibrium payoffs under each of these games to determine which of these institutional arrangements leads to a higher payoff for players (for a description of this method, see Diermeier and Krehbiel 2003). Mechanism design analysis is an important next step in this theoretical literature because it facilitates the assessment of the welfare properties of all veto bargaining institutions. In other words, using mechanism design allows us to conduct a comprehensive evaluation of all possible institutional arrangements that could structure how veto players interact. This implies that the results of our analysis can serve as a normative benchmark by which to assess the optimality of veto bargaining models, regardless of their specific institutional characteristics. Our research also contributes to a literature that applies mechanism design to the study of political institutions and settings (Banks 1990; Baron 2000; Gailmard 2009; Dragu, Fan and Kuklinski 2014; Hörner et al. 2015, among others). 1 In related work, Dragu, Fan and Kuklinski (2014) have shown that the unique mechanism that satisfies certain procedural 1 This research note is also related to a literature that investigates the properties of strategy-proof social choice functions on single peaked domains (e.g. Moulin 1981; Penn Patty, and Gailmard 2011). 2

5 properties (i.e. individual rationality constraints, strategy proofness, and Pareto efficiency) is the mechanism that implements the ideal policy of the player preferring the less aggressive change from the policy status-quo. This research note focuses on a different normative criterion (which mechanism maximizes each player s expected payoff) to show that the unique welfare-maximizing mechanism is also the mechanism that implements the preferred policy of the player whose ideal policy is the closest to the status quo. The Model There are two veto players A and B. The players have preferences over a one-dimensional policy space. An exogenous status-quo q is in place. Without loss of generality, we fix the status-quo at q = 0. Each player s preference is represented by a twice continuously differentiable, single-peaked and symmetric (about an ideal position a and b respectively) and (weakly) concave utility function U i ( ) for i {A, B}. The players policy preferences are private information. Let a and b, the ideal positions of A and B, be independently distributed according to uniform distributions on [0, L A ] and [0, L B ], respectively. As mentioned, we focus our analysis on the scenario in which players agree on the direction of policy change, i.e., a, b 0, 2 because only in this setting does the resulting outcome depend on the institutional arrangement within which the players interact. That is, when players disagree about the direction of policy change (i.e., a < 0 < b or b < 0 < a), the outcome will be the status-quo policy regardless of the institutional arrangement within which the players interact, since this is the only outcome that satisfies the veto condition. A mechanism can be understood as the institution that governs the process by which the two veto players make a collective policy choice. Formally, a mechanism Γ = {S A, S B ; p( )} specifies the set of strategies available to each player, and a rule p(s A, s B ) that stipulates the policy outcome implemented by the mechanism for a given strategy profile s = (s A, s B ). Notice that a mechanism could, in principle, be a complex dynamic procedure, in which case 2 The scenario in which a, b < 0 is similar. 3

6 the elements of the strategy S i for {A, B} would consist of contingent plans of actions and messages. Notice also that a mechanism Γ, together with the players utility functions and beliefs about their preferred policy, induces a game of incomplete information. To illustrate, consider the following two examples of mechanisms that could structure the interaction of two veto players. First, suppose the players operate within a no communication agenda-setting mechanism in which player A proposes a policy x R +, after which player B decides to accept or veto x. The policy outcome is x if player B accepts player A s policy proposal and q = 0 if player B vetoes A s proposal. Here, player A s strategy is a policy proposal s A = x, and player B s strategy is a binary decision d(x) {yes, no} for every proposal of player A. The rule function that stipulates the outcome under this mechanism is p(x, d(x)) = x if d = yes and p(x, d) = 0 if d = no. Notice that in this mechanism there is no communication between the players regarding their preferred policies, which implies that player A s belief about player B s preferred policy when player A chooses x is the same as her prior (i.e b U[0, L B ]). Now suppose the players operate within a communication agenda-setting mechanism in which player B first sends a message m [0, L B ] about its preferred policy; next, player A observes the message and makes a policy proposal x R + ; and finally, player B accepts or vetoes x. In this mechanism, the strategy of player A is a policy choice as a function of the message player B sends, s A = x(m) R, and the strategy of player B is a message m and a binary decision d(x) {yes, no}. The rule function that stipulates the outcome under this mechanism is p(x(m); (m, d(x))) = x if d(x) = yes and p(x(m); (m, d(x))) = 0 if d(x) = no. In a similar vein, we can construct other mechanisms by permitting different communication protocols and/or by extending the timing of the interaction; in fact, there are infinitely many ways to specify the mechanism under which the two veto players interact, simply by varying the timing of the interaction, the policy proposals, and the messages each player can send. Our goal is to determine the optimal mechanism, by which we mean the mechanism that, among all possible mechanisms, maximizes the expected (interim) payoff of the two veto 4

7 players. This task would be difficult, if not impossible, to achieve via the standard approach to comparative institutional analysis: modeling each institution as a non-cooperative game, solving for the equilibrium policy outcome generated under each, and then comparing the expected equilibrium payoff for each player under the different institutional arrangements. Going back to the previous examples, for instance, one would solve for the equilibrium outcome under the no communication and communication agenda-setting mechanisms, and then compare the players equilibrium expected payoffs to asses which of the two mechanisms is better from this welfare perspective. While this technique is valuable, it doesn t allows us to conduct a comprehensive evaluation of all possible institutional arrangements that could structure how veto players interact. Instead, we employ a mechanism design approach and exploit the revelation principle. The revelation principle states that, for any equilibrium of a game of incomplete information that is induced by some mechanism under which the players interact, there exists an incentive-compatible direct revelation mechanism that is payoff-equivalent with that equilibrium (Myerson 1979). This implies that it is sufficient to find the optimal mechanism among the set of incentive compatible direct revelation mechanisms in order to determine which is the optimal mechanism among all possible mechanisms that could structure the players interaction. In a direct revelation mechanism, D = {S A, S B ; p( )}, the (message) strategy spaces are precisely the type spaces, i.e S i = [0, L i ], and a policy outcome results as a function of the reported types. One way of thinking about this is that instead of considering all possible institutional arrangements under which the players could interact, we need only study a simple setting: the set of mechanisms in which the players actions are to report their types and an outcome, p(a, b), results as a function of the players (true) types. In other words, an incentive compatible direct mechanism p(a, b) specifies a policy outcome p R as a function of A s and B s true types. To identify the optimal mechanism, we need only find the optimal mechanism from the set of direct revelation mechanisms subject to incentive compatibility constraints which ensure that the veto players have incentives to 5

8 truthfully reveal their types. In this context, the incentive compatibility constraints are as follows: Incentive Compatibility: A mechanism p(a, b) is dominant-strategy incentive compatible if and only if U A (p(a, b), a) U A (p(ã, b), a) and U B (p(a, b), b) U B (p(a, b), b), for all a,b, ã and b. This incentive compatibility condition requires that truthful revelation is an equilibrium in (weakly) dominant strategies in the game of incomplete information induced by the direct mechanism p(a, b). 3 To illustrate what the incentive compatibility condition entails, consider the following dominant-strategy incentive-compatible mechanisms. p(a, b) = max{a, b} are both incentive-compatible. The mechanisms p(a, b) = 0 and The second mechanism is incentivecompatible because, for each player, the outcome is either its own ideal policy or some policy higher than its ideal policy; in the former case, a player has no incentive to deviate and, in the latter case, the only way to change the outcome is to announce and implement an even higher policy, which would make the player worse off. The first policy mechanism is trivially dominant-strategy incentive-compatible. The outcome is the status quo, q = 0, regardless of what the players are doing; therefore, the players do not have an incentive to misreport their preferences. Note that dominant-strategy incentive-compatible mechanisms can be complicated in the sense that, in some intervals, a player s ideal policy is implemented and in other intervals a constant policy is implemented. Consider also the following examples of a mechanism that violates incentive compatibility. The mechanism p(a, b) = a+b 2 is not dominant-strategy incentive-compatible, as the players have clear incentives to misreport their preferred policy so as to induce an outcome that 3 Notice that the incentive compatible direct mechanisms are required to operate on the basis of veto players ideal points alone. In principle, these mechanisms could take into account all aspects of players preferences, however, the existing literature has shown that allowing for the use of additional information (in settings in which agents have single-peaked preferences over a one-dimensional policy space) does not enlarge the set of dominant strategy incentive compatible mechanisms (Barbera and Jackson 1994); thus our restriction is without loss of generality. 6

9 is closer to their most preferred policy outcome. For example, let a = 1 and b = 11. The outcome under this mechanism is p(a, b) = 6; player B has incentives to misreport its preferred policy to b = 21 so to change the outcome to p(a, b ) = 11, player B s ideal policy. Since each player can veto changes to the status-quo policy, players utility from the policy outcome resulting under an incentive-compatible mechanism p(a, b) must be at least as high as their payoffs from the status-quo. This gives rise to the following veto requirement: Veto Constraints: A policy mechanism p(a, b) satisfies the veto constraints if and only if U A (p(a, b), a) U A (0, a) and U B (p(a, b), b) U A (0, b) for all a and b. To illustrate what the veto requirement entails, consider the following mechanisms. First, the mechanism p(a, b) = 0 satisfies the veto condition since the outcome under this policy mechanism is always the status-quo policy. On the other hand, the mechanism p(a, b) = max{a, b} doesn t satisfy the veto requirement. To see this, let a = 1 and b = 10, which implies that the outcome of this mechanism is p(a, b) = 10. However, player A is better off with the status-quo policy than with the policy p(a, b) = 10; therefore, the veto constraint is not met. Analysis Given the mechanism design problem formulated previously, the mechanism p(a, b) that maximizes player A s expected payoff for any type a 0 [0, L A ] is the solution to the following maximization problem: LB max U A (p(a 0, b), a 0 )f B (b)db, p(a,b) 0 subject to the incentive compatibility constraints U A (p(a, b), a) U A (p(ã, b), a), a, ã, b, 7

10 U B (p(a, b), b) U B (p(a, b), b), b, b, a, and the veto constraints U A (p(a, b), a) U A (0, a), a, b, U B (p(a, b), b) U B (0, b), a, b. The maximization problem for player B is defined in an analogous manner. 4 Finding the optimal incentive-compatible mechanism for player B) (and A) that satisfies the veto conditions is a somewhat technical problem. We relegate the details of the proof to the appendix and state the main result below: Proposition. The unique incentive-compatible policy mechanism that satisfies the veto constraints and maximizes player i s expected (interim) payoff is p(a, b) = min{a, b} for i {A, B}. The proposition suggests that player i s optimal mechanism is p(a, b) = min{a, b} for i {A, B}. This result implies that, for example, even if player A s preferred policy is a further departure from the status-quo than player B, the mechanism that maximizes player A s expected (interim) payoff is the one that implements the ideal policy of player B. To provide some intuition for this result, let b [0, a] and let us compare player A s expected payoff under the mechanism p(a, b) = b for b [0, a] with player A s expected payoff under the mechanism p(a, b) = a for b [ a, a] and p(a, b) = 0 for b [0, a ]. Notice that, given that 2 2 player A is uncertain about player B s ideal policy, the outcome is b for any b [0, a] in the former mechanism while the outcome is 0 with probability 1/2 and a with probability 1/2 in the latter mechanism. Now consider the expected payoff of player A under two distributions: one in which the outcome is b for b [0, a] and one for which the outcome is 0 if b [0, a ] and a if 2 4 Notice that we are looking for the mechanism that maximizes player i s expected (interim) payoff given that player i knows her type but is uncertain about the other player s ideal policy for i {A, B}. 8

11 b [ a, a], given that b U[0, a]. The two distributions have the same mean a, but the second 2 2 distribution has a bigger variance. Thus the first distribution second-order stochastically dominates the second, and, because the players have weakly concave preferences, player A is better off under the first distribution. As a result, player A s expected payoff is better under the mechanism p(a, b) = b for b [0, a] than under the mechanism p(a, b) = a for b [ a 2, a] and p(a, b) = 0 for b [0, a 2 ].5 The previous example compares two mechanisms to illustrate the intuition of the proposition. But the proposition is more encompassing: it states that, for all possible institutional arrangements (i.e., mechanisms) within which the two veto players could interact, the institution where p(a, b) = min{a, b} is the unique equilibrium outcome that provides both players their best expected equilibrium payoff. In other words, the institution under which p(a, b) = min{a, b} for all a, b 0 is the unique equilibrium outcome is the optimal institutional arrangement among all possible institutions that could structure the interaction between the two veto players. Figure 1 illustrates A s optimal policy outcome as a function of all possible locations of B s preferred policy. The variable on the horizontal axis is B s preferred policy b, while the variable on the vertical axis A s optimal outcome p(a, b). Notice that this proposition can be used as a normative benchmark to assess various veto player institutions. In principle, we can take any institutional setting under which two veto players interact, formalize that institution as a game, and then analyze its equilibrium outcomes. If the equilibrium of that game is p(a, b) = min{a, b} for all a, b 0, then that institution maximizes each player s expected utility. In contrast, if the equilibrium outcome is not p(a, b) = min{a, b} for all a, b 0, then the players do not secure maximal attainment of their payoffs under that institution. For example, the no communication agenda-setting institution previously discussed is not welfare-optimal since there are conditions under which the equilibrium outcome of that game is the status-quo policy, although both players would 5 The same rationale applies when comparing the mechanism p(a, b) = b for b [0, t] with the mechanism p(a, b) = t for b [ t 2, t] and p(a, b) = 0 for b [0, t 2 ] where t [0, a]. 9

12 p(a, b) a a b Figure 1: A s optimal mechanism as a function of the B s ideal policy (for a fixed a). prefer some policy change (i.e. there is a positive equilibrium probability that player B rejects player A s policy proposal p and therefore the equilibrium outcome is the status-quo policy for some a, b > 0). It is also of interest to establish whether the outcome induced by the optimal mechanism can be obtained as the unique equilibrium outcome under some well specified non-cooperative game. In the remainder of this note, we show this by setting out two simple games of incomplete information, one simultaneous and one sequential, each of which generates outcome induced by the optimal mechanism as the unique equilibrium. First, consider the following simultaneous game in which a player i s action space is a policy demand x i [0, L i ] for i {A, B}. The timing of the game is the following 10

13 The players simultaneously make a policy demand x i [0, L i ] for i {A, B}. The policy outcome is min{x A, x B }. Given this game, each player has a (weakly) dominant strategy to demand its ideal policy, i.e. x A = a and x B = b, which implies that the unique equilibrium of this game is p(a, b) = min{a, b} for any a and b. To show this, we show that, for any choice x B, the unique optimal strategy of player B is x A = a. If player A were to choose some policy x A < a, then such a choice either makes no difference for the outcome or can result in a worse outcome for player A (a choice of x A < a makes no difference to the outcome if x B < a and results in a worse outcome for player A if a < x B ). Similarly, if player A were to choose some policy x A > a, then such a choice either makes no difference for the outcome or can result in a worse outcome for player A (a choice of x A > a makes no difference to the outcome if x B < a and results in a worse outcome for player A if a < x B ). Therefore, player A has a dominant strategy to choose x A = a. By a similar reasoning, player B has a dominant strategy to choose x B = b. Second, consider the following sequential game in which player A chooses a policy bound l and then player B chooses a policy x R. The timing of the game is the following: Player A chooses a policy bound l. Player B chooses a policy x R. The outcome of the game is x if x l and q = 0 if x > l. We show that the unique equilibrium outcome of this game is min{a, b}. We prove this by backward induction. In the second stage, player B s beliefs about player A s type after each observed policy bound are irrelevant because they do not affect player B s payoff. That is, if player A s choice in the first stage is l, the unique optimal strategy for player B is x = min{b, l} for any strategy of player A, and any beliefs of player B. To see this, let l be some policy bound chosen by player A in the first stage. After player B observes player A s 11

14 choice, player B can either choose a policy x l and the resulting outcome is x; or player B can choose a policy x > l and the resulting outcome is q = 0. Since U B ( ) is single-peaked, player B s optimal strategy is b if b l and l if b > l. Therefore, player b s unique optimal strategy is x = min{g, l}. Given that the unique optimal strategy for player B is x = min{g, l} for any l, we next prove that, in the first stage, player A s optimal strategy is l = a. If player A were to choose some l < a, then for all b l, player A receives the same payoff; for all b (l, a], player A is worse off because the outcome is b if it chooses a and l < b a if it chooses l ; and for all b > a, player A is worse off because the outcome is a if it chooses a and l < a if it chooses l. And if player A were to choose some l > a, then for all b a, player A receives the same payoff; for all b > a, player A is worse off because the outcome is b if b [a, l ] or l if b > l. Thus player A s optimal decision is l = a. As a result, the unique equilibrium outcome of this game is min{a, b} for any a, b 0, as claimed. Conclusion In this paper, we conduct a mechanism design analysis to determine how, under circumstances where all veto players agree on the direction of policy change but may diverge on the optimal amount, veto player institutions can be designed to facilitate the implementation of policy that maximizes the players expected payoff. We focus on a system with two veto players, each with incomplete information about the other s policy preferences. We show that the welfare-optimizing mechanism is the mechanism that implements the preferred policy of the player whose ideal policy is closer to the status quo. We provide examples of institutional structures under which the unique equilibrium outcome of this two-player incomplete information game is the policy outcome implemented by this mechanism, and argue that our result can be used as a normative benchmark to assess the optimality of veto player institutions. 12

15 References [1] Banks, Jeffrey Equilibrium Behavior in Crisis Bargaining Games. American Journal of Political Science 34 (3): [2] Barbera, Salvador, and Matthew Jackson A characterization of strategy-proof social choice functions for economies with pure public goods. Social Choice and Welfare 11 (3): [3] Baron, David Legislative Organization with Information Committees. American Journal of Political Science 44 (3): [4] Bueno de Mesquita, Ethan and Matthew C. Stephenson Regulatory quality under imperfect oversight. American Political Science Review 101 (3): [5] Callander, Steven, and Keith Krehbiel Gridlock and delegation in a changing world. American Journal of Political Science 58 (4): [6] Cameron, Charles. M Veto Bargaining: Presidents and the Politics of Negative Power. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press. [7] Cameron, Charles. M. and Nolan McCarty Models of Vetoes and Veto Bargaining. Annual Review of Political Science 7: [8] Cox, G. W. and M. McCubbins The Institutional Determinants of Economic Policy Outcomes, in Presidents, Parliaments and Policy, eds. Stephan Haggard and Mathew McCubbins. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, pp [9] Crombez, Christophe, Tim Groseclose, and Keith Krehbiel Gatekeeping. Journal of Politics 68 (2): [10] Diermeier, Daniel, and Keith Krehbiel Institutionalism as a Methodology. Journal of Theoretical Politics 15 (2): [11] Dragu, Tiberiu, Xiaochen Fan and James Kuklinski Designing Checks and Balances, Quarterly Journal of Political Science 9 (1):

16 [12] Dragu, Tiberiu, and Oliver Board On judicial review in a separation of powers system. Political Science Research and Methods 3 (3): [13] Fox, Justin, and Richard Van Weelden Partisanship and the Effectiveness of Oversight. Journal of Public Economics 94 (9): [14] Fox, Justin and Matthew Stephenson Judicial Review as a Response to Political Posturing. American Political Science Review 105 (2): 397. [15] Gailmard, Sean Multiple principals and oversight of bureaucratic policymaking. Journal of Theoretical Politics 21 (2): [16] Gehlbach, Scott and Edmund J. Malesky The contribution of veto players to economic reform. The Journal of Politics 72 (4): [17] Hörner, Johannes, Massimo Morelli, and Francesco Squintani Mediation and peace. The Review of Economic Studies 82 (4): [18] Maggi, Giovanni, and Massimo Morelli Self-enforcing voting in international organizations. The American Economic Review 96 (4): [19] Matthews, S. A Veto Threats: Rhetoric in a Bargaining Game. Quarterly Journal of Economics 104 (2): [20] McCarty, Nolan Presidential Reputation and the Veto. Economics and Politics 9 (1): 1-27 [21] Moulin, Herve On strategy-proofness and single peakedness. Public Choice 35 (4): [22] Myerson, Roger B Incentive Compatibility and the Bargaining Problem. Econometrica 47 (1): [23] Penn, Elizabeth Maggie, John W. Patty, and Sean Gailmard Manipulation and Single-Peakedness: A General Result. American Journal of Political Science 55 (2):

17 [24] Romer, Thomas and Howard Rosenthal Political Resource Allocation, Controlled Agendas, and the Status Quo. Public Choice 33: [25] Tsebelis, George. Veto players: How political institutions work. Princeton University Press,

18 Online Appendix Before proceeding to prove the main proposition, we use the following lemmas 1 4 that describe some properties of dominant strategy incentive compatible mechanisms in this setting, properties that are useful to prove our main result (for proofs of these lemma, see Dragu, Fan and Kuklinski (2014)). Lemma 1. For any b, any mechanism p(a, b) that is dominant strategy incentive compatible for player A is weakly increasing in a; if p(a, b) is strictly increasing in a on an open interval (a 1, a 2 ), then p(a, b) = a on (a 1, a 2 ). For any a, any mechanism p(a, b) that is dominant strategy incentive compatible for player B is weakly increasing in b; if p(a, b) is strictly increasing in b on an open interval (b 1, b 2 ), then p(a, b) = b on (b 1, b 2 ). Lemma 2. Let p(a, b) be a dominant strategy incentive compatible mechanism. Then for any b, if p(a, b) = a on (a 1, a 2 ), then p(a, b) is continuous at both a 1 and a 2. Similarly, for any a, if p(a, b) = b on (b 1, b 2 ), then p(a, b) is continuous at both b 1 and b 2. Lemma 3. Let p(a, b) be a dominant strategy incentive compatible mechanism. Then for any b, if â is a discontinuity point of p(a, b), then â lim a â p(a, b) > 0 and lim a â +p(a, b) â > 0. Similarly, for any a, if ˆb is a discontinuity point of p(a, b), then ˆb lim b ˆb p(a, b) > 0 and lim b ˆb+p(a, b) ˆb > 0. Lemma 4. Let p(a, b) be a dominant strategy incentive compatible mechanism. Then for any b, if for some â, p(â, b) = c â, then p(a, b) = c for all a (min{c, â}, max{c, â}). Similarly, for any a, if for some ˆb, p(a, ˆb) = c ˆb, then p(a, b) = c for all b (min{c, ˆb}, max{c, ˆb}). Proof of Proposition. First, it s easy to see that p(a, b) = min{a, b} is a dominant strategy incentive compatible mechanism. For example, if player A were to report some â > a, then player A s payoff is either unchanged (if b a) or lower if (b > a). A similar reasoning 16

19 applies to why player B does not have an incentive to misreport its type if the outcome is p(a, b) = min{a, b}. Next we show that p(a, b) = min{a, b} is the unique mechanism that maximizes player A s expected (interim) payoff (among all dominant strategy incentive compatible mechanisms that satisfy the veto constraints). That is, we show that for any a 0 [0, L A ], p(a, b) = min{a, b} solves the following maximization problem subject to the incentive compatibility constraints LB max U A (p(a 0, b), a 0 )f B (b)db, (1) p(a,b) 0 U A (p(a, b), a) U A (p(ã, b), a), a, ã, b, U B (p(a, b), b) U B (p(a, b), b), b, b, a, and the veto constraints U A (p(a, b), a) U A (0, a), a, b, U B (p(a, b), b) U G (0, b) a, b. To show that p(a, b) = min{a, b} is the solution of (1), it suffices to show that p(a 0, b) = min{a 0, b} solves the following maximization problem LB max U A (p(a 0, b), a 0 )f B (b)db, (2) p(a 0,b) 0 subject to incentive compatibility and veto constraints of B when A is at a 0 U B (p(a 0, b), b) U B (p(a 0, b), b), b, b U B (p(a 0, b), b) U B (0, b), b. 17

20 Note that the second problem maximizes the same objective function from a larger pool of mechanisms than the first problem. As a result, if p(a 0, b) = min{a 0, b} is the solution to the second problem, (2), then p(a, b) = min{a, b} for all a and b, which satisfies all the constraints of the first problem, is the solution to the first problem, (1). Therefore, denote the solution to (2) by p (a 0, b), it suffices to show that p (a 0, b) = min{a 0, b}. First, we show that p (a 0, b) is continuous in b. Suppose p (a 0, b) is not continuous in b, and let ˆb be a discontinuity point of p (a 0, b). By Lemma 3, ˆb lim b ˆb p (a 0, b) > 0 and lim b ˆb+p (a 0, b) ˆb > 0. Since U B ( ) is symmetric, we have ˆb lim b ˆb p (a 0, b) = lim b ˆb+p (a 0, b) ˆb. We prove this last statement by contradiction. Suppose that ˆb lim b ˆb p (a 0, b) lim b ˆb+p (a 0, b) ˆb, and, with loss of generality, suppose that ˆb lim b ˆb p (a 0, b) > lim b ˆb+p (a 0, b) ˆb(> 0). By Lemma 1 and Lemma 2, any discontinuity point must be one that connects two flat segments. As a result, there exists ɛ > 0 such that p (a 0, ˆb ɛ) = lim b ˆb p (a 0, b) and p (a 0, ˆb + ɛ) = lim b ˆb+p (a 0, b). Since (ˆb ɛ) p (a 0, ĉ ɛ) > p (a 0, ˆb + ɛ) (ˆb ɛ), player B type ˆb ɛ has an incentive to misreport its type as ˆb + ɛ and thus p (a 0, b) violates the incentive compatibility constraint for b = ˆb ɛ. Denote m lim b ˆb p (a 0, b) and n lim b ˆb+p (a 0, b), from the above we have ˆb m = n ˆb > 0, that is ˆb = m+n 2. By Lemma 4, p (a 0, b) = m for all b [m, m+n 2 ), and p (a 0, b) = n for all b ( m+n 2, n]. Now consider p (a 0, b) such that p (a 0, b) = b for b [m, n] and p (a 0, b) = p (a 0, b) for all other b. Since p (a 0, b) satisfies the incentive compatibility and veto constraints for all b, it is easy to check that p (a 0, b) also satisfies the incentive compatibility and veto constraints for all b. We now show that p (a 0, b) yields a higher expected payoff for player A than p (a 0, b). Since p (a 0, b) and p (a 0, b) differ only on [m, n], it is sufficient to show that n U m A(a 0, b)f B (b)db > m+n 2 U m A (a 0, m)f B (b)db + b m+n U A (a 0, b)f B (b)db. The outcome of the 2 left hand side is a random variable, denoted by p, which is uniformly distributed on [m, n]; 18

21 while the outcome of the right hand side is a random variable, denoted by y, such that y = m with probability 1 and y = n with probability 1 m+n. We have Ep = Ey = ; Varp = (n m)2 ; and Vary = 1 m+n (m ) m+n (n ) 2 = (n m)2. Since Ep = Ey and Varp < Vary, y is a mean-preserving spread of p. Since U A (a 0, ) is (weakly) concave, player A prefers p to y, that is, the left hand side is greater than the right hand side, a contradiction to p (a 0, b) being the solution to (2). Therefore, the solution p (a 0, b) is continuous in b. The veto constraint at b = 0 requires that p (a 0, 0) = 0. This together with Lemma 1 and the continuity of p (a 0, b) imply that p (a 0, b) can only take the following form: for some t [0, L B ], p (a 0, b) = b for b [0, t] and p (a 0, b) = t for b > t. As a result, p (a 0, b) is equivalent to the solution to the following problem. LB t max t [0,L B ] t 0 U A (a 0, b)f B (b)db + LB t U A (a 0, t)f B (b)db (3) We claim the solution to (3) is t = a 0. To see this, denote Φ(t) t 0 U A(a 0, b)f B (b)db + U A (a 0, t)f B (b)db. For any t < a 0, Φ(a 0 ) = t U 0 A(a 0, b)f B (b)db+ a 0 U t A (a 0, b)f B (b)db+ L B a 0 U A (a 0, a 0 )f B (b)db, and Φ(t) = t U 0 A(a 0, b)f B (b)db+ a 0 t a0 t U A (a 0, t)f B (b)db+ L B a 0 U A (a 0, t)f B (b)db. Φ(a 0 ) Φ(t) = [U A (a 0, b) U A (a 0, t)]f B (b)db+ L B a 0 [U A (a 0, a 0 ) U A (a 0, t)]f B (b)db > 0, because U A (a 0, b) U A (a 0, t) > 0 for any b (t, a 0 ) due to single-peakedness of U A (a 0, ), and U A (a 0, a 0 ) U a (a 0, t) > 0 since a 0 is the peak of U A (a 0, ). For any t > a 0, Φ(a 0 ) = a 0 U 0 A (a 0, b)f B (b)db+ t a 0 U A (a 0, a 0 )f B (b)db+ L B U t A (a 0, a 0 )f B (b)db, and Φ(t) = a 0 0 U A (a 0, b)f B (b)db + t a 0 U A (a 0, b)f B (b)db + L B t U A (a 0, t)f B (b)db. Φ(a 0 ) Φ(t) = t a 0 [U A (a 0, a 0 ) U A (a 0, b)]f B (b)db + L B [U t A (a 0, a 0 ) U A (a 0, t)]f B (b)db > 0, because U A (a 0, a 0 ) U A (a 0, b) > 0 and U A (a 0, a 0 ) U A (a 0, t) > 0 since a 0 is the peak of U A (a 0, ). Therefore, Φ(a 0 ) > Φ(t) for any t a 0, and therefore t = a 0. That is, p (a 0, b) = b for 19

22 c [0, a 0 ] and p (a 0, b) = a 0 for b > a 0, which implies that p (a 0, b) = min{b, a 0 }. The proof for p(a, b) = min{a, b} being also the unique mechanism that maximizes the player B s expected payoff (among all dominant strategy incentive compatible mechanisms that satisfy the veto constraints) is analogous. 20

1 Electoral Competition under Certainty

1 Electoral Competition under Certainty 1 Electoral Competition under Certainty We begin with models of electoral competition. This chapter explores electoral competition when voting behavior is deterministic; the following chapter considers

More information

Enriqueta Aragones Harvard University and Universitat Pompeu Fabra Andrew Postlewaite University of Pennsylvania. March 9, 2000

Enriqueta Aragones Harvard University and Universitat Pompeu Fabra Andrew Postlewaite University of Pennsylvania. March 9, 2000 Campaign Rhetoric: a model of reputation Enriqueta Aragones Harvard University and Universitat Pompeu Fabra Andrew Postlewaite University of Pennsylvania March 9, 2000 Abstract We develop a model of infinitely

More information

The Role of the Trade Policy Committee in EU Trade Policy: A Political-Economic Analysis

The Role of the Trade Policy Committee in EU Trade Policy: A Political-Economic Analysis The Role of the Trade Policy Committee in EU Trade Policy: A Political-Economic Analysis Wim Van Gestel, Christophe Crombez January 18, 2011 Abstract This paper presents a political-economic analysis of

More information

Supporting Information for Competing Gridlock Models and Status Quo Policies

Supporting Information for Competing Gridlock Models and Status Quo Policies for Competing Gridlock Models and Status Quo Policies Jonathan Woon University of Pittsburgh Ian P. Cook University of Pittsburgh January 15, 2015 Extended Discussion of Competing Models Spatial models

More information

Rhetoric in Legislative Bargaining with Asymmetric Information 1

Rhetoric in Legislative Bargaining with Asymmetric Information 1 Rhetoric in Legislative Bargaining with Asymmetric Information 1 Ying Chen Arizona State University yingchen@asu.edu Hülya Eraslan Johns Hopkins University eraslan@jhu.edu June 22, 2010 1 We thank Ming

More information

Common Agency Lobbying over Coalitions and Policy

Common Agency Lobbying over Coalitions and Policy Common Agency Lobbying over Coalitions and Policy David P. Baron and Alexander V. Hirsch July 12, 2009 Abstract This paper presents a theory of common agency lobbying in which policy-interested lobbies

More information

Optimal Voting Rules for International Organizations, with an. Application to the UN

Optimal Voting Rules for International Organizations, with an. Application to the UN Optimal Voting Rules for International Organizations, with an Application to the UN Johann Caro Burnett November 24, 2016 Abstract This paper examines a self-enforcing mechanism for an international organization

More information

Reviewing Procedure vs. Judging Substance: The Effect of Judicial Review on Agency Policymaking*

Reviewing Procedure vs. Judging Substance: The Effect of Judicial Review on Agency Policymaking* Reviewing Procedure vs. Judging Substance: The Effect of Judicial Review on Agency Policymaking* Ian R. Turner March 30, 2014 Abstract Bureaucratic policymaking is a central feature of the modern American

More information

Political Economics II Spring Lectures 4-5 Part II Partisan Politics and Political Agency. Torsten Persson, IIES

Political Economics II Spring Lectures 4-5 Part II Partisan Politics and Political Agency. Torsten Persson, IIES Lectures 4-5_190213.pdf Political Economics II Spring 2019 Lectures 4-5 Part II Partisan Politics and Political Agency Torsten Persson, IIES 1 Introduction: Partisan Politics Aims continue exploring policy

More information

"Efficient and Durable Decision Rules with Incomplete Information", by Bengt Holmström and Roger B. Myerson

Efficient and Durable Decision Rules with Incomplete Information, by Bengt Holmström and Roger B. Myerson April 15, 2015 "Efficient and Durable Decision Rules with Incomplete Information", by Bengt Holmström and Roger B. Myerson Econometrica, Vol. 51, No. 6 (Nov., 1983), pp. 1799-1819. Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/1912117

More information

Ideology and Competence in Alternative Electoral Systems.

Ideology and Competence in Alternative Electoral Systems. Ideology and Competence in Alternative Electoral Systems. Matias Iaryczower and Andrea Mattozzi July 9, 2008 Abstract We develop a model of elections in proportional (PR) and majoritarian (FPTP) electoral

More information

HOTELLING-DOWNS MODEL OF ELECTORAL COMPETITION AND THE OPTION TO QUIT

HOTELLING-DOWNS MODEL OF ELECTORAL COMPETITION AND THE OPTION TO QUIT HOTELLING-DOWNS MODEL OF ELECTORAL COMPETITION AND THE OPTION TO QUIT ABHIJIT SENGUPTA AND KUNAL SENGUPTA SCHOOL OF ECONOMICS AND POLITICAL SCIENCE UNIVERSITY OF SYDNEY SYDNEY, NSW 2006 AUSTRALIA Abstract.

More information

The Provision of Public Goods Under Alternative. Electoral Incentives

The Provision of Public Goods Under Alternative. Electoral Incentives The Provision of Public Goods Under Alternative Electoral Incentives Alessandro Lizzeri and Nicola Persico March 10, 2000 American Economic Review, forthcoming ABSTRACT Politicians who care about the spoils

More information

ONLINE APPENDIX: Why Do Voters Dismantle Checks and Balances? Extensions and Robustness

ONLINE APPENDIX: Why Do Voters Dismantle Checks and Balances? Extensions and Robustness CeNTRe for APPlieD MACRo - AND PeTRoleuM economics (CAMP) CAMP Working Paper Series No 2/2013 ONLINE APPENDIX: Why Do Voters Dismantle Checks and Balances? Extensions and Robustness Daron Acemoglu, James

More information

Parliamentarism or Presidentialism? 1

Parliamentarism or Presidentialism? 1 Parliamentarism or Presidentialism? 1 Peter Buisseret Princeton University JOB MARKET PAPER Abstract In parliamentary and presidential systems, the voter delegates policy proposal and veto responsibilities

More information

Sincere Versus Sophisticated Voting When Legislators Vote Sequentially

Sincere Versus Sophisticated Voting When Legislators Vote Sequentially Sincere Versus Sophisticated Voting When Legislators Vote Sequentially Tim Groseclose Departments of Political Science and Economics UCLA Jeffrey Milyo Department of Economics University of Missouri September

More information

Formal Modeling in Political Science Mon & Wed 10:00-11:50

Formal Modeling in Political Science Mon & Wed 10:00-11:50 POLS 606-300: Advanced Research Methods for Political Scientists Summer 2012 Formal Modeling in Political Science Mon & Wed 10:00-11:50 http://www-polisci.tamu.edu/faculty/kurizaki/ Allen 2064 Shuhei Kurizaki

More information

Working Smart and Hard? Agency Effort, Judicial Review, and Policy Precision

Working Smart and Hard? Agency Effort, Judicial Review, and Policy Precision Working Smart and Hard? Agency Effort, Judicial Review, and Policy Precision Ian R. Turner* August 21, 2014 Abstract The lion s share of policy in the United States is made by administrative agencies.

More information

Corruption and Political Competition

Corruption and Political Competition Corruption and Political Competition Richard Damania Adelaide University Erkan Yalçin Yeditepe University October 24, 2005 Abstract There is a growing evidence that political corruption is often closely

More information

14.770: Introduction to Political Economy Lecture 11: Economic Policy under Representative Democracy

14.770: Introduction to Political Economy Lecture 11: Economic Policy under Representative Democracy 14.770: Introduction to Political Economy Lecture 11: Economic Policy under Representative Democracy Daron Acemoglu MIT October 16, 2017. Daron Acemoglu (MIT) Political Economy Lecture 11 October 16, 2017.

More information

IMPERFECT INFORMATION (SIGNALING GAMES AND APPLICATIONS)

IMPERFECT INFORMATION (SIGNALING GAMES AND APPLICATIONS) IMPERFECT INFORMATION (SIGNALING GAMES AND APPLICATIONS) 1 Equilibrium concepts Concept Best responses Beliefs Nash equilibrium Subgame perfect equilibrium Perfect Bayesian equilibrium On the equilibrium

More information

Published in Canadian Journal of Economics 27 (1995), Copyright c 1995 by Canadian Economics Association

Published in Canadian Journal of Economics 27 (1995), Copyright c 1995 by Canadian Economics Association Published in Canadian Journal of Economics 27 (1995), 261 301. Copyright c 1995 by Canadian Economics Association Spatial Models of Political Competition Under Plurality Rule: A Survey of Some Explanations

More information

Sincere versus sophisticated voting when legislators vote sequentially

Sincere versus sophisticated voting when legislators vote sequentially Soc Choice Welf (2013) 40:745 751 DOI 10.1007/s00355-011-0639-x ORIGINAL PAPER Sincere versus sophisticated voting when legislators vote sequentially Tim Groseclose Jeffrey Milyo Received: 27 August 2010

More information

Sampling Equilibrium, with an Application to Strategic Voting Martin J. Osborne 1 and Ariel Rubinstein 2 September 12th, 2002.

Sampling Equilibrium, with an Application to Strategic Voting Martin J. Osborne 1 and Ariel Rubinstein 2 September 12th, 2002. Sampling Equilibrium, with an Application to Strategic Voting Martin J. Osborne 1 and Ariel Rubinstein 2 September 12th, 2002 Abstract We suggest an equilibrium concept for a strategic model with a large

More information

Darmstadt Discussion Papers in Economics

Darmstadt Discussion Papers in Economics Darmstadt Discussion Papers in Economics Coalition Governments and Policy Reform with Asymmetric Information Carsten Helm and Michael Neugart Nr. 192 Arbeitspapiere des Instituts für Volkswirtschaftslehre

More information

Illegal Migration and Policy Enforcement

Illegal Migration and Policy Enforcement Illegal Migration and Policy Enforcement Sephorah Mangin 1 and Yves Zenou 2 September 15, 2016 Abstract: Workers from a source country consider whether or not to illegally migrate to a host country. This

More information

INTERNATIONAL ECONOMICS, FINANCE AND TRADE Vol. II - Strategic Interaction, Trade Policy, and National Welfare - Bharati Basu

INTERNATIONAL ECONOMICS, FINANCE AND TRADE Vol. II - Strategic Interaction, Trade Policy, and National Welfare - Bharati Basu STRATEGIC INTERACTION, TRADE POLICY, AND NATIONAL WELFARE Bharati Basu Department of Economics, Central Michigan University, Mt. Pleasant, Michigan, USA Keywords: Calibration, export subsidy, export tax,

More information

Information Aggregation and Optimal Structure of the Executive

Information Aggregation and Optimal Structure of the Executive Information Aggregation and Optimal Structure of the Executive Torun Dewan Andrea Galeotti Christian Ghiglino Francesco Squintani December,2013 Abstract We provide a novel model of executives in parliamentary

More information

ELECTIONS, GOVERNMENTS, AND PARLIAMENTS IN PROPORTIONAL REPRESENTATION SYSTEMS*

ELECTIONS, GOVERNMENTS, AND PARLIAMENTS IN PROPORTIONAL REPRESENTATION SYSTEMS* ELECTIONS, GOVERNMENTS, AND PARLIAMENTS IN PROPORTIONAL REPRESENTATION SYSTEMS* DAVID P. BARON AND DANIEL DIERMEIER This paper presents a theory of parliamentary systems with a proportional representation

More information

Reviewing Procedure vs. Judging Substance: The Scope of Review and Bureaucratic Policymaking

Reviewing Procedure vs. Judging Substance: The Scope of Review and Bureaucratic Policymaking Reviewing Procedure vs. Judging Substance: The Scope of Review and Bureaucratic Policymaking Ian R. Turner Abstract How does the scope of review affect bureaucratic policymaking incentives? To explore

More information

A Theory of Political Polarization*

A Theory of Political Polarization* A Theory of Political Polarization* John W. Patty Elizabeth Maggie Penn August 22, 2017 Abstract We present a simple theory of voters preferences over representatives, assuming that a representative will

More information

Social Rankings in Human-Computer Committees

Social Rankings in Human-Computer Committees Social Rankings in Human-Computer Committees Moshe Bitan 1, Ya akov (Kobi) Gal 3 and Elad Dokow 4, and Sarit Kraus 1,2 1 Computer Science Department, Bar Ilan University, Israel 2 Institute for Advanced

More information

Coalition Governments and Political Rents

Coalition Governments and Political Rents Coalition Governments and Political Rents Dr. Refik Emre Aytimur Georg-August-Universität Göttingen January 01 Abstract We analyze the impact of coalition governments on the ability of political competition

More information

ECO/PSC 582 Political Economy II

ECO/PSC 582 Political Economy II ECO/PSC 582 Political Economy II Jean Guillaume Forand Spring 2011, Rochester Lectures: TBA. Office Hours: By appointment, or drop by my office. Course Outline: This course, a companion to ECO/PSC 575,

More information

THE EFFECT OF OFFER-OF-SETTLEMENT RULES ON THE TERMS OF SETTLEMENT

THE EFFECT OF OFFER-OF-SETTLEMENT RULES ON THE TERMS OF SETTLEMENT Last revision: 12/97 THE EFFECT OF OFFER-OF-SETTLEMENT RULES ON THE TERMS OF SETTLEMENT Lucian Arye Bebchuk * and Howard F. Chang ** * Professor of Law, Economics, and Finance, Harvard Law School. ** Professor

More information

Information Aggregation and. Optimal Structure of the Executive

Information Aggregation and. Optimal Structure of the Executive Information Aggregation and Optimal Structure of the Executive First Draft: September 2011 This draft: March, 2013 Torun Dewan Andrea Galeotti Christian Ghiglino Francesco Squintani Abstract We provide

More information

Answers to Practice Problems. Median voter theorem, supermajority rule, & bicameralism.

Answers to Practice Problems. Median voter theorem, supermajority rule, & bicameralism. Answers to Practice Problems Median voter theorem, supermajority rule, & bicameralism. Median Voter Theorem Questions: 2.1-2.4, and 2.8. Located at the end of Hinich and Munger, chapter 2, The Spatial

More information

THREATS TO SUE AND COST DIVISIBILITY UNDER ASYMMETRIC INFORMATION. Alon Klement. Discussion Paper No /2000

THREATS TO SUE AND COST DIVISIBILITY UNDER ASYMMETRIC INFORMATION. Alon Klement. Discussion Paper No /2000 ISSN 1045-6333 THREATS TO SUE AND COST DIVISIBILITY UNDER ASYMMETRIC INFORMATION Alon Klement Discussion Paper No. 273 1/2000 Harvard Law School Cambridge, MA 02138 The Center for Law, Economics, and Business

More information

Committee proposals and restrictive rules

Committee proposals and restrictive rules Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA Vol. 96, pp. 8295 8300, July 1999 Political Sciences Committee proposals and restrictive rules JEFFREY S. BANKS Division of Humanities and Social Sciences, California Institute

More information

Bureaucratic Decision Costs and Endogeneous Agency Expertise

Bureaucratic Decision Costs and Endogeneous Agency Expertise NELLCO NELLCO Legal Scholarship Repository Harvard Law School John M. Olin Center for Law, Economics and Business Discussion Paper Series Harvard Law School 7-5-2006 Bureaucratic Decision Costs and Endogeneous

More information

Bargaining and vetoing

Bargaining and vetoing Bargaining and vetoing Hankyoung Sung The Ohio State University April 30, 004 Abstract This paper studies the bargaining game between the president and the congress when these two players have conflicting

More information

Spring 2017 SOCI Social Science Inquiry III

Spring 2017 SOCI Social Science Inquiry III Spring 2017 SOCI 30900 Social Science Inquiry III Professor Nalepa mnalepa@uchicago.edu The University of Chicago T, Th: 9:00-10:20 a.m. Wieboldt Hall 130 Office hours: Tuesday 3-5 p.m. TA: Ji Xue jixue@uchicago.edu

More information

Defensive Weapons and Defensive Alliances

Defensive Weapons and Defensive Alliances Defensive Weapons and Defensive Alliances Sylvain Chassang Princeton University Gerard Padró i Miquel London School of Economics and NBER December 17, 2008 In 2002, U.S. President George W. Bush initiated

More information

Immigration and Conflict in Democracies

Immigration and Conflict in Democracies Immigration and Conflict in Democracies Santiago Sánchez-Pagés Ángel Solano García June 2008 Abstract Relationships between citizens and immigrants may not be as good as expected in some western democracies.

More information

Information Aggregation in Voting with Endogenous Timing

Information Aggregation in Voting with Endogenous Timing Information Aggregation in Voting with Endogenous Timing Konstantinos N. Rokas & Vinayak Tripathi Princeton University June 17, 2007 Abstract We study information aggregation in an election where agents

More information

George Mason University

George Mason University George Mason University SCHOOL of LAW Two Dimensions of Regulatory Competition Francesco Parisi Norbert Schulz Jonathan Klick 03-01 LAW AND ECONOMICS WORKING PAPER SERIES This paper can be downloaded without

More information

Supporting Information Political Quid Pro Quo Agreements: An Experimental Study

Supporting Information Political Quid Pro Quo Agreements: An Experimental Study Supporting Information Political Quid Pro Quo Agreements: An Experimental Study Jens Großer Florida State University and IAS, Princeton Ernesto Reuben Columbia University and IZA Agnieszka Tymula New York

More information

MIDTERM EXAM 1: Political Economy Winter 2017

MIDTERM EXAM 1: Political Economy Winter 2017 Name: MIDTERM EXAM 1: Political Economy Winter 2017 Student Number: You must always show your thinking to get full credit. You have one hour and twenty minutes to complete all questions. All questions

More information

On Deliberative Authoritarian Governance

On Deliberative Authoritarian Governance On Deliberative Authoritarian Governance Jidong Chen Yiqing Xu (job market paper) Abstract Why would an authoritarian regime set up deliberative institutions to allow people to complain publicly if, as

More information

Bargaining and Cooperation in Strategic Form Games

Bargaining and Cooperation in Strategic Form Games Bargaining and Cooperation in Strategic Form Games Sergiu Hart July 2008 Revised: January 2009 SERGIU HART c 2007 p. 1 Bargaining and Cooperation in Strategic Form Games Sergiu Hart Center of Rationality,

More information

OPTIMAL AGENCY BIAS AND REGULATORY REVIEW. Preliminary and incomplete.

OPTIMAL AGENCY BIAS AND REGULATORY REVIEW. Preliminary and incomplete. OPTIMAL AGENCY BIAS AND REGULATORY REVIEW RYAN BUBB* AND PATRICK WARREN** ABSTRACT. Why do bureaucratic principals appoint agents who hold different policy views from the principal and subject their decisions

More information

Good Politicians' Distorted Incentives

Good Politicians' Distorted Incentives Good Politicians' Distorted Incentives Margherita Negri School of Economics and Finance Online Discussion Paper Series issn 2055-303X http://ideas.repec.org/s/san/wpecon.html info: econ@st-andrews.ac.uk

More information

ECONS 491 STRATEGY AND GAME THEORY 1 SIGNALING IN THE LABOR MARKET

ECONS 491 STRATEGY AND GAME THEORY 1 SIGNALING IN THE LABOR MARKET ECONS 491 STRATEGY AND GAME THEORY 1 SIGNALING IN THE LABOR MARKET Let us consider the following sequential game with incomplete information. A worker privately observes whether he has a High productivity

More information

ESSAYS ON STRATEGIC VOTING. by Sun-Tak Kim B. A. in English Language and Literature, Hankuk University of Foreign Studies, Seoul, Korea, 1998

ESSAYS ON STRATEGIC VOTING. by Sun-Tak Kim B. A. in English Language and Literature, Hankuk University of Foreign Studies, Seoul, Korea, 1998 ESSAYS ON STRATEGIC VOTING by Sun-Tak Kim B. A. in English Language and Literature, Hankuk University of Foreign Studies, Seoul, Korea, 1998 Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of the Kenneth P. Dietrich

More information

Classical papers: Osborbe and Slivinski (1996) and Besley and Coate (1997)

Classical papers: Osborbe and Slivinski (1996) and Besley and Coate (1997) The identity of politicians is endogenized Typical approach: any citizen may enter electoral competition at a cost. There is no pre-commitment on the platforms, and winner implements his or her ideal policy.

More information

Approval Voting and Scoring Rules with Common Values

Approval Voting and Scoring Rules with Common Values Approval Voting and Scoring Rules with Common Values David S. Ahn University of California, Berkeley Santiago Oliveros University of Essex June 2016 Abstract We compare approval voting with other scoring

More information

Wisdom of the Crowd? Information Aggregation and Electoral Incentives

Wisdom of the Crowd? Information Aggregation and Electoral Incentives Wisdom of the Crowd? Information Aggregation and Electoral Incentives Carlo Prato Stephane Wolton June 2016 Abstract Elections have long been understood as a mean to encourage candidates to act in voters

More information

The Administrative Foundation of the Rule of Law

The Administrative Foundation of the Rule of Law University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign From the SelectedWorks of Mattias K Polborn 2013 The Administrative Foundation of the Rule of Law Tiberiu Dragu Mattias K Polborn Available at: https://works.bepress.com/polborn/27/

More information

1 Grim Trigger Practice 2. 2 Issue Linkage 3. 3 Institutions as Interaction Accelerators 5. 4 Perverse Incentives 6.

1 Grim Trigger Practice 2. 2 Issue Linkage 3. 3 Institutions as Interaction Accelerators 5. 4 Perverse Incentives 6. Contents 1 Grim Trigger Practice 2 2 Issue Linkage 3 3 Institutions as Interaction Accelerators 5 4 Perverse Incentives 6 5 Moral Hazard 7 6 Gatekeeping versus Veto Power 8 7 Mechanism Design Practice

More information

Campaign Contributions as Valence

Campaign Contributions as Valence Campaign Contributions as Valence Tim Lambie-Hanson Suffolk University June 11, 2011 Tim Lambie-Hanson (Suffolk University) Campaign Contributions as Valence June 11, 2011 1 / 16 Motivation Under what

More information

A Theory of Policy Expertise

A Theory of Policy Expertise A Theory of Policy Expertise Steven Callander January 9, 2008 Abstract The canonical model of expertise has two prominent features: expertise is a single piece of information and it is perfectly invertible.

More information

GAME THEORY. Analysis of Conflict ROGER B. MYERSON. HARVARD UNIVERSITY PRESS Cambridge, Massachusetts London, England

GAME THEORY. Analysis of Conflict ROGER B. MYERSON. HARVARD UNIVERSITY PRESS Cambridge, Massachusetts London, England GAME THEORY Analysis of Conflict ROGER B. MYERSON HARVARD UNIVERSITY PRESS Cambridge, Massachusetts London, England Contents Preface 1 Decision-Theoretic Foundations 1.1 Game Theory, Rationality, and Intelligence

More information

Politics is the subset of human behavior that involves the use of power or influence.

Politics is the subset of human behavior that involves the use of power or influence. What is Politics? Politics is the subset of human behavior that involves the use of power or influence. Power is involved whenever individuals cannot accomplish their goals without either trying to influence

More information

APPLICATION: PIVOTAL POLITICS

APPLICATION: PIVOTAL POLITICS APPLICATION: PIVOTAL POLITICS 1 A. Goals Pivotal Politics 1. Want to apply game theory to the legislative process to determine: 1. which outcomes are in SPE, and 2. which status quos would not change in

More information

Should Straw Polls be Banned?

Should Straw Polls be Banned? The Ronald O. Perelman Center for Political Science and Economics (PCPSE) 133 South 36 th Street Philadelphia, PA 19104-6297 pier@econ.upenn.edu http://economics.sas.upenn.edu/pier PIER Working Paper 18-022

More information

policy-making. footnote We adopt a simple parametric specification which allows us to go between the two polar cases studied in this literature.

policy-making. footnote We adopt a simple parametric specification which allows us to go between the two polar cases studied in this literature. Introduction Which tier of government should be responsible for particular taxing and spending decisions? From Philadelphia to Maastricht, this question has vexed constitution designers. Yet still the

More information

(67686) Mathematical Foundations of AI June 18, Lecture 6

(67686) Mathematical Foundations of AI June 18, Lecture 6 (67686) Mathematical Foundations of AI June 18, 2008 Lecturer: Ariel D. Procaccia Lecture 6 Scribe: Ezra Resnick & Ariel Imber 1 Introduction: Social choice theory Thus far in the course, we have dealt

More information

Reputation and Rhetoric in Elections

Reputation and Rhetoric in Elections Reputation and Rhetoric in Elections Enriqueta Aragonès Institut d Anàlisi Econòmica, CSIC Andrew Postlewaite University of Pennsylvania April 11, 2005 Thomas R. Palfrey Princeton University Earlier versions

More information

In bureaucratic organizations, conflict over policy goals creates incentive problems

In bureaucratic organizations, conflict over policy goals creates incentive problems Political Science Research and Methods Page 1 of 18 The European Political Science Association, 2018 doi:10.1017/psrm.2018.5 Giving Advice Versus Making Decisions: Transparency, Information, and Delegation*

More information

Policy Reputation and Political Accountability

Policy Reputation and Political Accountability Policy Reputation and Political Accountability Tapas Kundu October 9, 2016 Abstract We develop a model of electoral competition where both economic policy and politician s e ort a ect voters payo. When

More information

The Robustness of Herrera, Levine and Martinelli s Policy platforms, campaign spending and voter participation

The Robustness of Herrera, Levine and Martinelli s Policy platforms, campaign spending and voter participation The Robustness of Herrera, Levine and Martinelli s Policy platforms, campaign spending and voter participation Alexander Chun June 8, 009 Abstract In this paper, I look at potential weaknesses in the electoral

More information

The disadvantages of winning an election.

The disadvantages of winning an election. The disadvantages of winning an election. Enriqueta Aragones Institut d Anàlisi Econòmica, CSIC Santiago Sánchez-Pagés University of Edinburgh January 2010 Abstract After an election, the winner has to

More information

Endogenous Politics and the Design of Trade Agreements

Endogenous Politics and the Design of Trade Agreements Endogenous Politics and the Design of Trade Agreements Kristy Buzard* May 10, 2014 Abstract Political pressure is undoubtedly an important influence in the setting of trade policy and the formulation of

More information

An example of public goods

An example of public goods An example of public goods Yossi Spiegel Consider an economy with two identical agents, A and B, who consume one public good G, and one private good y. The preferences of the two agents are given by the

More information

MULTIPLE VOTES, MULTIPLE CANDIDACIES AND POLARIZATION ARNAUD DELLIS

MULTIPLE VOTES, MULTIPLE CANDIDACIES AND POLARIZATION ARNAUD DELLIS MULTIPLE VOTES, MULTIPLE CANDIDACIES AND POLARIZATION ARNAUD DELLIS Université Laval and CIRPEE 105 Ave des Sciences Humaines, local 174, Québec (QC) G1V 0A6, Canada E-mail: arnaud.dellis@ecn.ulaval.ca

More information

Handcuffs for the Grabbing Hand? Media Capture and Government Accountability by Timothy Besley and Andrea Prat (2006)

Handcuffs for the Grabbing Hand? Media Capture and Government Accountability by Timothy Besley and Andrea Prat (2006) Handcuffs for the Grabbing Hand? Media Capture and Government Accountability by Timothy Besley and Andrea Prat (2006) Group Hicks: Dena, Marjorie, Sabina, Shehryar To the press alone, checkered as it is

More information

The relation between the prosecutor, the attorney and the client in plea bargaining : a principal-agent model 1

The relation between the prosecutor, the attorney and the client in plea bargaining : a principal-agent model 1 The relation between the prosecutor, the attorney the client in plea bargaining : a principal-agent model 1 ANCELOT Lydie 2 Preliminary draft, October 2007 1 I wish to acknowledge for the helpful comments:

More information

Optimal Checks and Balances Under Policy Uncertainty

Optimal Checks and Balances Under Policy Uncertainty Optimal Checks and Balances Under Policy Uncertainty Gabriele Gratton and Massimo Morelli December 26, 2018 Abstract Political checks and balances are certainly among the most debated desiderata in the

More information

Policy Stability under Different Electoral Systems Λ Massimo Morelli? and Michele Tertilt??? Ohio State University?? University of Minnesota OSU Worki

Policy Stability under Different Electoral Systems Λ Massimo Morelli? and Michele Tertilt??? Ohio State University?? University of Minnesota OSU Worki Policy Stability under Different Electoral Systems Λ Massimo Morelli? and Michele Tertilt??? Ohio State University?? University of Minnesota OSU Working Paper no. 00-13, October 2000 Abstract This paper

More information

Choosing Among Signalling Equilibria in Lobbying Games

Choosing Among Signalling Equilibria in Lobbying Games Choosing Among Signalling Equilibria in Lobbying Games July 17, 1996 Eric Rasmusen Abstract Randolph Sloof has written a comment on the lobbying-as-signalling model in Rasmusen (1993) in which he points

More information

Authority versus Persuasion

Authority versus Persuasion Authority versus Persuasion Eric Van den Steen December 30, 2008 Managers often face a choice between authority and persuasion. In particular, since a firm s formal and relational contracts and its culture

More information

Behavioral Public Choice. Professor Rebecca Morton New York University

Behavioral Public Choice. Professor Rebecca Morton New York University Behavioral Public Choice Professor Rebecca Morton New York University Reading List Ali, Nageeb, Jacob Goeree, Navin Kartik, and Thomas Palfrey. 2008a. Information Aggregation in Ad Hoc and Standing Committees.

More information

VOTING ON INCOME REDISTRIBUTION: HOW A LITTLE BIT OF ALTRUISM CREATES TRANSITIVITY DONALD WITTMAN ECONOMICS DEPARTMENT UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA

VOTING ON INCOME REDISTRIBUTION: HOW A LITTLE BIT OF ALTRUISM CREATES TRANSITIVITY DONALD WITTMAN ECONOMICS DEPARTMENT UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA 1 VOTING ON INCOME REDISTRIBUTION: HOW A LITTLE BIT OF ALTRUISM CREATES TRANSITIVITY DONALD WITTMAN ECONOMICS DEPARTMENT UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA SANTA CRUZ wittman@ucsc.edu ABSTRACT We consider an election

More information

Allies or Commitment Devices? A Model of Appointments to the Federal Reserve

Allies or Commitment Devices? A Model of Appointments to the Federal Reserve Allies or Commitment Devices? A Model of Appointments to the Federal Reserve Keith E. Schnakenberg Ian R. Turner Abstract We present a model of executive-legislative bargaining over appointments to independent

More information

Are Supreme Court Nominations a Move-the-Median Game?

Are Supreme Court Nominations a Move-the-Median Game? Are Supreme Court Nominations a Move-the-Median Game? Charles M. Cameron Professor of Politics and Public Affairs Department of Politics & Woodrow Wilson School Princeton University ccameron@princeton.edu

More information

Judicial Mechanism Design

Judicial Mechanism Design Judicial Mechanism Design Ron Siegel and Bruno Strulovici May 218 Abstract This paper proposes a modern mechanism design approach to study welfare-maximizing criminal judicial processes. We provide a framework

More information

We analyze the positive and normative implications of regulatory oversight when the policymaking

We analyze the positive and normative implications of regulatory oversight when the policymaking American Political Science Review Vol. 101, No. 3 August 2007 Regulatory Quality Under Imperfect Oversight ETHAN BUENO DE MESQUITA Washington University MATTHEW C. STEPHENSON Harvard Law School DOI: 10.1017/S0003055407070359

More information

Sequential Voting with Externalities: Herding in Social Networks

Sequential Voting with Externalities: Herding in Social Networks Sequential Voting with Externalities: Herding in Social Networks Noga Alon Moshe Babaioff Ron Karidi Ron Lavi Moshe Tennenholtz February 7, 01 Abstract We study sequential voting with two alternatives,

More information

BIPOLAR MULTICANDIDATE ELECTIONS WITH CORRUPTION by Roger B. Myerson August 2005 revised August 2006

BIPOLAR MULTICANDIDATE ELECTIONS WITH CORRUPTION by Roger B. Myerson August 2005 revised August 2006 BIPOLAR MULTICANDIDATE ELECTIONS WITH CORRUPTION by Roger B. Myerson August 2005 revised August 2006 Abstract. The goals of democratic competition are not only to give implement a majority's preference

More information

Median voter theorem - continuous choice

Median voter theorem - continuous choice Median voter theorem - continuous choice In most economic applications voters are asked to make a non-discrete choice - e.g. choosing taxes. In these applications the condition of single-peakedness is

More information

Learning and Belief Based Trade 1

Learning and Belief Based Trade 1 Learning and Belief Based Trade 1 First Version: October 31, 1994 This Version: September 13, 2005 Drew Fudenberg David K Levine 2 Abstract: We use the theory of learning in games to show that no-trade

More information

Political Science (POLS) 604 Conceptualization and Theory in Political Analysis Wednesday 9 a.m. to 11:50 a.m. Allen 2115

Political Science (POLS) 604 Conceptualization and Theory in Political Analysis Wednesday 9 a.m. to 11:50 a.m. Allen 2115 Political Science (POLS) 604 Conceptualization and Theory in Political Analysis Wednesday 9 a.m. to 11:50 a.m. Allen 2115 Ahmer Tarar ahmertarar@tamu.edu Allen 2045 Office Hours: Monday and Friday 11 a.m.

More information

University of Toronto Department of Economics. Party formation in single-issue politics [revised]

University of Toronto Department of Economics. Party formation in single-issue politics [revised] University of Toronto Department of Economics Working Paper 296 Party formation in single-issue politics [revised] By Martin J. Osborne and Rabee Tourky July 13, 2007 Party formation in single-issue politics

More information

Winter 2019 PLSC Game Theory I

Winter 2019 PLSC Game Theory I Winter 2019 PLSC 30901 Game Theory I Professor Nalepa mnalepa@uchicago.edu The University of Chicago T, Th: 2:00-3:30 Pick 506 Office hours: Tuesdays 3:30-5pm Pick 324A TA: Genevieve Bates genbates@uchicago.edu

More information

Refinements of Nash equilibria. Jorge M. Streb. Universidade de Brasilia 7 June 2016

Refinements of Nash equilibria. Jorge M. Streb. Universidade de Brasilia 7 June 2016 Refinements of Nash equilibria Jorge M. Streb Universidade de Brasilia 7 June 2016 1 Outline 1. Yesterday on Nash equilibria 2. Imperfect and incomplete information: Bayes Nash equilibrium with incomplete

More information

Preferential votes and minority representation in open list proportional representation systems

Preferential votes and minority representation in open list proportional representation systems Soc Choice Welf (018) 50:81 303 https://doi.org/10.1007/s00355-017-1084- ORIGINAL PAPER Preferential votes and minority representation in open list proportional representation systems Margherita Negri

More information

Cambridge University Press Political Game Theory: An Introduction Nolan McCarty and Adam Meirowitz Frontmatter More information

Cambridge University Press Political Game Theory: An Introduction Nolan McCarty and Adam Meirowitz Frontmatter More information POLITICAL GAME THEORY Political Game Theory is a self-contained introduction to game theory and its applications to political science. The book presents choice theory, social choice theory, static and

More information

Testing Political Economy Models of Reform in the Laboratory

Testing Political Economy Models of Reform in the Laboratory Testing Political Economy Models of Reform in the Laboratory By TIMOTHY N. CASON AND VAI-LAM MUI* * Department of Economics, Krannert School of Management, Purdue University, West Lafayette, IN 47907-1310,

More information

Topics in the Economics of Politics

Topics in the Economics of Politics Mehdi Shadmehr Eco 634 P 517-J Jenkins Hall 11-12:15 TR shad@miami.edu Objective Topics in the Economics of Politics This course covers selected topics in political economy. I focus on non-democracies,

More information

Voter Participation with Collusive Parties. David K. Levine and Andrea Mattozzi

Voter Participation with Collusive Parties. David K. Levine and Andrea Mattozzi Voter Participation with Collusive Parties David K. Levine and Andrea Mattozzi 1 Overview Woman who ran over husband for not voting pleads guilty USA Today April 21, 2015 classical political conflict model:

More information