Inequality: A Complex, Individualistic, and Comparative Notion 1

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Inequality: A Complex, Individualistic, and Comparative Notion 1"

Transcription

1 13 Philosophical Issues, 11 Social, Political, and Legal Philosophy, 2001 Inequality: A Complex, Individualistic, and Comparative Notion 1 Larry S. Temkin Introduction Equality has long been among the most potent of human ideals, and it continues to play a prominent role in political argument. Views about equality inform much of the debates about such wideranging issues as racism, sexism, obligations to the poor or handicapped, relations between developed and developing countries, and the justification of competing political, economic, and ideological systems. Unfortunately, these debates have been shrouded in error and confusion, for few ideals have been more widely discussed, yet less well understood, than the ideal of equality. This essay is divided into two main parts. In part I, I distinguish between different kinds of egalitarian positions. I show that numerous so-called egalitarian positions are compatible with the central tenet of non-egalitarianism, and suggest a core notion that would distinguish egalitarians from non-egalitarians. In addition, I claim that there is an intimate connection between equality and fairness, and suggest that egalitarians should be pluralists both in terms of other ideals and in terms of the kinds of equality that

2 328 Larry S. Temkin matter. In part II, I gather together, for the first time in an essay, some of the central results of my book, Inequality. 2 I introduce my approach to understanding equality as a complex, individualistic, and comparative notion. In addition, I briefly address several questions about which many have been confused or mistaken. These include whether inequality matters more at high levels or low levels, whether variation in population size affects inequality, and whether one should focus on whole lives in comparing individuals with respect to inequality. Finally, I briefly consider a possible implication of my work that would be surprising and dismaying. The aim of my essay is modest, but important. It is to contribute to a better understanding of the ideal of equality. I do not argue that one should care about equality. Nor do I address the question of how much one should care about equality, assuming one should. It seems to me that until one understands the notion such questions are premature. One preliminary comment. The set of issues that most philosophers and political scientists cast in the terminology of equality, most economists cast in the terminology of inequality. The issues are the same, but there are two ways of talking about them. Thus, the egalitarian s concern to promote equality, just is the concern to reduce inequality. In general, I shall follow the economists usage, which I find more perspicuous. However, in contexts where it would be misleading or awkward to do so, I shall follow the philosophers usage. I trust, in each case, context will make my meaning plain. Part I Egalitarians come in many stripes. Too many, I m afraid. There is no consensus as to what egalitarianism is, hence no single position being defended or attacked. Worse, both advocates and opponents conflate equality with a host of other positions. This is unfortunate. We cannot make progress in this difficult area until we are clear what we are arguing about. The main aim of this part is to help rectify this situation. I want to carefully distinguish between different possible egalitarian positions, so that future debates can be more focused and effective. Unfortunately, to do this properly involves some boring taxonomy. Nevertheless, years of reading and lecturing about equality have convinced me that although some of these distinctions have long been recognized,

3 13. Inequality 329 too often they are overlooked or ignored. Moreover, much needless confusion could be avoided if they were kept in mind. In the interests of space, I shall largely restrict myself to bald but not, I think, unwarranted assertions. A. Philosophers have long distinguished between purely formal principles of equality and substantive principles of equality, where, roughly, a formal principle is one that demands universality in its application, while a substantive principle is one that demands that people be treated equally in certain respects. Unfortunately, this distinction is neither as clean, nor as helpful as one might hope. Many positions meet the criteria of both formal and substantive principles of equality, and among positions that meet the stated criterion of a substantive principle of equality, some are associated with a deep and thoroughgoing commitment to equality, while others are not. Consequently, it may be useful to distinguish between equality as universality principles, equality as impartiality principles, and equality as comparability principles. Roughly, equality as universality reflects the view that all reasons and principles must be universal in their application. The view that all blue-eyed people should be made kings, and all browneyed people paupers meets the equality as universality criterion! So too would the more restricted view that all blue-eyed people named Temkin should be made kings, and all brown-eyed people not named Temkin paupers. Thus, no matter how inegalitarian a view may be in its motivation and implications, all that matters for a view to be egalitarian in this sense is that it apply universally. Equality as universality corresponds to the notion of pure formal equality noted above. It is widely regarded as a basic principle of rationality. Equality as impartiality reflects the view that all people must be treated impartially. Of course, positions can vary dramatically in their understanding of what treating people impartially requires. Kantians believe we treat people impartially by treating them all as ends, and never merely as means. Utilitarians believe we treat all impartially when we count each person s interests as of equal weight in deciding what maximizes the good. Certain Marxists believe we treat all impartially by following the dictum from each according to his ability, to each according to his need. Though each of these views has its own conception of impartiality, each is committed to treating people equally in the sense of being impartial between them. Note, those committed to equality

4 330 Larry S. Temkin as impartiality will also tend to be committed to equality as universality, but the reverse need not hold. Equality as comparability reflects a different kind of commitment to equality. Equality as comparability reflects a fundamental concern with how people fare relative to others. More particularly, I believe the fundamental view underlying equality as comparability is that it is bad for some to be worse off than others through no fault or choice of their own. Importantly, those committed to equality as comparability will also be committed to both equality as impartiality and equality as universality, but their substantive views extend significantly beyond a concern for universality or impartiality. Correspondingly, many committed to equality as universality or equality as impartiality lack the concern for equality as comparability. Thus, one might say that equality as comparability reflects a deeper and more thoroughgoing commitment to equality than either equality as universality or equality as impartiality. Such a view reflects a significant and distinctive commitment to equality as an independent substantive ideal. To see the value of these distinctions, let us consider some claims of Amartya Sen, one of the most thoughtful and influential writers on equality. Most philosophical discussions of equality have focused on two questions: Is equality really desirable? And what kind of equality should we seek that is, insofar as we are egalitarians, should we want equality of opportunity, primary goods, need satisfaction, welfare, or what? Sen has suggested that only the second question is really in doubt. According to Sen, virtually all moral theories want equality of something, what they differ about is equality of what? Thus, income-egalitarians...demand equal incomes,...welfare-egalitarians...equal welfare levels,...classical utilitarians...equal weights on the utilities of all, and...libertarians... equality with respect to...rights and liberties. 3 Sen s view is interesting and important. Yet many will find it hard to believe that utilitarianism and libertarianism two views most widely associated with non-egalitarianism are in fact egalitarian positions. Indeed, it seems clear that there is something distinctive about positions like income-egalitarianism, primary goods-egalitarianism, or welfare-egalitarianism, and that such positions share a spirit or focus that is fundamentally different from that of utilitarianism or libertarianism. So what are we to make of Sen s claims? I think Sen is right that there are important senses in which virtually all contempo-

5 13. Inequality 331 rary moral views incorporate commitments to equality. But what they are committed to are equality as universality and equality as impartiality. They are not all committed to equality as comparability. Indeed, notoriously, both permit gross inequalities between better- and worse-off. The utilitarian s fundamental concern is to maximize utility; the libertarian s fundamental concern is for people to act freely, without interference, as long as they respect the rights and liberties of others. Neither has a fundamental concern for how people fare relative to others. Aristotle s famous principle of equality, that likes should be treated alike, and unalikes should be treated unalike, has long been regarded as a merely formal principle of equality. It corresponds to what I have called equality as universality. By itself, such a principle tells us nothing about how likes or unalikes should actually be treated, it is not committed to treating all people impartially, and it neither approves, nor condemns, some being worse off than others through no fault or choice of their own. The widely-held view that all person s should be treated with equal consideration and respect 4 expresses a commitment to equality as universality, but it is not just a formal principle like Aristotle s. It is also a substantive principle of equality, in that it expresses a commitment to impartiality that Aristotle s principle lacks. Still, by itself, the view is sufficiently broad as to be compatible with any moral principle that insists on impartiality, and so might be endorsed by such diverse positions as Kantianism, utilitarianism, Marxism, or libertarianism. Correspondingly, while such a position is compatible with equality as comparability, it does not entail it. Thus, it need not reflect the distinctive thoroughgoing commitment to equality expressed by equality as comparability. Virtually all agree that equality as universality is necessary as a condition of rationality. And virtually all contemporary theorists agree that equality as impartiality is a requirement of any plausible moral principle. But whether a further, deeper, commitment to a distinctive principle of equality as comparability is desirable remains highly disputed. B. Let us next distinguish between instrumental egalitarianism and non-instrumental egalitarianism. On instrumental egalitarianism, equality is extrinsically valuable that is, valuable because it promotes some other valuable ideal. On non-instrumental egalitarianism equality is intrinsically valuable that is, valuable in

6 332 Larry S. Temkin itself, over and above the extent to which it promotes other ideals. On instrumental egalitarianism, the value of equality is derivative from the value of the ideal it promotes. Thus, the ideal of equality does not play a fundamental role in one s account of the moral realm. On non-instrumental egalitarianism, equality is a distinct moral ideal with independent normative significance. Thus, a complete account of the moral realm must allow for equality s value. Non-egalitarians can readily admit that equality sometimes promotes other desirable ideals. Their central tenet is that equality is not a fundamental ideal. Those who would refute the nonegalitarian must endorse non-instrumental egalitarianism. Unfortunately, failure to recognize the distinction between instrumental and non-instrumental egalitarianism is responsible for much confusion regarding the nature and value of equality. Many who think of themselves as egalitarians are in fact only instrumental egalitarians, though they may not realize this. Moreover, they believe, wrongly, that a defense of instrumental egalitarianism is sufficient to refute non-egalitarians. Similarly, many nonegalitarians are in fact instrumental egalitarians, but they think, wrongly, that they must reject the arguments of instrumental egalitarians if they want to remain non-egalitarians. Defending an instrumental egalitarian position requires two moves: a defense of the ideal that equality is purportedly promoting, and a defense of the claim that in certain circumstances equality promotes that ideal. Neither move has any bearing on whether equality is a fundamental ideal. The first involves a normative claim about the value of an ideal other than equality; the second strictly involves an empirical fact. Thus, one hoping to respond to the non-egalitarian s central tenet in fact gains nothing by supporting instrumental egalitarianism. Let me illustrate some of these claims. Many people argue for equality and in so doing think of themselves as opposing nonegalitarianism because they favor significant redistribution from the better- to worse-off. But the reasons they have for favoring such redistribution vary markedly, and may have nothing to do with a concern for equality itself. For example, some favor such transfers for humanitarian reasons they favor equality solely as a means of reducing suffering, and given the choice between redistribution from the better- to worse-off, and identical gains for the worse-off with equal, or even greater, gains for the better-off, they would see no reason to favor the former over the latter. Such people are instrumental egalitarians, rather than non-instrumental

7 13. Inequality 333 egalitarians. Their position offers no more support of equality as an independent ideal than utilitarianism, which, of course, also favors transfers from better- to worse-off on all and only those occasions that maximize utility. Similarly, some would favor transfers from better- to worse-off as a way of promoting freedom they believe that genuine freedom involves the autonomous formulation and effective implementation of a meaningful life plan, and this requires satisfaction of one s basic needs, acceptable levels of resources or primary goods, and freedom from social, economic, and political coercion of a sort incompatible with great inequality. And the list goes on. Socialists, capitalists, communitarians, and others all might favor redistribution from better- to worse-off purely for instrumental reasons. Instrumental reasons for promoting equality may have tremendous moral significance but, as noted, they do not support the value of equality per se. Unfortunately, many have not recognized this, and thus concern for equality is often conflated with other concerns that equality may, under certain circumstances, promote. One striking example of this is Rawls s maximin principle, which requires that we maximize the expectations of the representative member of the worst-off group. 5 Maximin is widely regarded as an egalitarian principle, and many who accept maximin think of themselves as egalitarians. Yet maximin is concerned with how well off the worst-off fare, it is not concerned with how the worst-off fare relative to others. Thus, maximin licenses vast increases in inequality, if necessary for improving however slightly the worst-off. Of course, in most cases promoting equality will improve a situation according to maximin. Hence maximin is plausible as an instrumental egalitarian position. Moreover, like most plausible moral principles maximin is acceptable both as a principle of equality as universality, and also as a principle of equality as impartiality. But maximin is no different from utilitarianism in these respects. It is not plausible as a non-instrumental egalitarian position in the sense I am concerned with in this essay. It does not express a distinctive thoroughgoing commitment to equality as comparability. We have distinguished many different kinds of egalitarian positions: equality as universality, equality as impartiality, equality as comparability, instrumental egalitarianism, and non-instrumental egalitarianism. Having done this, in the remainder of this essay, I shall use the term egalitarian and its correlates to refer to those who share the deep thoroughgoing commitment to equality as comparability, and in particular to those who believe in the non-

8 334 Larry S. Temkin instrumental value equality. So, for my purposes, egalitarians believe that how people fare relative to others has independent moral significance, and in particular, they believe that it is bad for some to be worse off than others through no fault or choice of their own. Naturally, those who wish to continue to use the term egalitarian to refer to other positions may legitimately do so, but it is important not to conflate distinct positions. C. I have claimed that a principle of equality as comparability is one whose principal concern is with how people fare relative to others and which regards it as bad for some to be worse off than others through no fault or choice of their own. I have also claimed that only non-instrumental egalitarianism conflicts with the central tenet of non-egalitarianism. Many have wondered how there could be anything bad about inequality itself, over and above the extent to which it affects other ideals. Notoriously, egalitarians are accused of engaging in the politics of envy, as if only envy could account for a concern with how people fare relative to others, rather than a concern with how people fare. In addition, many wonder about the relevance of the no fault or choice of their own clause. After all, if inequality really is bad in itself, what difference does it make how it comes about? These worries raise a host of important questions. Unfortunately, I can only say a few words about each. Let me begin by carefully interpreting, or qualifying, my claim that inequality is bad in itself. If I give one piece of candy to Andrea, and two to Rebecca, Andrea will immediately assert unfair! This natural reaction suggests that equality is intimately connected with notions of fairness. I say intimately connected with advisedly. On my view, equality is a subtopic of the more general and even more complex topic of fairness. Specifically, concern about inequality is that portion of our concern about fairness that focuses on how people fare relative to others. So, our concern for equality is not separable from our concern for a certain aspect of fairness; they are part and parcel of a single concern. We say that certain inequalities are objectionable because they are unfair; but by the same token, we say that there is a certain kind of unfairness in being worse off than another through no fault or choice of one s own. This explains the importance of the no fault or choice clause. Egalitarians are not committed to the view that deserved inequalities if there are any are as bad as undeserved ones. In fact, I think deserved inequalities are not bad at all. Rather, what

9 13. Inequality 335 is objectionable is some being worse off than others through no fault or choice of their own. The reason for this is simple. Undeserved inequality is unfair, but deserved inequality is not. The egalitarian is not committed to the implausible view that it is bad for parents or citizens to freely and rationally sacrifice for their descendants so that their descendants will be better off than they. Nor is the egalitarian committed to the implausible view that it is bad for imprisoned criminals to be worse off than regular citizens, if the egalitarian believes that the criminal could have been as well off as others, but freely and rationally chose a life of crime. In such cases, the unequal outcomes are not unfair, and hence not objectionable, because the worse-off are so by their own free choice. These cases presumably differ from those where the worse-off are so because they were unlucky enough to born into poverty, or with severe handicaps, or with the wrong color skin in a racist society. The preceding reminds us that egalitarians are not simply concern with how much inequality obtains, they are concerned with how bad the inequality is. Thus, while there may be more inequality in one situation than another, that needn t be worse if the greater inequality is deserved, but the lesser is not. In thinking about this it helps to remember a simple point. Inequality is rampant in the universe. There are more electrons than protons, more roaches than whales, more numbers than mountains. These inequalities are real. But they are merely factual, descriptive, or arithmetical inequalities. Of the innumerable descriptive inequalities, only a few have normative significance. Egalitarians may argue as to which inequalities have normative significance, or whether some inequalities are more significant than others. But they can agree, I think, that only undeserved inequalities matter. It is, of course, extremely difficult to decide when people are worse off than others through no fault or choice of their own. Egalitarians tend to think this is often, or nearly always, the case. Non-egalitarians tend to think this is rarely, if ever, the case. This raises enormous practical and theoretical issues for egalitarians. But it is important to distinguish the difficulty of determining when inequalities are undeserved from the crucial normative question of whether only undeserved inequalities are objectionable. It is an interesting question to what extent debates between people who think of themselves as egalitarians or non-egalitarians actually turn on whether prevalent inequalities, such as those produced under capitalism, are undeserved.

10 336 Larry S. Temkin Are egalitarians necessarily envious? Are they maliciously covetous or resentful of the possessions or good fortune of another as Webster s Third New International Dictionary defines the term envious? Surely not. When an egalitarian condemns past inequalities between clan leaders and their followers, or servants, she is not maliciously covetous or resentful of the clan leader s possessions or good fortune. Indeed, she may well believe, rightly, that she is much better off than the clan leader ever was. Nevertheless, she believes it is bad because unfair for some to be much worse off than others through no fault or choice of their own. Thus, the egalitarian s judgment is not motivated by envy, but by a sense of fairness. At least, I believe that is what an egalitarian s judgment should be motivated by, whether considering other societies or one s own. D. Milton Friedman reputedly claimed that people can serve only one master, and that master is freedom. Those sharing Friedman s view that the true, or correct, moral theory must be monistic that there can be one and only one true moral ideal often argue against equality by appealing to examples like the following. Imagine two alternative outcomes, A and B. A and B are each perfectly equal outcomes, that is, within each outcome each person would be as well off as every other. However, those in A would all be much better off than those in B in terms of resources, welfare, freedom, opportunity, etc. Surely, A is a better outcome than B, since everyone in A is equally well off, and much better off than those in B. However, A is not better than B regarding equality; they are equivalent, since, by hypothesis, both are perfect regarding equality. Monistic egalitarians those who believed that equality was the only moral value would have no reason to prefer A to B. But this, we agree, is implausible. A is better than B. But what does this show? All it shows is that if we are egalitarians we should be pluralists. We should admit that equality is not our only ideal, that it is but one, among others, that we value. Correspondingly, we should distinguish between our purely egalitarian judgments our judgments about how situations compare regarding equality, and hence the judgments we would make if equality were our only concern and our all things considered judgments our judgments about how situations compare after giving each ideal its due weight. If we were committed to moral monism, arguments such as the preceding would successfully undermine egalitarianism. Though

11 13. Inequality 337 the stubborn monistic egalitarian could, of course, implausibly insist that there is nothing to choose between A and B, since inequality is all that matters. But there is little reason to believe moral monism is true, and good reason to believe it is false. Equality is not the only ideal that would, if exclusively pursued, have implausible or even terrible implications. The same is true of justice, utility, freedom, and probably every other ideal. Recall Kant s view that justice be done though the heavens should fall. Do we really think, with Kant, that it would be wrong to falsely imprison an innocent man for even five minutes, if that were necessary to save 1,000,000 innocent lives? Or consider the principle of utility, which would require us to torture an innocent person if only enough people had their lives improved by the tiniest of amounts because of our action. Or finally, consider the implications of unfettered freedom to act as one wants without government interference, as long as one doesn t interfere with the rights or liberties of others. Such a principle could allow complete neglect of the least fortunate, even regarding basic necessities such as food, clothing, shelter, and healthcare. Considerations such as these do not show that each of these moral ideals should be rejected, only that morality is complex. As noted, one of the most widely debated issues among egalitarians concerns what kind of equality is desirable. This issue is extremely important, both practically and theoretically. Clearly, different outcomes or choices will seem better or worse regarding equality, depending on what kind of inequality one is concerned with. Moreover, one must be particularly careful in determining what kind of inequality matters, since, as has long been recognized, equality of one kind will often require inequality of another. For example, equality of income may correlate with inequality of need satisfaction between the handicapped and the healthy, and vice versa. Similarly, in many circumstances equality of opportunity may correlate with inequality of welfare, and vice versa. Many assume that concern for one kind of equality rules out concern for others. Correspondingly, philosophers favoring different conceptions of what kind of equality matters have gone to great lengths illustrating cases where rival conceptions have implausible implications. Unfortunately, on a pluralistic view of morality the assumption in question is dubious. Perhaps different kinds of equality matter in different contexts. Or perhaps even in the same context there are strong reasons for promoting different kinds of equality. Thus, the question equality of what? may have several plausible answers.

12 338 Larry S. Temkin As we have just seen, the fact that ideals like equality, utility, or freedom sometimes have implausible, or even terrible, implications, does not show that those ideals do not matter. It merely shows that each ideal, alone, is not all that matters. Likewise, the fact that different conceptions of what kind of equality matters sometimes have implausible implications does not necessarily show that those conceptions do not matter. Equality, like morality itself, is complex. And more than one conception may be relevant to our all things considered egalitarian judgments. My own view is that a large component of the egalitarian s concern should be with equality of welfare; but as I use it welfare is a technical term that needs to be interpreted broadly, and with great care. It must appropriately include, among other things, most of the elements that Amartya Sen carefully distinguishes in his sophisticated account of functionings, capability sets, freedom, agency, and well-being. 6 However, I also think the egalitarian should give weight to equality of opportunity. Suppose, for example, that we lived in a world not too unlike the actual one, in which a relatively small percentage of people were very well off, while the vast majority were much worse off. Concern for equality of welfare would impel us to raise everyone to the level of the best-off. But suppose, for empirical reasons of limited resources, this were not possible. Concern for equality of welfare might then impel us to redistribute from the better-off to the worse-off. But if the percentage of better-off were small, this might do little to actually improve the lot of the worse-off, its main effect might be to reduce the better-off to the level of the worse-off. Even if we think this would be an improvement regarding equality of welfare, we might agree it would not be an improvement all things considered. Thus, we might conclude that in such a case we must accept, even if not happily, a significantly unequal situation regarding welfare. Still, we might distinguish two versions of this scenario. In one version, the better-off group are members of a hereditary aristocracy. They, and their descendants, have been guaranteed a place in the better-off group. Likewise, the members of the worse-off group, and their descendants, are destined to remain in the worseoff group regardless of their abilities or efforts. In the second version there is genuine equality of opportunity. At birth, each person, and her descendants, has an equal chance of ending up in the better-off group. By hypothesis, the two versions of the scenario are equivalent regarding equality of welfare. Yet, I think many would agree the

13 13. Inequality 339 second is better than the first all things considered, and better largely, if not wholly, because it is better regarding equality of opportunity. I think, then, that qua egalitarian, one should care about equality of opportunity. But this concern should be in addition to, rather than in place of, a concern for equality of welfare. The second situation may be perfect regarding equality of opportunity but it still involves many people who are worse off than others through no choice of their own. The egalitarian, qua egalitarian, will regard this as objectionable. It would be better, regarding equality, if, in addition to everyone having equal opportunities, they actually fared equally well. Does the egalitarian have to make room in her spectrum of concerns for other kinds of equality? Perhaps, but I am inclined to think that, theoretically at least, the plausible elements of most other kinds of equality will be captured by a sufficiently sophisticated interpretation of welfare. Still, in the real world it may be extremely difficult or undesirable to pursue equality of welfare, for a host of political, practical, and moral reasons. Given this, it may well be better to pursue equality of other kinds, such as income, resources, primary goods, or need satisfaction. However, we must be careful to distinguish our ultimate reasons for advocating one kind of equality over another. There may well be a difference between the option that is most desirable, from an egalitarian perspective, and the option that is most desirable or feasible all things considered, and we must not fool ourselves that the latter is necessarily the same as the former. Part II The considerations in this part are addressed to those who accept non-instrumental egalitarianism. I claimed that according to this position it is bad because unfair for some to be worse off than others through no fault or choice of their own. Unfortunately, as we shall see next, it is one thing to note such a position, quite another to accurately interpret it, or unpack what it involves. As noted, most philosophical discussions of equality have focused on two questions: Is equality really desirable? And what kind of equality should we seek? These are important questions. But egalitarians must address a slew of other questions as well, including, but by no means are limited to, the following: When is one situation worse than another regarding inequality? Does inequality matter between groups, or between individuals? Does in-

14 340 Larry S. Temkin equality matter differently at high levels than low levels? Is inequality affected by variations in population size? If one compares individuals with respect to inequality, should one focus on their lives taken as complete wholes, on contemporaneous portions of their lives say, the elderly of today with the youth of today or on corresponding segments of their lives say, the elderly of today with the elderly of tomorrow? Those who believe that inequality matters must ultimately address each of these questions, and others as well. After all, it does no good to claim that inequality matters, if one cannot determine what factors affect inequality and whether one situation is worse than another regarding inequality. I believe the answers to the preceding questions are not only interesting and important, in many cases they are perplexing, disturbing, and controversial. They have significant implications not only for our understanding of equality, but for our understanding of morality itself, including the structure and relation of our moral ideals. Unfortunately, I cannot defend these claims here. Instead, I wish to present a brief overview of a few conclusions I have arrived at in thinking about these questions, and convey some sense for the kinds of considerations underlying my thinking. Most of this part will discuss the general question, when is one situation worse than another regarding inequality? This is my book s central question, and it is one that led me both to develop a new approach to understanding inequality, and to consider the other, more specific, questions. After discussing the general question, I shall briefly comment on the other questions noted above. For the interested reader, extensive arguments are available in Inequality. 7 A. When is one situation worse than another regarding inequality? In some cases the answer to this question can be easily given. We know, for instance, that among equally deserving people a situation where some are worse off than others is worse than one where everyone is equal, in terms of inequality. We also know that among equally deserving people the inequality in a situation would be worse if the gaps between the better- and worse-off were large, than if they were small. Consider, however, a situation where many are better-off, and a few are worse-off. How would the inequality in such a situation compare to the inequality in a situation where a few are better-off and many are worse-off? How would both of these compare to a situation where the better- and worseoff groups were similar in size? It turns out that these are com-

15 13. Inequality 341 plicated questions, and ones to which several plausible but conflicting answers might be given. For example, one way we may judge inequality is in terms of how gratuitous the inequality seems. Consider a situation where many are better-off, and only a few are worse-off. Call this the first situation. In such a situation the inequality may seem pointless and unnecessary. If direct redistribution were possible to bring about equality, the better-off would hardly lose anything and the worse-off would gain tremendously. Hence, the inequality in the first situation may seem particularly offensive as there seems to be virtually nothing gained by it. Next consider the situation where half of the people are betteroff, and half are worse-off. Call this the middle situation. It seems that in the middle situation redistribution would cost a lot. A large number would have to sacrifice a great deal to achieve equality. In such a situation, we could understand the reluctance of the better-off to redistribute, and while we might think it would be good if they were to voluntarily do this, we might not think they were morally required to do this. In that situation, then, the inequality might strike us as more excusable, and hence less disturbing, than the inequality in the first situation. Finally, consider a situation where only a few are better-off, and the vast majority are worse-off. Call this the last situation. In the last situation direct redistribution from better- to worse-off would involve tremendous loss for some, with virtually no gain for those thus benefited. Therefore, the inequality might seem least offensive in the last situation, where the cost of the inequality might seem smallest, and the gain highest. This position might be summed up as follows. Egalitarians will think it unfair if, through no fault or choice of their own, some are badly-off e.g., struggling to survive while others are well-off e.g., living lives of ease and comfort. But from one perspective, at least, egalitarians may be most offended if just a few are badlyoff while the vast majority are well-off, since the inequality then seems particularly gratuitous. Thus, in accordance with this way of thinking, it will seem that the three situations are getting better and better regarding inequality. Another reason egalitarians may think the three situations are getting better and better is that it appears to be less and less the case that those who are worse-off are being especially victimized by the situation. In the first situation, for instance, it is as if the entire burden of the inequality is borne by those few who are unfortunate enough to be among the worse-off. Given that those

16 342 Larry S. Temkin few people are much worse off than every other member of their world, it may seem that they have a very large complaint regarding inequality, and correspondingly, that the inequality is especially offensive. By contrast, the last situation s inequality may seem relatively inoffensive. In that situation each member of the worse-off group is as well off as all but a few of the other members of her world. Hence, in that world it may seem as if nobody has much to complain about regarding inequality. This view is plausible, and it expresses itself in the way we react to the actions of bullies or tyrants. If a bully or tyrant decides to humiliate certain people, from a utilitarian standpoint we may well hope that it is a small portion of the population that is so mistreated. Nevertheless, from an egalitarian standpoint we may well find the mistreatment most offensive if it applies to only a small segment of the population. Thus, it may seem particularly unfair for a few people to bear the brunt of their world s unfairness; and it may seem especially galling that the vast majority should be leading normal happy lives, while one small segment of it gets crushed beneath the heel of oppression. One way of putting this point is that certain egalitarian intuitions are especially attuned to instances of invidious or capricious discrimination where a particular person or small number of people is singled out for discriminatory treatment. In fact, I think it is the singling out in this way of an individual or small number that is the paradigmatic case of where we judge a harmful discrimination to be grossly unfair. I suspect this element of our thinking may be one of the reasons it has taken many people so long to recognize pervasive discrimination against women. Even though women were and still are being treated very differently than men, half of the population was being treated in the same way. Because of this, and because of the fact that certain of our egalitarian intuitions are especially attuned to discrimination against individuals and small numbers, it was easy for both men and women to realize that women were being treated differently, and yet fail to recognize that women were actually being discriminated against. There are, then, several ways of thinking that might lead one to think the three situations are getting better and better regarding inequality. But there are also ways of thinking that might lead one to judge that the situations first get worse, then better. It is easy to be drawn to such an ordering by reasoning as follows. In the first situation, everyone is perfectly equal except, regrettably, for a few isolated individuals. In that situation, then,

17 13. Inequality 343 the worse-off represent an ever-so-slight perturbation in an otherwise perfectly homogeneous system. Therefore, since in the first situation there is just a slight deviation from absolute equality that situation may seem nearly perfect regarding inequality. In the middle situation, the deviation from absolute equality is much larger. Half the population is much better off than the other half. In the last situation, there is once again just an ever-so-slight deviation from absolute equality. Everyone is perfectly equal except, regrettably, for a few isolated individuals. Like the first situation, therefore, that world may appear almost perfect regarding inequality. In sum, it seems there is a natural and plausible way of looking at the three situations such that we would judge they first get worse, then better. Another line of thought also supports the worse, then better ordering. In the first situation, only a few people have a complaint regarding inequality, so as large as their complaint may be that situation s inequality may not seem too bad. However, in the middle situation, it may seem both that a large number have a complaint half of the population, and that the magnitude of their complaints will be large they are, after all, worse off than half the population through no fault or choice of their own. In the last world, on the other hand, the situation may seem analogous to, though the reverse of, the one obtaining in the first. Although almost everyone has something to complain about, it may seem that the size of their complaints will be virtually negligible, as they are as well off as almost every other person in the situation. Hence, as with the first situation, the inequality may not seem too bad. It seems, then, there are egalitarian reasons to rank the three situations as getting worse, then better, as well as reasons to rank them as just getting better. Still other reasons seem to support ranking them as getting worse and worse. In the first situation, only a few people are worse off than the better-off. In the middle situation, half the population are worse off than the better-off. In the last situation, virtually everybody is worse off than the betteroff. Since the size of the gap between better- and worse-off is the same in each situation, we may conclude that the first situation is the best regarding inequality, and the last situation is worst. Before going on, let me note two examples where such reasoning seems to be in involved. First, if one asks audiences to think of the worst periods of inequality in human history as I have many times over the years one of the most common responses is that of medieval Europe. But the common conception of medieval

18 344 Larry S. Temkin Europe involves a few kings, queens, and noblemen living in the lap of luxury while the vast majority peasants and serfs struggle to survive. Such a situation resembles the last situation, rather than the first or middle one. And while here, as elsewhere, I think people s intuitive responses may be partly influenced by non-egalitarian factors as well as various different egalitarian factors, I think one reason so many think of medieval Europe as among the worst periods of inequality is that the number of worseoff is so large relative to the fortunate few who are well off. This way of thinking is compatible with the judgment that the three situations are getting worse and worse, but not with the ways of thinking discussed previously. Another example where such thinking seems operative is illustrated by a Marxian analysis of the advance of capitalism. On a Marxian view, as capitalism advances more and more people are squeezed out of the ranks of the bourgeoisie into the ranks of the proletariat; hence, fewer and fewer people come to reap the benefits of capitalism. Now whatever one thinks of its ultimate accuracy, it must be admitted that as stories go a Marxian analysis of capitalism exerts a strong pull on one s egalitarian intuitions. Specifically, egalitarians would find advancing capitalism increasingly objectionable for at least two reasons: first, because the rich become richer and the poor at least relatively poorer; and second, because the ranks of the worse-off swell and the ranks of the better-off shrink. It is the latter point that concerns us here. It suggests that certain egalitarian intuitions will be increasingly offended as more and more people are worse-off relative to the better-off. These intuitions support the judgment that the three situations are getting worse and worse. This discussion has been vastly oversimplified. But I hope to have conveyed some sense for why I claim inequality is complex. There are many different positions, or aspects, capable of underlying and influencing our egalitarian judgments. In fact, in my book I argue there are at least twelve such aspects. I do not claim each of these aspects is equally appealing. But I do believe each represents elements of the egalitarian s thinking that are not easily dismissed. Given that equality s different aspects often diverge in the judgments they yield, and that, on examination, many apparently rest on contrary views, one may come to conclude that the notion of equality is largely inconsistent and severely limited. Alternatively, one may try to maintain that it is complex, multi-faceted, and

19 13. Inequality 345 partially incomplete. Either way, once one understands what the notion of equality involves, many of one s common-sense judgments about equality will need to be revised. Reflecting on considerations like the preceding, led me to develop a new way of thinking about inequality. The common view is that the notion of inequality is simple, holistic, and essentially distributive. This view is thoroughly misleading the notion of inequality is complex, individualistic, and essentially comparative. Let me briefly explain. Simple versus complex. People have long recognized that there are complicated issues connected with inequality, such as whether inequality is truly undesirable, and if so, with respect to what. Still, most have thought the notion of inequality itself is simple. We all know what equality is, it has been thought, that s where everybody has the same amount of x for whatever x we are interested in. Similarly, we all know what inequality is, that s where some have more x than others. What could be simpler? Thus, it has been assumed that once we determine with respect to what, if anything, we should care about inequality, it will be easy to rank situations regarding inequality. As we have seen, there is reason to reject this. Inequality is very complex, as many aspects with different implications underlie and influence our egalitarian judgments. Holistic versus individualistic. Most who learn that I work on inequality immediately ask something like the following: inequality between whom: blacks and whites, women and men, Americans and Ethiopians, or homosexuals and heterosexuals? The assumption is that the egalitarian should be concerned about in equality between groups or societies. Again, there are powerful reasons to question this assumption. The notion of inequality has a strong individualistic component. Looking at situations we are capable of making judgments as to which individuals fare better or worse regarding inequality. Thus, for any situation where some are better off than others through no fault or choice of their own, we can say that the best-off have nothing to complain about regarding inequality since they are already as well off as every other member of their situation while the worst-off have the most to complain about regarding inequality since, by hypothesis, they are worse off than every other member of their situation. Moreover, on reflection, not only can we make judgments about how different individuals fare with respect to inequality, but our overall judgments regarding inequality are generally based on how individuals fare regarding inequality.

20 346 Larry S. Temkin In addition, it seems clear that groups or societies aren t the proper objects of moral concern, individuals are. Thus, although different individuals or social institutions often discriminate against groups, and though, for political and practical reasons we may need to focus on groups in responding to such discrimination, our ultimate concern is for the individual members of the affected groups. While on average whites may be much better off than blacks, some blacks will be much better off than others, and some whites will be much worse off than some blacks. Correspondingly, insofar as one is concerned about inequality, one will favor transfers from better-off whites to worse-off blacks, but should oppose transfers except, perhaps, for indirect long term reasons from worse-off whites to better-off blacks. Likewise, one should favor transfers from better-off blacks to worse-off blacks, or for that matter, from better-off blacks to worse-off whites. Similarly, for the case of men and women, or other cases of general inequality between groups or societies. Essentially distributive versus essentially comparative. I agree that the egalitarian is not merely concerned with how much good obtains, but with how the good is distributed. But, fundamentally, the concern for equality is not so much essentially distributive, as it is essentially comparative. Equality is a relation between individuals and, as previously suggested, the egalitarian s fundamental concern is with how individuals fare relative to each other. B. Does inequality matter more at high levels or low levels? This is a question about which there has been much confusion. Some argue that inequality matters more at high levels than low levels because they think that only at high levels can one afford the luxury of equality. So, for example, they point out that in a situation of extreme scarcity, inequality might allow some to live, while perfect equality might result in everyone dying. Others argue that inequality matters the same at high and low levels. They claim that whether one is at level 1,000 or level 1,000,000 makes no difference to how bad it would be to be worse off than another by 1,000 units, since in each case it would take an increase of the same amount namely 1,000 to make you equal with the other. In addition, many economists measures of inequality are indifferent between proportional increases in people s levels. So, on those measures, the inequality between someone at level 1 and someone at level 10 would be just as bad as the inequality between someone at level 100 and someone at level Economists have as-

Philosophy 285 Fall, 2007 Dick Arneson Overview of John Rawls, A Theory of Justice. Views of Rawls s achievement:

Philosophy 285 Fall, 2007 Dick Arneson Overview of John Rawls, A Theory of Justice. Views of Rawls s achievement: 1 Philosophy 285 Fall, 2007 Dick Arneson Overview of John Rawls, A Theory of Justice Views of Rawls s achievement: G. A. Cohen: I believe that at most two books in the history of Western political philosophy

More information

CHAPTER 19 MARKET SYSTEMS AND NORMATIVE CLAIMS Microeconomics in Context (Goodwin, et al.), 2 nd Edition

CHAPTER 19 MARKET SYSTEMS AND NORMATIVE CLAIMS Microeconomics in Context (Goodwin, et al.), 2 nd Edition CHAPTER 19 MARKET SYSTEMS AND NORMATIVE CLAIMS Microeconomics in Context (Goodwin, et al.), 2 nd Edition Chapter Summary This final chapter brings together many of the themes previous chapters have explored

More information

Ethics Handout 18 Rawls, Classical Utilitarianism and Nagel, Equality

Ethics Handout 18 Rawls, Classical Utilitarianism and Nagel, Equality 24.231 Ethics Handout 18 Rawls, Classical Utilitarianism and Nagel, Equality The Utilitarian Principle of Distribution: Society is rightly ordered, and therefore just, when its major institutions are arranged

More information

Politics between Philosophy and Democracy

Politics between Philosophy and Democracy Leopold Hess Politics between Philosophy and Democracy In the present paper I would like to make some comments on a classic essay of Michael Walzer Philosophy and Democracy. The main purpose of Walzer

More information

Definition: Institution public system of rules which defines offices and positions with their rights and duties, powers and immunities p.

Definition: Institution public system of rules which defines offices and positions with their rights and duties, powers and immunities p. RAWLS Project: to interpret the initial situation, formulate principles of choice, and then establish which principles should be adopted. The principles of justice provide an assignment of fundamental

More information

What Is Unfair about Unequal Brute Luck? An Intergenerational Puzzle

What Is Unfair about Unequal Brute Luck? An Intergenerational Puzzle https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-018-00053-5 What Is Unfair about Unequal Brute Luck? An Intergenerational Puzzle Simon Beard 1 Received: 16 November 2017 /Revised: 29 May 2018 /Accepted: 27 December 2018

More information

RAWLS DIFFERENCE PRINCIPLE: ABSOLUTE vs. RELATIVE INEQUALITY

RAWLS DIFFERENCE PRINCIPLE: ABSOLUTE vs. RELATIVE INEQUALITY RAWLS DIFFERENCE PRINCIPLE: ABSOLUTE vs. RELATIVE INEQUALITY Geoff Briggs PHIL 350/400 // Dr. Ryan Wasserman Spring 2014 June 9 th, 2014 {Word Count: 2711} [1 of 12] {This page intentionally left blank

More information

Do we have a strong case for open borders?

Do we have a strong case for open borders? Do we have a strong case for open borders? Joseph Carens [1987] challenges the popular view that admission of immigrants by states is only a matter of generosity and not of obligation. He claims that the

More information

Rawls versus the Anarchist: Justice and Legitimacy

Rawls versus the Anarchist: Justice and Legitimacy Rawls versus the Anarchist: Justice and Legitimacy Walter E. Schaller Texas Tech University APA Central Division April 2005 Section 1: The Anarchist s Argument In a recent article, Justification and Legitimacy,

More information

Meena Krishnamurthy a a Assistant Professor, Department of Philosophy, Associate

Meena Krishnamurthy a a Assistant Professor, Department of Philosophy, Associate This article was downloaded by: [Meena Krishnamurthy] On: 20 August 2013, At: 10:48 Publisher: Routledge Informa Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954 Registered office: Mortimer

More information

John Rawls THEORY OF JUSTICE

John Rawls THEORY OF JUSTICE John Rawls THEORY OF JUSTICE THE ROLE OF JUSTICE Justice is the first virtue of social institutions, as truth is of systems of thought. A theory however elegant and economical must be rejected or revised

More information

When Does Equality Matter? T. M. Scanlon. Lecture 1: Introduction. Our country, and the world, are marked by extraordinarily high levels of

When Does Equality Matter? T. M. Scanlon. Lecture 1: Introduction. Our country, and the world, are marked by extraordinarily high levels of When Does Equality Matter? T. M. Scanlon Lecture 1: Introduction Our country, and the world, are marked by extraordinarily high levels of inequality. This inequality raises important empirical questions,

More information

The limits of background justice. Thomas Porter. Rawls says that the primary subject of justice is what he calls the basic structure of

The limits of background justice. Thomas Porter. Rawls says that the primary subject of justice is what he calls the basic structure of The limits of background justice Thomas Porter Rawls says that the primary subject of justice is what he calls the basic structure of society. The basic structure is, roughly speaking, the way in which

More information

At a time when political philosophy seemed nearly stagnant, John Rawls

At a time when political philosophy seemed nearly stagnant, John Rawls Bronwyn Edwards 17.01 Justice 1. Evaluate Rawls' arguments for his conception of Democratic Equality. You may focus either on the informal argument (and the contrasts with Natural Liberty and Liberal Equality)

More information

Assignment to make up for missed class on August 29, 2011 due to Irene

Assignment to make up for missed class on August 29, 2011 due to Irene SS141-3SA Macroeconomics Assignment to make up for missed class on August 29, 2011 due to Irene Read pages 442-445 (copies attached) of Mankiw's "The Political Philosophy of Redistributing Income". Which

More information

Equality, Priority, and the Levelling Down Objection *

Equality, Priority, and the Levelling Down Objection * * I. Introduction This essay aims to clarify a number of issues regarding egalitarianism. These include the relation between equality and priority, and whether one should be a non-instrumental egalitarian

More information

Phil 115, June 20, 2007 Justice as fairness as a political conception: the fact of reasonable pluralism and recasting the ideas of Theory

Phil 115, June 20, 2007 Justice as fairness as a political conception: the fact of reasonable pluralism and recasting the ideas of Theory Phil 115, June 20, 2007 Justice as fairness as a political conception: the fact of reasonable pluralism and recasting the ideas of Theory The problem with the argument for stability: In his discussion

More information

CONTEXTUALISM AND GLOBAL JUSTICE

CONTEXTUALISM AND GLOBAL JUSTICE CONTEXTUALISM AND GLOBAL JUSTICE 1. Introduction There are two sets of questions that have featured prominently in recent debates about distributive justice. One of these debates is that between universalism

More information

Why Does Inequality Matter? T. M. Scanlon. Chapter 8: Unequal Outcomes. It is well known that there has been an enormous increase in inequality in the

Why Does Inequality Matter? T. M. Scanlon. Chapter 8: Unequal Outcomes. It is well known that there has been an enormous increase in inequality in the Why Does Inequality Matter? T. M. Scanlon Chapter 8: Unequal Outcomes It is well known that there has been an enormous increase in inequality in the United States and other developed economies in recent

More information

The limits of background justice. Thomas Porter. Social Philosophy & Policy volume 30, issues 1 2. Cambridge University Press

The limits of background justice. Thomas Porter. Social Philosophy & Policy volume 30, issues 1 2. Cambridge University Press The limits of background justice Thomas Porter Social Philosophy & Policy volume 30, issues 1 2 Cambridge University Press Abstract The argument from background justice is that conformity to Lockean principles

More information

Phil 115, May 24, 2007 The threat of utilitarianism

Phil 115, May 24, 2007 The threat of utilitarianism Phil 115, May 24, 2007 The threat of utilitarianism Review: Alchemy v. System According to the alchemy interpretation, Rawls s project is to convince everyone, on the basis of assumptions that he expects

More information

AN EGALITARIAN THEORY OF JUSTICE 1

AN EGALITARIAN THEORY OF JUSTICE 1 AN EGALITARIAN THEORY OF JUSTICE 1 John Rawls THE ROLE OF JUSTICE Justice is the first virtue of social institutions, as truth is of systems of thought. A theory however elegant and economical must be

More information

Controversy Liberalism, Democracy and the Ethics of Votingponl_

Controversy Liberalism, Democracy and the Ethics of Votingponl_ , 223 227 Controversy Liberalism, Democracy and the Ethics of Votingponl_1359 223..227 Annabelle Lever London School of Economics This article summarises objections to compulsory voting developed in my

More information

Any non-welfarist method of policy assessment violates the Pareto principle: A comment

Any non-welfarist method of policy assessment violates the Pareto principle: A comment Any non-welfarist method of policy assessment violates the Pareto principle: A comment Marc Fleurbaey, Bertil Tungodden September 2001 1 Introduction Suppose it is admitted that when all individuals prefer

More information

1 Aggregating Preferences

1 Aggregating Preferences ECON 301: General Equilibrium III (Welfare) 1 Intermediate Microeconomics II, ECON 301 General Equilibrium III: Welfare We are done with the vital concepts of general equilibrium Its power principally

More information

VALUING DISTRIBUTIVE EQUALITY CLAIRE ANITA BREMNER. A thesis submitted to the Department of Philosophy. in conformity with the requirements for

VALUING DISTRIBUTIVE EQUALITY CLAIRE ANITA BREMNER. A thesis submitted to the Department of Philosophy. in conformity with the requirements for VALUING DISTRIBUTIVE EQUALITY by CLAIRE ANITA BREMNER A thesis submitted to the Department of Philosophy in conformity with the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts Queen s University Kingston,

More information

Jan Narveson and James P. Sterba

Jan Narveson and James P. Sterba 1 Introduction RISTOTLE A held that equals should be treated equally and unequals unequally. Yet Aristotle s ideal of equality was a relatively formal one that allowed for considerable inequality. Likewise,

More information

In Defense of Liberal Equality

In Defense of Liberal Equality Public Reason 9 (1-2): 99-108 M. E. Newhouse University of Surrey 2017 by Public Reason Abstract: In A Theory of Justice, Rawls concludes that individuals in the original position would choose to adopt

More information

The Provision of Public Goods, and the Matter of the Revelation of True Preferences: Two Views

The Provision of Public Goods, and the Matter of the Revelation of True Preferences: Two Views The Provision of Public Goods, and the Matter of the Revelation of True Preferences: Two Views Larry Levine Department of Economics, University of New Brunswick Introduction The two views which are agenda

More information

Phil 115, June 13, 2007 The argument from the original position: set-up and intuitive presentation and the two principles over average utility

Phil 115, June 13, 2007 The argument from the original position: set-up and intuitive presentation and the two principles over average utility Phil 115, June 13, 2007 The argument from the original position: set-up and intuitive presentation and the two principles over average utility What is the role of the original position in Rawls s theory?

More information

1100 Ethics July 2016

1100 Ethics July 2016 1100 Ethics July 2016 perhaps, those recommended by Brock. His insight that this creates an irresolvable moral tragedy, given current global economic circumstances, is apt. Blake does not ask, however,

More information

RECONCILING LIBERTY AND EQUALITY: JUSTICE AS FAIRNESS. John Rawls s A Theory of Justice presents a theory called justice as fairness.

RECONCILING LIBERTY AND EQUALITY: JUSTICE AS FAIRNESS. John Rawls s A Theory of Justice presents a theory called justice as fairness. RECONCILING LIBERTY AND EQUALITY: JUSTICE AS FAIRNESS 1. Two Principles of Justice John Rawls s A Theory of Justice presents a theory called justice as fairness. That theory comprises two principles of

More information

Equality, Justice and Legitimacy in Selection 1. (This is the pre-proof draft of the article, which was published in the

Equality, Justice and Legitimacy in Selection 1. (This is the pre-proof draft of the article, which was published in the Equality, Justice and Legitimacy in Selection 1 (This is the pre-proof draft of the article, which was published in the Journal of Moral Philosophy, 9 (2012), 8-30. Matthew Clayton University of Warwick

More information

Distributive Justice Rawls

Distributive Justice Rawls Distributive Justice Rawls 1. Justice as Fairness: Imagine that you have a cake to divide among several people, including yourself. How do you divide it among them in a just manner? If any of the slices

More information

Newcastle Fairness Commission Principles of Fairness

Newcastle Fairness Commission Principles of Fairness Newcastle Fairness Commission Principles of Fairness 15 December 2011 Context The Newcastle Fairness Commission was set up by the City Council in summer 2011. Knowing that they would face budget cuts and

More information

An appealing and original aspect of Mathias Risse s book On Global

An appealing and original aspect of Mathias Risse s book On Global BOOK SYMPOSIUM: ON GLOBAL JUSTICE On Collective Ownership of the Earth Anna Stilz An appealing and original aspect of Mathias Risse s book On Global Justice is his argument for humanity s collective ownership

More information

Comments on Justin Weinberg s Is Government Supererogation Possible? Public Reason Political Philosophy Symposium Friday October 17, 2008

Comments on Justin Weinberg s Is Government Supererogation Possible? Public Reason Political Philosophy Symposium Friday October 17, 2008 Helena de Bres Wellesley College Department of Philosophy hdebres@wellesley.edu Comments on Justin Weinberg s Is Government Supererogation Possible? Public Reason Political Philosophy Symposium Friday

More information

Equality and Priority

Equality and Priority Equality and Priority MARTIN PETERSON AND SVEN OVE HANSSON Philosophy Unit, Royal Institute of Technology, Sweden This article argues that, contrary to the received view, prioritarianism and egalitarianism

More information

University of Alberta

University of Alberta University of Alberta Rawls and the Practice of Political Equality by Jay Makarenko A thesis submitted to the Faculty of Graduate Studies and Research in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the

More information

When Does Equality Matter? 1. T. M. Scanlon. The first theme of this paper is that we have many different reasons for being

When Does Equality Matter? 1. T. M. Scanlon. The first theme of this paper is that we have many different reasons for being When Does Equality Matter? 1 T. M. Scanlon The first theme of this paper is that we have many different reasons for being opposed to inequality. Only some of these reasons are egalitarian that is to say,

More information

Democracy As Equality

Democracy As Equality 1 Democracy As Equality Thomas Christiano Society is organized by terms of association by which all are bound. The problem is to determine who has the right to define these terms of association. Democrats

More information

Aggregation and the Separateness of Persons

Aggregation and the Separateness of Persons Aggregation and the Separateness of Persons Iwao Hirose McGill University and CAPPE, Melbourne September 29, 2007 1 Introduction According to some moral theories, the gains and losses of different individuals

More information

Proceduralism and Epistemic Value of Democracy

Proceduralism and Epistemic Value of Democracy 1 Paper to be presented at the symposium on Democracy and Authority by David Estlund in Oslo, December 7-9 2009 (Draft) Proceduralism and Epistemic Value of Democracy Some reflections and questions on

More information

The Limits of Self-Defense

The Limits of Self-Defense The Limits of Self-Defense Jeff McMahan Necessity Does not Require the Infliction of the Least Harm 1 According to the traditional understanding of necessity in self-defense, a defensive act is unnecessary,

More information

Voting Criteria April

Voting Criteria April Voting Criteria 21-301 2018 30 April 1 Evaluating voting methods In the last session, we learned about different voting methods. In this session, we will focus on the criteria we use to evaluate whether

More information

Matthew Adler, a law professor at the Duke University, has written an amazing book in defense

Matthew Adler, a law professor at the Duke University, has written an amazing book in defense Well-Being and Fair Distribution: Beyond Cost-Benefit Analysis By MATTHEW D. ADLER Oxford University Press, 2012. xx + 636 pp. 55.00 1. Introduction Matthew Adler, a law professor at the Duke University,

More information

FAIRNESS VERSUS WELFARE. Louis Kaplow & Steven Shavell. Thesis: Policy Analysis Should Be Based Exclusively on Welfare Economics

FAIRNESS VERSUS WELFARE. Louis Kaplow & Steven Shavell. Thesis: Policy Analysis Should Be Based Exclusively on Welfare Economics FAIRNESS VERSUS WELFARE Louis Kaplow & Steven Shavell Thesis: Policy Analysis Should Be Based Exclusively on Welfare Economics Plan of Book! Define/contrast welfare economics & fairness! Support thesis

More information

Global Aspirations versus Local Plumbing: Comment: on Nussbaum. by Richard A. Epstein

Global Aspirations versus Local Plumbing: Comment: on Nussbaum. by Richard A. Epstein Global Aspirations versus Local Plumbing: Comment: on Nussbaum by Richard A. Epstein Martha Nussbaum has long been a champion of the capabilities approach which constantly worries about what state people

More information

Introduction to Equality and Justice: The Demands of Equality, Peter Vallentyne, ed., Routledge, The Demands of Equality: An Introduction

Introduction to Equality and Justice: The Demands of Equality, Peter Vallentyne, ed., Routledge, The Demands of Equality: An Introduction Introduction to Equality and Justice: The Demands of Equality, Peter Vallentyne, ed., Routledge, 2003. The Demands of Equality: An Introduction Peter Vallentyne This is the second volume of Equality and

More information

DEMOCRACY AND EQUALITY

DEMOCRACY AND EQUALITY The Philosophical Quarterly 2007 ISSN 0031 8094 doi: 10.1111/j.1467-9213.2007.495.x DEMOCRACY AND EQUALITY BY STEVEN WALL Many writers claim that democratic government rests on a principled commitment

More information

David A. Reidy, J.D., Ph.D. University of Tennessee

David A. Reidy, J.D., Ph.D. University of Tennessee 92 AUSLEGUNG Jeff Spinner, The Boundaries of Citizenship: Race, Ethnicity, and Nationality in the Liberal State, Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press, 1994,230 pp. David A. Reidy, J.D., Ph.D.

More information

Suppose that you must make choices that may influence the well-being and the identities of the people who will

Suppose that you must make choices that may influence the well-being and the identities of the people who will Priority or Equality for Possible People? Alex Voorhoeve and Marc Fleurbaey Suppose that you must make choices that may influence the well-being and the identities of the people who will exist, though

More information

S.L. Hurley, Justice, Luck and Knowledge, (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2003), 341 pages. ISBN: (hbk.).

S.L. Hurley, Justice, Luck and Knowledge, (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2003), 341 pages. ISBN: (hbk.). S.L. Hurley, Justice, Luck and Knowledge, (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2003), 341 pages. ISBN: 0-674-01029-9 (hbk.). In this impressive, tightly argued, but not altogether successful book,

More information

Poverty--absolute and relative Inequalities of income and wealth

Poverty--absolute and relative Inequalities of income and wealth Development Ethics The task: provide a normative basis for guiding development decisions Development as a historical process Development as the result of policy choices A role for ethics Normative issues

More information

VI. Rawls and Equality

VI. Rawls and Equality VI. Rawls and Equality A society of free and equal persons Last time, on Justice: Getting What We Are Due 1 Redistributive Taxation Redux Can we justly tax Wilt Chamberlain to redistribute wealth to others?

More information

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. Comment on Steiner's Liberal Theory of Exploitation Author(s): Steven Walt Source: Ethics, Vol. 94, No. 2 (Jan., 1984), pp. 242-247 Published by: The University of Chicago Press Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2380514.

More information

Introduction. Cambridge University Press Global Distributive Justice Chris Armstrong Excerpt More information

Introduction. Cambridge University Press Global Distributive Justice Chris Armstrong Excerpt More information Introduction Protests in favour of global justice are becoming a familiar part of the political landscape. Placards demanding a more just, fair or equal world present a colourful accompaniment to every

More information

24.03: Good Food 3/13/17. Justice and Food Production

24.03: Good Food 3/13/17. Justice and Food Production 1. Food Sovereignty, again Justice and Food Production Before when we talked about food sovereignty (Kyle Powys Whyte reading), the main issue was the protection of a way of life, a culture. In the Thompson

More information

CHAPTER 1 PROLOGUE: VALUES AND PERSPECTIVES

CHAPTER 1 PROLOGUE: VALUES AND PERSPECTIVES CHAPTER 1 PROLOGUE: VALUES AND PERSPECTIVES Final draft July 2009 This Book revolves around three broad kinds of questions: $ What kind of society is this? $ How does it really work? Why is it the way

More information

Cambridge University Press The Cambridge Rawls Lexicon Edited by Jon Mandle and David A. Reidy Excerpt More information

Cambridge University Press The Cambridge Rawls Lexicon Edited by Jon Mandle and David A. Reidy Excerpt More information A in this web service in this web service 1. ABORTION Amuch discussed footnote to the first edition of Political Liberalism takes up the troubled question of abortion in order to illustrate how norms of

More information

Criminal Justice Without Moral Responsibility: Addressing Problems with Consequentialism Dane Shade Hannum

Criminal Justice Without Moral Responsibility: Addressing Problems with Consequentialism Dane Shade Hannum 51 Criminal Justice Without Moral Responsibility: Addressing Problems with Consequentialism Dane Shade Hannum Abstract: This paper grants the hard determinist position that moral responsibility is not

More information

Are Second-Best Tariffs Good Enough?

Are Second-Best Tariffs Good Enough? Are Second-Best Tariffs Good Enough? Alan V. Deardorff The University of Michigan Paper prepared for the Conference Celebrating Professor Rachel McCulloch International Business School Brandeis University

More information

Facts and Principles in Political Constructivism Michael Buckley Lehman College, CUNY

Facts and Principles in Political Constructivism Michael Buckley Lehman College, CUNY Facts and Principles in Political Constructivism Michael Buckley Lehman College, CUNY Abstract: This paper develops a unique exposition about the relationship between facts and principles in political

More information

Immigration. Average # of Interior Removals # of Interior Removals in ,311 81,603

Immigration. Average # of Interior Removals # of Interior Removals in ,311 81,603 Immigration 1. Introduction: Right now, there are over 11 million immigrants living in the United States without authorization or citizenship. Each year, the U.S. government forcibly expels around 100,000

More information

CHAPTER 1 PROLOGUE: VALUES AND PERSPECTIVES

CHAPTER 1 PROLOGUE: VALUES AND PERSPECTIVES CHAPTER 1 PROLOGUE: VALUES AND PERSPECTIVES Final draft July 2009 This Book revolves around three broad kinds of questions: $ What kind of society is this? $ How does it really work? Why is it the way

More information

Justice Green s decision is a sophisticated engagement with some of the issues raised last class about the moral justification of punishment.

Justice Green s decision is a sophisticated engagement with some of the issues raised last class about the moral justification of punishment. PHL271 Handout 9: Sentencing and Restorative Justice We re going to deepen our understanding of the problems surrounding legal punishment by closely examining a recent sentencing decision handed down in

More information

Are Decent Non-Liberal Societies Really Non-Liberal?

Are Decent Non-Liberal Societies Really Non-Liberal? 논문 Are Decent Non-Liberal Societies Really Non-Liberal? Chung, Hun Subject Class Political Philosophy, Practical Ethics Keywords Rawls, The Laws of People, Justice as Fairness, Global Justice, International

More information

The Effects of the Right to Silence on the Innocent s Decision to Remain Silent

The Effects of the Right to Silence on the Innocent s Decision to Remain Silent Preliminary Draft of 6008 The Effects of the Right to Silence on the Innocent s Decision to Remain Silent Shmuel Leshem * Abstract This paper shows that innocent suspects benefit from exercising the right

More information

Chapter 4. Justice and the Law. Justice vs. Law. David Hume. Justice does not dictate a perfect world, but one in which people live up

Chapter 4. Justice and the Law. Justice vs. Law. David Hume. Justice does not dictate a perfect world, but one in which people live up Chapter 4 Justice and the Law Justice vs. Law Law & Justice are very different. Law is often defined as the administration of justice. Law may result in judgments that many feel are unjust Justice: Is

More information

A PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW OF POVERTY

A PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW OF POVERTY REPORT A PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW OF POVERTY Jonathan Wolff, Edward Lamb and Eliana Zur-Szpiro This report explores how poverty has been understood and analysed in contemporary political philosophy. Philosophers

More information

Global Justice and Two Kinds of Liberalism

Global Justice and Two Kinds of Liberalism Global Justice and Two Kinds of Liberalism Christopher Lowry Dept. of Philosophy, Queen s University christopher.r.lowry@gmail.com Paper prepared for CPSA, June 2008 In a recent article, Nagel (2005) distinguishes

More information

Introduction. Cambridge University Press Rawls's Egalitarianism Alexander Kaufman Excerpt More Information

Introduction. Cambridge University Press Rawls's Egalitarianism Alexander Kaufman Excerpt More Information Introduction This study focuses on John Rawls s complex understanding of egalitarian justice. Rawls addresses this subject both in A Theory of Justice andinmanyofhisarticlespublishedbetween1951and1982.inthese

More information

Political Justice, Reciprocity and the Law of Peoples

Political Justice, Reciprocity and the Law of Peoples Political Justice, Reciprocity and the Law of Peoples Hugo El Kholi This paper intends to measure the consequences of Rawls transition from a comprehensive to a political conception of justice on the Law

More information

Last time we discussed a stylized version of the realist view of global society.

Last time we discussed a stylized version of the realist view of global society. Political Philosophy, Spring 2003, 1 The Terrain of a Global Normative Order 1. Realism and Normative Order Last time we discussed a stylized version of the realist view of global society. According to

More information

Utilitarianism, Game Theory and the Social Contract

Utilitarianism, Game Theory and the Social Contract Macalester Journal of Philosophy Volume 14 Issue 1 Spring 2005 Article 7 5-1-2005 Utilitarianism, Game Theory and the Social Contract Daniel Burgess Follow this and additional works at: http://digitalcommons.macalester.edu/philo

More information

POL 343 Democratic Theory and Globalization February 11, "The history of democratic theory II" Introduction

POL 343 Democratic Theory and Globalization February 11, The history of democratic theory II Introduction POL 343 Democratic Theory and Globalization February 11, 2005 "The history of democratic theory II" Introduction Why, and how, does democratic theory revive at the beginning of the nineteenth century?

More information

-Capitalism, Exploitation and Injustice-

-Capitalism, Exploitation and Injustice- UPF - MA Political Philosophy Modern Political Philosophy Elisabet Puigdollers Mas -Capitalism, Exploitation and Injustice- Introduction Although Marx fiercely criticized the theories of justice and some

More information

New Directions for the Capability Approach: Deliberative Democracy and Republicanism

New Directions for the Capability Approach: Deliberative Democracy and Republicanism New Directions for the Capability Approach: Deliberative Democracy and Republicanism Rutger Claassen Published in: Res Publica 15(4)(2009): 421-428 Review essay on: John. M. Alexander, Capabilities and

More information

Great comments! (A lot of them could be germs of term papers )

Great comments! (A lot of them could be germs of term papers ) Phil 290-1: Political Rule February 3, 2014 Great comments! (A lot of them could be germs of term papers ) Some are about the positive view that I sketch at the end of the paper. We ll get to that in two

More information

Chapter Two: Normative Theories of Ethics

Chapter Two: Normative Theories of Ethics Chapter Two: Normative Theories of Ethics This multimedia product and its contents are protected under copyright law. The following are prohibited by law: any public performance or display, including transmission

More information

Why Rawls's Domestic Theory of Justice is Implausible

Why Rawls's Domestic Theory of Justice is Implausible Fudan II Why Rawls's Domestic Theory of Justice is Implausible Thomas Pogge Leitner Professor of Philosophy and International Affairs, Yale 1 Justice versus Ethics The two primary inquiries in moral philosophy,

More information

Problems with the one-person-one-vote Principle

Problems with the one-person-one-vote Principle Problems with the one-person-one-vote Principle [Please note this is a very rough draft. A polished and complete draft will be uploaded closer to the Congress date]. In this paper, I highlight some normative

More information

enforce people s contribution to the general good, as everyone naturally wants to do productive work, if they can find something they enjoy.

enforce people s contribution to the general good, as everyone naturally wants to do productive work, if they can find something they enjoy. enforce people s contribution to the general good, as everyone naturally wants to do productive work, if they can find something they enjoy. Many communist anarchists believe that human behaviour is motivated

More information

Introduction to Rawls on Justice and Rawls on utilitarianism. For THEORIES OF JUSTICE USD Fall, 2008 Richard Arneson

Introduction to Rawls on Justice and Rawls on utilitarianism. For THEORIES OF JUSTICE USD Fall, 2008 Richard Arneson 1 Introduction to Rawls on Justice and Rawls on utilitarianism. For THEORIES OF JUSTICE USD Fall, 2008 Richard Arneson In chapter 1 of A Theory of Justice John Rawls introduces the conception of justice

More information

John Rawls's Difference Principle and The Strains of Commitment: A Diagrammatic Exposition

John Rawls's Difference Principle and The Strains of Commitment: A Diagrammatic Exposition From the SelectedWorks of Greg Hill 2010 John Rawls's Difference Principle and The Strains of Commitment: A Diagrammatic Exposition Greg Hill Available at: https://works.bepress.com/greg_hill/3/ The Difference

More information

SHOULD DESERT REPLACE EQUALITY? REPLIES TO KAGAN

SHOULD DESERT REPLACE EQUALITY? REPLIES TO KAGAN BY MICHAEL WEBER JOURNAL OF ETHICS & SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY VOL. 4, NO. 3 AUGUST 2010 URL: WWW.JESP.ORG COPYRIGHT MICHAEL WEBER 2010 Should Desert Replace Equality? Replies to Kagan E QUALITY IS FUNDAMENTALLY

More information

Choice-Based Libertarianism. Like possessive libertarianism, choice-based libertarianism affirms a basic

Choice-Based Libertarianism. Like possessive libertarianism, choice-based libertarianism affirms a basic Choice-Based Libertarianism Like possessive libertarianism, choice-based libertarianism affirms a basic right to liberty. But it rests on a different conception of liberty. Choice-based libertarianism

More information

Though several factors contributed to the eventual conclusion of the

Though several factors contributed to the eventual conclusion of the Aporia vol. 24 no. 1 2014 Nozick s Entitlement Theory of Justice: A Response to the Objection of Arbitrariness Though several factors contributed to the eventual conclusion of the Cold War, one of the

More information

The (Many) Models of Rawls and Harsanyi

The (Many) Models of Rawls and Harsanyi 1 RATIONAL CHOICE AND THE ORIGINAL POSITION: The (Many) Models of Rawls and Harsanyi Gerald Gaus and John Thrasher 1. The Original Position and Rational Justification 1.1 The Fundamental Derivation Thesis

More information

The Justification of Justice as Fairness: A Two Stage Process

The Justification of Justice as Fairness: A Two Stage Process The Justification of Justice as Fairness: A Two Stage Process TED VAGGALIS University of Kansas The tragic truth about philosophy is that misunderstanding occurs more frequently than understanding. Nowhere

More information

JUSTICE, NON-VIOLENCE, AND THE PRACTICE OF POLITICAL JUDGMENT: A STUDY OF RICOEUR S CONCEPTION OF JUSTICE YANG-SOO LEE

JUSTICE, NON-VIOLENCE, AND THE PRACTICE OF POLITICAL JUDGMENT: A STUDY OF RICOEUR S CONCEPTION OF JUSTICE YANG-SOO LEE JUSTICE, NON-VIOLENCE, AND THE PRACTICE OF POLITICAL JUDGMENT: A STUDY OF RICOEUR S CONCEPTION OF JUSTICE By YANG-SOO LEE (Under the Direction of CLARK WOLF) ABSTRACT In his recent works, Paul Ricoeur

More information

Is Rawls s Difference Principle Preferable to Luck Egalitarianism?

Is Rawls s Difference Principle Preferable to Luck Egalitarianism? Western University Scholarship@Western 2014 Undergraduate Awards The Undergraduate Awards 2014 Is Rawls s Difference Principle Preferable to Luck Egalitarianism? Taylor C. Rodrigues Western University,

More information

II. Bentham, Mill, and Utilitarianism

II. Bentham, Mill, and Utilitarianism II. Bentham, Mill, and Utilitarianism Do the ends justify the means? Getting What We Are Due We ended last time (more or less) with the well-known Latin formulation of the idea of justice: suum cuique

More information

Book Reviews. Julian Culp, Global Justice and Development, Palgrave Macmillan, Basingstoke, UK, 2014, Pp. xi+215, ISBN:

Book Reviews. Julian Culp, Global Justice and Development, Palgrave Macmillan, Basingstoke, UK, 2014, Pp. xi+215, ISBN: Public Reason 6 (1-2): 83-89 2016 by Public Reason Julian Culp, Global Justice and Development, Palgrave Macmillan, Basingstoke, UK, 2014, Pp. xi+215, ISBN: 978-1-137-38992-3 In Global Justice and Development,

More information

A Rawlsian Perspective on Justice for the Disabled

A Rawlsian Perspective on Justice for the Disabled Volume 9 Issue 1 Philosophy of Disability Article 5 1-2008 A Rawlsian Perspective on Justice for the Disabled Adam Cureton University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill Follow this and additional works at:

More information

This book has a simple and straightforward message. The

This book has a simple and straightforward message. The 1 Introduction This book has a simple and straightforward message. The political and programmatic success of social programs requires improved target efficiency: directing resources where they do the most

More information

Jürgen Kohl March 2011

Jürgen Kohl March 2011 Jürgen Kohl March 2011 Comments to Claus Offe: What, if anything, might we mean by progressive politics today? Let me first say that I feel honoured by the opportunity to comment on this thoughtful and

More information

Let's define each spectrum, and see where liberalism and conservatism reside on them.

Let's define each spectrum, and see where liberalism and conservatism reside on them. THE DEFINITION OF LIBERALISM The purpose of this section is to define liberalism, and the differences between it and other political ideologies. In defining the differences between liberalism and conservatism,

More information

Chapter 2: American Citizens and Political Culture Test Bank. Multiple Choice

Chapter 2: American Citizens and Political Culture Test Bank. Multiple Choice Chapter 2: American Citizens and Political Culture Test Bank Multiple Choice 1. What s at Stake? at the beginning of Chapter 2 shows that immigration reform. a. is a very important issue b. is not an important

More information

MAJORITARIAN DEMOCRACY

MAJORITARIAN DEMOCRACY MAJORITARIAN DEMOCRACY AND CULTURAL MINORITIES Bernard Boxill Introduction, Polycarp Ikuenobe ONE OF THE MAJOR CRITICISMS of majoritarian democracy is that it sometimes involves the totalitarianism of

More information