Indivisibility and Linkage Arguments: A Reply to Gilabert

Similar documents
Why Does Inequality Matter? T. M. Scanlon. Chapter 8: Unequal Outcomes. It is well known that there has been an enormous increase in inequality in the

Is the Ideal of a Deliberative Democracy Coherent?

POLITICAL SCIENCE 1101 SAMPLE ESSAY ANSWERS BUCKNER F. MELTON, JR.

Comment on Baker's Autonomy and Free Speech

The Determinacy of Republican Policy: A Reply to McMahon

Questions. Hobbes. Hobbes s view of human nature. Question. What justification is there for a state? Does the state have supreme authority?

Hobbes. Questions. What justification is there for a state? Does the state have supreme authority? What limits are there upon the state?

POLITICAL AUTHORITY AND PERFECTIONISM: A RESPONSE TO QUONG

Getting a Handle on the Super PAC Problem. Bob Bauer. Stanford Law Symposium. February 5, 2016

Phil 290, February 8, 2011 Christiano, The Constitution of Equality, Ch. 2 3

Lecture 11: The Social Contract Theory. Thomas Hobbes Leviathan Mozi Mozi (Chapter 11: Obeying One s Superior)

DEMOCRACY AND EQUALITY

VOTER ID 101. The Right to Vote Shouldn t Come With Barriers. indivisible435.org

RELATIVISM, SELF-DETERMINATION, AND HUMAN RIGHTS. James Nickel and David Reidy

Property and Progress

CONTEXTUALISM AND GLOBAL JUSTICE

Input to Phase 3 Consultation: World Bank Environmental and Social Safeguard Framework

Comments on Justin Weinberg s Is Government Supererogation Possible? Public Reason Political Philosophy Symposium Friday October 17, 2008

Ethics Handout 18 Rawls, Classical Utilitarianism and Nagel, Equality

and government interventions, and explain how they represent contrasting political choices

SOCIAL CHARTER OF THE AMERICAS. (Adopted at the second plenary session, held on June 4, 2012, and reviewed by the Style Committee)

Further key insights from the Indigenous Community Governance Project, 2006

The Limits of Self-Defense

Confining Pogge s Analysis of Global Poverty to Genuinely Negative Duties

Immigration. Average # of Interior Removals # of Interior Removals in ,311 81,603

Report on Women and Poverty ( ) September 2016

PHYSICIANS AS CANDIDATES PROGRAM

The Impact of Immigration on Housing Demand in England

Voters Interests in Campaign Finance Regulation: Formal Models

Democracy Building Globally

Ordering Power: Contentious Politics and Authoritarian Leviathans in Southeast Asia

Interview with Jacques Bwira Hope Primary School Kampala, Uganda

Human Rights: International Dimensions

ADDRESS BY GATT DIRECTOR-GENERAL TO UNCTAD VIII IN CARTAGENA, COLOMBIA

Well-Being and Fairness in the Distribution of Scarce Health Resources

Review of Mathias Risse, On Global Justice Princeton University Press, 2012, Reviewed by Christian Barry, Australian National University

Problems with the one-person-one-vote Principle

ANTI-CORRUPTION POLICY. Adopted on June 12, 2012 by the boards of directors

Christian Aid Ireland's Submission to the Review of Ireland s Foreign Policy and External Relations

Deliberative Online Poll Phase 2 Follow Up Survey Experimental and Control Group

The Standard of Utility. What makes an action right?

Two Pictures of the Global-justice Debate: A Reply to Tan*

Trade Union Comments. Throughout this process, we have advocated for the following key priorities to be included in the Binding Treaty:

Proceduralism and Epistemic Value of Democracy

An appealing and original aspect of Mathias Risse s book On Global

Trade liberalisation and globalisation: What are the impacts on women's lives?

Commentary on Idil Boran, The Problem of Exogeneity in Debates on Global Justice

Review of Michael E. Bratman s Shared Agency: A Planning Theory of Acting Together (Oxford University Press 2014) 1

Testimony prepared by. Triada Stampas. for the. Committee on Health. on a

CAUSES AND CONSEQUENCES OF GROWING INEQUALITY and what can be done about it

PolicyBrief. by Trey Moore & Scott Sumner

PHIL 3226: Social and Political Philosophy, Fall 2009 TR 11:00-12:15, Denny 216 Dr. Gordon Hull

Jürgen Kohl March 2011

The present volume is an accomplished theoretical inquiry. Book Review. Journal of. Economics SUMMER Carmen Elena Dorobăț VOL. 20 N O.

Exam Questions By Year IR 214. How important was soft power in ending the Cold War?

Introductory Remarks. Michael Schaefer, Chairman of the Board, BMW Foundation. Check against delivery!

Organization for Security and Co-operation in Europe. Strengthening Energy Security in the OSCE Area

enforce people s contribution to the general good, as everyone naturally wants to do productive work, if they can find something they enjoy.

Ethnic Diversity and Perceptions of Government Performance

Draft Conclusions. Inter-Parliamentary Conference for the Common Foreign and Security Policy and the Common Security and Defence Policy

TWELVE FACTS AND FALLACIES ABOUT THE CONVENTION ON CLUSTER MUNITIONS

WHY NOT BASE FREE SPEECH ON AUTONOMY OR DEMOCRACY?

1100 Ethics July 2016

BATTLEGROUND BRIEFING

A PAPER ON "THE EAST AFRICAN POLITICAL FEDERATION; ADDRESSING FEARS, CONCERNS AND CHALLENGES PRESENTED BY HON

The key building blocks of a successful implementation of the Sustainable Development Goals

I. Rocco s Critique of Liberalism, Democracy and Socialism

elation, Washington D.C, September 6-8, INFLUENCE RANKING IN THE UNITED STATES SENATE*" Robert A. Dahl James G. March David Nasatir

Unleashing the Full Potential of Civil Society

Corruption Spotlight. GOVERNANCE and THE LAW BACKGROUND NOTE. Mushtaq H. Khan University of London. Public Disclosure Authorized

UvA-DARE (Digital Academic Repository) Religious Freedom and the Threat of Jurisdictional Pluralism Rummens, S.; Pierik, R.H.M.

The reality of Christian mission. work towards North Korean. Refugees and its future. strategy. -Seoul Centered-

The Role of U.N. in Understanding Globalization

Ten Years of the National Basic Livelihood Security System and Working Poor Women

DECLARATION OF PANAMA

Examiners Report June GCE Government & Politics 6GP04 4B

Adelaide Recommendations on Healthy Public Policy

THE CONSTITUTIONALIZATION OF MONEY James M. Buchanan

Spurring Growth in the Global Economy A U.S. Perspective World Strategic Forum: Pioneering for Growth and Prosperity

12th IACC. Workshop: 2.1. Human rights and Anti-corruption Strategies: Determinants for Development?

AirPlus International Travel Management Study 2015 Part 1 A comparison of global trends and costs in business travel management.

LESSON 9: What Basic Ideas about Government Did the State Constitutions Include? How Did the New States Protect Rights?

Economic and Social Council

Philosophy 34 Spring Philosophy of Law. What is law?

SMALL CLAIMS PROCEDURE I

Testimony to the United States Senate Budget Committee Hearing on Opportunity, Mobility, and Inequality in Today's Economy April 1, 2014

An Increased Incumbency Effect: Reconsidering Evidence

Voting Alternate Lesson Plan

Session 20 Gerald Dworkin s Paternalism

No real development without human rights

BERKELEY DAVIS IRVINE LOS ANGELES MERCED RIVERSIDE SAN DIEGO SAN FRANCISCO. Chair of the Assembly of the Academic Senate

Standard Eurobarometer 88. National report PUBLIC OPINION IN THE EUROPEAN UNION MALTA.

On the Level. Who s Got the Power? Government on Three Levels. Fighting for Control. Spread It Around. Federal. State. Local. You. Reading p.1.

Running head: THE AMERICAN DREAM. The American Dream: Dead, Alive, or on Hold? Brandon King University of Cincinnati

Terry and Substantive Law

November/December 2001

Waltz s book belongs to an important style of theorizing, in which far-reaching. conclusions about a domain in this case, the domain of international

Current Developments in Middle Eastern Politics and Religion

International Business 7e

Robust Political Economy. Classical Liberalism and the Future of Public Policy

Transcription:

HUMAN RIGHTS QUARTERLY Indivisibility and Linkage Arguments: A Reply to Gilabert James W. Nickel* ABSTRACT This reply discusses Pablo Gilabert s response to my article, Rethinking Indivisibility. It welcomes his distinction between conceptual, normative, epistemic, and causal forms of support from one right to another. It denies, however, that Rethinking Indivisibility downplayed linkage arguments for human rights (although it did call for careful evaluation of such arguments), and rejects Gilabert s suggestion that we understand the indivisibility of two rights as two rights being highly useful to each other (interdependence) rather than as mutual indispensability. In the final section, I offer two new worries about the system-wide indivisibility of human rights. I am grateful to Pablo Gilabert for his thoughtful response to my article on the indivisibility of human rights. The goal of my article was to sow doubt about indivisibility that stimulates reflection and deeper understanding, 1 and Gilabert s response furthers the realization of that goal. This brief reply does not attempt to respond to all of Gilabert s criticisms and suggestions. Instead it identifies some areas where I am happy to accept his suggestions as well as some areas of continued disagreement. I. TYPES OF SUPPORT AND THE EXTENT OF INDIVISIBILITY Gilabert usefully distinguishes between conceptual, normative, epistemic, and causal forms of support from one right to another. A conceptual (or * James W. Nickel is Professor of Philosophy and Law at the University of Miami. Thanks are due to Patricia D. White for helpful comments on this reply. 1. James W. Nickel, Rethinking Indivisibility: Towards a Theory of Supporting Relations Between Human Rights, 30 HUM. RTS. Q. 984, 985 (2008). Human Rights Quarterly 32 (2010) 433 440 2010 by The Johns Hopkins University Press

434 HUMAN RIGHTS QUARTERLY Vol. 32 constitutive) relation holds between freedom of movement and freedom of assembly because moving is part of (physical if not electronic) assembly. Normative support from one right to another occurs when the first enriches the normative meaning of the second right as when democratically implemented social benefits have a different normative significance 2 than ones that are implemented without popular participation. Epistemic support occurs, if I understand Gilabert correctly, when the exercise of one right helps promote people s knowledge of the existence, meaning, and possible uses of their rights. Examples 2, 3, and 5 in the paragraph below illustrate causal relations. These types of support crosscut the more specific forms that were suggested in Rethinking Indivisibility. 3 Those were: (1) promoting the supported right against some of its main threats as when a right to freedom of movement protects against those violations of the right to freedom of assembly that block people from moving to the location of the assembly; 4 (2) providing a remedy or process that helps protect the supported right as when the right to petition government or of access to the courts helps uphold many rights; (3) making institutions used to implement the supported right less vulnerable to corruption and abuse as when rights to freedom of the press expose corrupt voting systems; (4) improving the capacities of right holders as when the right to education helps make people knowledgeable about their other rights; and (5) ameliorating a problem such as climate change or a global economic crisis that is likely to undermine 5 the abilities of governments to respect and implement human rights. The example in 1 above is conceptual or constitutive. As mentioned above, examples 2, 3, and 5 above are causal. Example 4 above illustrates epistemological support. Rethinking Indivisibility distinguished between system-wide indivisibility and widespread indivisibility. Gilabert proposes a third category that is weaker, namely, partial but not widespread indivisibility. 6 This is a helpful suggestion. A fourth and still weaker category could be added as well, namely, has a few instances of indivisibility. Although I continue to doubt that system-wide indivisibility occurs in today s systems of rights, including the ones that are best implemented, the other three categories are likely to be useful in describing systems of rights in various countries with their different levels of implementation (high, medium, and low quality, along with non-implementation). 2. Pablo Gilabert, The Importance of Linkage Arguments for the Theory and Practice of Human Rights: A Response to James Nickel, 32 HUM. RTS. Q., [?] (2010). 3. Nickel, supra note 1, at 988. 4. Id. 5. Note the distinction here between violating and undermining. Conditions that do not violate a right may nevertheless undermine it by greatly weakening its system of implementation or conditions required for its implementation. 6. Gilabert, supra note 2, at [?].

2010 Indivisibility and Linkage Arguments: Reply to Gilabert 435 II. THE USE OF LINKAGE ARGUMENTS DOES NOT COMMIT ONE TO SYSTEM-WIDE OR EVEN WIDESPREAD INDIVISIBILITY Linkage arguments defend controversial rights by arguing that they provide indispensable support to one or more accepted or already justified rights. Gilabert worries that I am urging that we drop or downplay linkage arguments for human rights. Gilabert s worry is unfounded for three reasons. One is that I have often used linkage arguments as Gilabert notes. 7 Second, I think that under medium and high quality implementation, at least, all systems of rights have some strong supporting relations and these can generate interesting linkage arguments. And third, linkage arguments are still possible in the total absence of indivisibility. To see this, imagine a system of rights that has many strong one-way indispensability relations but none that are bidirectional. Those one-way indispensability relations would support a number of sound linkage arguments, but the system would, by hypothesis, lack indivisibility since that requires strong bidirectional support between at least two rights. 8 The purpose of Rethinking Indivisibility was not to discourage the use of linkage arguments, but rather to encourage and facilitate the careful evaluation of such arguments. I would like linkage arguments to be better even if that makes them fewer. As I suggested, in evaluating linkage arguments, we should carefully attend to the strength of the supporting relation(s) between the rights in question, consider different levels of implementation and what they imply for supporting relations, and choose an appropriate baseline for comparing scenarios where the supporting right is absent in one case and present in the other. III. AGAINST REPLACING INDISPENSABLE WITH HIGHLY USEFUL IN THE ANALYSIS OF INDIVISIBILITY In Rethinking Indivisibility, I proposed understanding the idea that two rights are indivisible as the claim that they are mutually indispensable (strongly supportive in both directions). If this is the right way to understand indivisibility, then system-wide indivisibility is not very plausible. Gilabert seems to accept this conditional proposition, but proposes to avoid accepting the consequence of the conditional (that is, that system-wide indivisibility is implausible) by denying the antecedent (that indivisibility should be understood in terms of mutual indispensability). He proposes that we 7. Id. at [?]. See JAMES W. NICKEL, MAKING SENSE OF HUMAN RIGHTS 129 32, 144 46 (2d ed. 2007), 8. Nickel, supra note 1, at 990 91.

436 HUMAN RIGHTS QUARTERLY Vol. 32 understand the idea that two rights are indivisible as the claim that they are highly useful to each other. [T]alk of indivisibility could be couched in weaker (but still robust) terms by saying that R1 and R2 are indivisible if the fulfillment of any one of them is highly useful to the fulfillment of the other.... I do not claim that those who use the notion of indivisibility mean it in this way, but it would not be a bad idea to do so. 9 I resist this suggestion. First, we already have good language for saying that two rights are highly useful to each other, namely saying that they are interdependent or mutually supportive. Second, if human rights advocates and theorists used indivisibility this way their statements would be highly misleading because they would be saying something weak, but because indivisibility has a well-established meaning their listeners would understand them to be saying something strong. There is a clear distinction between mutual usefulness and mutual indispensability. A person s left and right hands are highly useful to each other s functioning, but are not indispensable. A person can lose one hand while retaining the full function of the other. In contrast, a functioning liver and a functioning heart are indivisible; you cannot have one for very long without the other. The contrast between mutual usefulness and indispensability has existed for a long time. It appears, for example, in Thomas Hobbes Leviathan where he discusses the powers of the sovereign. 10 He states that there are various rights that a sovereign could give away and still be a sovereign, that is, while retaining the power to protect his subjects. 11 Hobbes presents the right to coin money as an example of something that is useful, but not indispensable, to the sovereign. However, there are a few rights that a sovereign cannot relinquish while remaining a sovereign. For example, if he transfer[s] the militia, he retains the judicature in vain, for want of execution of the laws; or if he grants away the power of raising money, the militia is in vain. These rights of the sovereign are indivisible, and inseparably annexed to the sovereignty. 12 Human rights discourse is widely suspected of containing numerous exaggerations (I hear these suspicions from my students every semester), and I see little reason to recommend adding one more by saying that human rights are indivisible when we really mean interdependent or mutually useful. 9. Gilabert, supra note 2, at [?]. 10. THOMAS HOBBES, LEVIATHAN ch. 18 (1660). 11. Id. 12. Id.

2010 Indivisibility and Linkage Arguments: Reply to Gilabert 437 IV. A WEAKER UNDERSTANDING OF INDISPENSABLE IN THE ANALYSIS OF INDIVISIBILITY Perhaps we can go a modest distance, at least, towards accommodating Gilabert s desire for a weaker notion of indivisibility by adopting an interpretation of indispensable that is weaker than the one I used in Rethinking Indivisibility. This slightly weaker notion takes into account costs and other practicalities in deciding whether a plausible alternative exists to some allegedly indispensable supporting right. To find out whether R1 is indispensable to R2 at some level of implementation, we need to consider whether there is some plausible alternative Z that could support R2 just as well in those circumstances. Z could be another right or some other sort of institution or governmental program. To be a plausible alternative, Z needs to work as well or better as R1 in supporting R2 and have about the same level of costs and risks. If there is no such alternative, then R1 is indeed indispensable to some level of implementation of R2. Let s call this weaker notion practical indispensability. To illustrate this idea, consider a traveler who wants to go from Atlanta, Georgia, to Brattleboro, Vermont, by commercial airliner and rental car. This traveler has no interest in sightseeing or visiting friends along the way. Someone tells the traveler that to make such a trip it is indispensable to fly to Hartford and rent a car there. We can show the falsity of this claim by observing that although Hartford is the closest commercial airport to Brattleboro (77 miles), there are good alternative airports such as Boston (105) and Providence (117). We could not make such a rebuttal, however, if Syracuse (220) were the only alternative. The costs in driving time and mileage are too much higher than those of flying to Hartford or Boston. This example demonstrates that costs and benefits often enter into deciding whether an alternative is plausible to a rational person and thus into deciding what counts as practically indispensable. When a right supports several rights rather than just one, the notion of practical indispensability can take this into account. A supporting right may be indispensable or near-indispensable because it provides substantial support to several rights even though it is not indispensable to any single one of them. Consider the household pliers as an analogy. This tool is useful for so many purposes as to be practically indispensable in one s home, yet one could almost always find some other tool that could do any one of its jobs. Perhaps we can explain the practical indispensability of the household pliers in terms of the higher cost of its alternatives. Because the cost of the dozens of specialized tools that could replace the pliers is much higher than buying a pair of pliers, the purchase of all those specialized tools is not a rational alternative to the many-purpose tool. We can use this pattern of argument to defend the indispensability of broadly useful rights such as the right to free public education and freedom of the press.

438 HUMAN RIGHTS QUARTERLY Vol. 32 Protecting rights is not a one-shot activity like taking a trip to Brattleboro. It is something that must be done continuously over a long period of time. Accordingly, another condition for an indispensable supporting relation is that it be sustainable something that is possible to accomplish over a long period under changing circumstances. Practical indispensability in both directions seems to be a beneficial way to understand indivisibility. It preserves the distinction between rights that are highly useful and ones that are genuinely indispensable, while avoiding turning indispensability into an impossible test. I doubt, however, that understanding indivisibility in terms of practical indispensability weakens the idea of indivisibility enough to make plausible the system-wide indivisibility of human rights even under high-quality implementation. If, as I suspect, the right to freedom of religion doesn t contribute much to the realization of due process rights, then a weakened notion of indispensability won t save the claim that these rights are indivisible. V. THE IMPORTANCE OF SUPPORTING RELATIONS BETWEEN HUMAN RIGHTS FOR DEVELOPING COUNTRIES In Rethinking Indivisibility I argued that the strength of supporting relations between rights varies with quality of implementation. The strength of support that one right provides to another will tend to decline as quality of implementation declines. If developing countries generally have a lower quality of implementation than developed countries, then they are likely also to have fewer supporting relations between rights. A general weakening of supporting relations makes claims of indivisibility less plausible and makes fewer sound linkage arguments available. The recognition of this result, I suggested, explains why early claims about the indivisibility of rights were restricted to full realization. 13 Rethinking Indivisibility did not deny the possibility that some strong supporting relations could exist under medium or low quality implementation. For example, under medium quality implementation, due process rights may in fact provide indispensable or highly useful support to the fundamental freedoms. Nor did I deny that some support from a partially implemented right can be of great importance to the partial or full implementation of another right. Gilabert rightly emphasizes in his fire escape example that a rusted and unsafe set of stairs is far better than none when they provide the only way of getting down from a burning apartment. 14 13. Nickel, supra note 1, at 985, 992. 14. Gilabert, supra note 2, at [?].

2010 Indivisibility and Linkage Arguments: Reply to Gilabert 439 The following is a case of a poorly implemented right providing low or medium strength support to other rights. In a country with low-quality implementation of the right to free public education at the elementary and secondary levels, the education provided in the public schools will generally be of low quality. Facilities will be overcrowded (with the possible result that school days are restricted to four hours so that several daily sessions can be run), schools will charge fees for books and supplies that many families cannot afford, and free public schools will simply be unavailable in remote areas of the country. Many developing countries are in this situation. Some children do receive at least a partial education, however, which supports the implementation of other rights to some degree because these children, once grown up, are more capable of understanding, using, and protecting their rights and of assisting others in doing so. But this rusty escape only allows some people to survive the fire. The claim that supporting relations between rights tend to be weaker in developing countries is bad news because it means that fewer sound linkage arguments are available to defend the justifiability and priority of controversial rights in those countries. Other justificatory strategies have to be used. But I believe this claim also brings good news, namely that developing countries are free to choose which rights to emphasize and invest in as they formulate their own development and rights implementation strategies. They are not required to do a little each year for each and every human right. Haiti can emphasize security rights while Bolivia emphasizes equality rights for indigenous peoples. This is particularly important as the number of internationally recognized human rights continues to grow. VI. TWO NEW CRITICISMS OF INDIVISIBILITY Since publishing Rethinking Indivisibility I have identified two additional worries about system-wide (and perhaps widespread) indivisibility. One is that indivisibility is hard to assess when we lack a settled list of which rights are genuine human rights (what we have now, I think, is a partially settled but still expanding list). For example, Kim could maintain that there is system-wide indivisibility because she thinks there are forty genuine human rights that are all indispensable to each other s realization. Lee, on the other hand, could deny system-wide indivisibility while agreeing with Kim about the forty rights, because he thinks there are forty-two human rights and believes that the forty-first and forty-second do not satisfy the strong mutual support criterion with all of the other forty. My other new worry about indivisibility concerns the potential impact of bringing what we might call undermining or conflict relations between rights into the discussion of indivisibility. In Rethinking Indivisibility, I noted

440 HUMAN RIGHTS QUARTERLY Vol. 32 that rights can conflict and suggested that we subtract the amount of harm done by the supporting right from the amount of positive support it provides to determine the degree (if any) of net positive support. 15 The example I provided was that security rights support rights to the fundamental freedoms, but the system of criminal law used to implement security rights creates serious risks to those freedoms and to other rights as well. Even if conflict relations between rights were only one third as frequent as supporting relations, their impact on the strength of supporting relations could be substantial. Further, conflict relations may be worse under high quality implementation because in that happy situation each right is likely to do more, have bigger implementation machinery, and require more support from other rights. An account of the varieties of conflicts between rights needs to be developed and then applied to discussions of linkage arguments and indivisibility. The effect of accounting for undermining relations between rights, I suspect, will be to render some linkage arguments unsound and make very strong claims about the extent of indivisibility still less plausible. 15. Nickel, supra note 1, at 989.