VOTING PARADOXES: A Socratic Dialogue

Similar documents
The Mathematics of Voting Transcript

The Arrow Impossibility Theorem: Where Do We Go From Here?

In Elections, Irrelevant Alternatives Provide Relevant Data

Electoral Reform Questionnaire Field Dates: October 12-18, 2016

Fairness Criteria. Review: Election Methods

Arrow s Impossibility Theorem

COULD THE LIB DEM MARGINAL MELTDOWN MEAN THE TORIES GAIN FROM A.V.? By Lord Ashcroft, KCMG 20 July 2010

Voting Criteria April

Voting: Issues, Problems, and Systems, Continued

Areeq Chowdhury: Yeah, could you speak a little bit louder? I just didn't hear the last part of that question.

What is the Best Election Method?

- The Fast PR System is a proportional representation (PR) system. Every vote counts. But it offers significant differences from other PR systems.

Repeat Voting: Two-Vote May Lead More People To Vote

1.6 Arrow s Impossibility Theorem

Possible voting reforms in the United States

How Should Members of Parliament (and Presidents) Be Elected? E. Maskin Institute for Advanced Study

Reading the local runes:

Voting: Issues, Problems, and Systems. Voting I 1/36

Of the 73 MEPs elected on 22 May in Great Britain and Northern Ireland 30 (41 percent) are women.

Many Social Choice Rules

Voting rules: (Dixit and Skeath, ch 14) Recall parkland provision decision:

VOTING TO ELECT A SINGLE CANDIDATE

! # % & ( ) ) ) ) ) +,. / 0 1 # ) 2 3 % ( &4& 58 9 : ) & ;; &4& ;;8;

DHSLCalc.xls What is it? How does it work? Describe in detail what I need to do

Measuring Fairness. Paul Koester () MA 111, Voting Theory September 7, / 25

Harry Ridgewell: So how have islands in the South Pacific been affected by rising sea levels in the last 10 years?

Easy Read Creating a Parliament for Wales

Chapter 9: Social Choice: The Impossible Dream

Voting: Issues, Problems, and Systems. Voting I 1/31

Notes for Session 7 Basic Voting Theory and Arrow s Theorem

Is Majority Rule the Best Voting Method? Partha Dasgupta and Eric Maskin

Why 100% of the Polls Were Wrong

Mathematics and Social Choice Theory. Topic 4 Voting methods with more than 2 alternatives. 4.1 Social choice procedures

Desirable properties of social choice procedures. We now outline a number of properties that are desirable for these social choice procedures:

Random tie-breaking in STV

Towards a hung Parliament? The battleground of the 2017 UK general election

Iowa Voting Series, Paper 4: An Examination of Iowa Turnout Statistics Since 2000 by Party and Age Group

From Minority Vote to Majority Challenge. How closing the ethnic gap would deliver a Conservative majority

Electoral Reform Brief

Compare the vote Level 1

Compare the vote Level 3

Economics 470 Some Notes on Simple Alternatives to Majority Rule

2017 general election Urban-Rural differences

Electoral Choice in Britain, 2010: Emerging Evidence From the BES

SPERI British Political Economy Brief No. 13. Conservative support in Northern England at the 2015 general election.

Electoral Reform: Making Every Vote Count Equally

Devolution in Scotland, Wales, Northern Ireland since 1997

A New Electoral System for a New Century. Eric Stevens

THE ANDREW MARR SHOW INTERVIEW: ALEX SALMOND, MSP FIRST MINISTER OF SCOTLAND OCTOBER 20 th 2013

Computational Social Choice: Spring 2007

Send My Friend to School 2017: General Election resource

The Relative Electoral Impact of Central Party Co-ordination and Size of Party Membership at Constituency Level

Exercises For DATA AND DECISIONS. Part I Voting

c M. J. Wooldridge, used by permission/updated by Simon Parsons, Spring

9 Advantages of conflictual redistricting

4 However, devolution would have better served the people of Wales if a better voting system had been used. At present:

Leaders, voters and activists in the elections in Great Britain 2005 and 2010

YouGovR. YouGov / Sunday Times Survey Results. Sample Size: 1118 Fieldwork: 15th - 17th August 2007 For full results click here

The Guardian. Campaign Poll 8, May 2017

Introduction to the Theory of Voting

12.2 Defects in Voting Methods

Voting: Issues, Problems, and Systems

If a party s share of the overall party vote entitles it to five seats, but it wins six electorates, the sixth seat is called an overhang seat.

Excerpts of the interview follow: Question: What is the primary purpose of Deliberative Polling? 3/11 Disaster in Japan GLO. Behind the News.

Today s plan: Section : Plurality with Elimination Method and a second Fairness Criterion: The Monotocity Criterion.

The Northeast Ohio Coalition for the Homeless, et al. v. Brunner, Jennifer, etc.

Proportion? Trade unions and electoral reform

Analysis of AV Voting System Rick Bradford, 24/4/11

Homework 7 Answers PS 30 November 2013

Font Size: A A. Eric Maskin and Amartya Sen JANUARY 19, 2017 ISSUE. 1 of 7 2/21/ :01 AM

The Electoral College. What is it?, how does it work?, the pros, and the cons

SOCIAL CHOICES (Voting Methods) THE PROBLEM. Social Choice and Voting. Terminologies

The Alternative Vote Referendum: why I will vote YES. Mohammed Amin

Voting: Issues, Problems, and Systems, Continued. Voting II 1/27

THE PEOPLE, THE PRESS & POLITICS 1990 After The Election

THE ANDREW MARR SHOW 24 TH APRIL 2016 THERESA MAY. AM: Good morning to you, Home Secretary. TM: Good morning, Andrew.

The Brookings Institution Dollar and Sense Ernesto Zedillo on globalization, NAFTA and the wall March 15, 2019

Disproportionality and bias in the results of the 2005 general election in Great Britain: evaluating the electoral system s impact

Syllabus update: Now keeping best 3 of 4 tests

Election Statistics: UK

Fair Division in Theory and Practice

Women and minority interests in Fiji s alternative electoral system

Chapter 10. The Manipulability of Voting Systems. For All Practical Purposes: Effective Teaching. Chapter Briefing

Problems with the one-person-one-vote Principle

CREASE HARMAN & COMPANY

Fairness Criteria. Majority Criterion: If a candidate receives a majority of the first place votes, that candidate should win the election.

THE ANDREW MARR SHOW INTERVIEW: NICOLA STURGEON, MSP FIRST MINISTER, SCOTLAND JANUARY 25 th 2015

SCOTTISH PUBLIC OPINION MONITOR

Social Choice: The Impossible Dream. Check off these skills when you feel that you have mastered them.

The South West contest by contest

The Mathematics of Voting

Math of Election APPORTIONMENT

THE ALTERNATIVE VOTE AND COOMBS RULE VERSUS FIRST-PAST-THE-POST: A SOCIAL CHOICE ANALYSIS OF SIMULATED DATA BASED ON ENGLISH ELECTIONS,

Arrow s Impossibility Theorem on Social Choice Systems

Sun On Sunday Campaign Poll 4. May-June 2017

MATH 1340 Mathematics & Politics

Voting Methods

Problems with Group Decision Making

The Impossibilities of Voting

F2PTP A VOTING SYSTEM FOR EQUALITY OF REPRESENTATION IN A MULTI-PARTY STATE FIRST TWO PAST THE POST. 1 Tuesday, 05 May 2015 David Allen

Transcription:

VOTING PARADOXES: A Socratic Dialogue ANDREW M. COLMAN AND IAN POUNTNEY 11 John Bull. Let us now resume our discussion of the electoral system, Socrates. Socrates. It is indeed an honour for me to discuss this interesting matter with so worthy a representative of this great nation, and I hope my remaining perplexities will be resolved. You will recall, Mr. Bull, that during our previous conversation we established that it is possible in principle for the most unpopular candidate to be elected. You assured me, however, that this would not occur in practice, and you undertook to find some evidence with which to demonstrate this point. I.E. I have some bad news, Socrates. I have scrupulously checked my calculations, and I find that this absurd possibility may well have occurred in practice in a British General Election. S. What evidence led you to this remarkable conclusion? I.B. The evidence concerns the order of preference in which a voter places the candidates. Butler and Stokes, in their book Political Change in Britain, report the results of a survey based upon a very large, self-weighting, multi-stage, stratified sample of the adult population of England, Wales and Scotland shortly after the 1966 General Election. Of those who voted Conservative, 76 per cent. preferred Liberal to Labour; of those who voted Labour, 74 per cent. preferred Liberal to Conservative; and among Liberal voters, 56 per cent. preferred Labour to Conservative. I have assumed that these percentages hold for voters within any particular constituency. S. Is it possible to make that assumption? J.B. In statistical work, Socrates, one is entitled to make whatever plausible assumptions are required. S. I see. J.B. With this data we can estimate the number of voters who considered a particular candidate to be the worst choice in any con- The first part of this dialogue appeared in the April-June issue this year. The authors are at the University of Leicester 304

VOTING PARADOXES stituency in which only Conservative, Liberal and Labour candidates stood. You will recall that we initially defined the most unpopular candidate as the one whom the greatest number of voters consider to be the worst. S. That seems the most natural definition, Mr. Bull. It is the exact converse of the criterion used to decide who is the most popular candidate and therefore who wins the seat. rb. Well, according to this definition, several seats in the 1966 General Election appear to have been won by the most unpopular candidates. I have performed detailed calculations for the constituency of Norfolk South for illustrative purposes. Would you care to cast your eye over my first table of results? JOHN BULL'S TABLE 1 Norfolk South, 1966 General Election Conservative Labour Liberal No. of tlotes cast for each candidate 16,968 16,849 4,079 Estimated No. considering candidate Ulorst 14,836 14,661 8,399 S. That is a startling result. J.B. I have to agree. But you will have observed that the Conservative candidate who won the seat was considered the worst choice by a very narrow margin of voters, so I wouldn't attach too much significance to this example. S. But he won the seat by a very narrow margin of voters, Mr. Bull. I'm sure you have noticed that the margin by which he won (119) is even smaller than the margin by which he was considered worst (175). The Conservative candidate was more emphatically the most unpopular than he was the most popular. '.B. Well, yes, I suppose so. Your facility with figures seems to be improving, Socrates. S. Did your statistical investigations lead to any further conclusions, Mr. Bull?,.B. You will remember that one of our alternative definitions of the most unpopular candidate was that an overall majority of the voters considers him the worst choice. Although we established that such a candidate could theoretically win the seat, my calculations have shown that it is not possible in practice, given Butler and Stokes' survey data. 305 p.q.-3

ANDREW M. COLMAN AND IAN POUNTNEY S. That, at least, is a relief. Did you perform any calculations for our third and most crucial definition of the most unpopular candidate? In this case we would require for, say, the Conservative candidate to be the most unpopular, that a majority of the voters prefer Labour to Conservative and, in addition, a majority prefer Liberal to Conservative. J.B. Yes, I have examined thiscase in the light of the survey data. It transpires that if the votes for the three candidates in a constituency had fallen within certain limits, then the most unpopular candidate in this stringent sense would, nevertheless, have won the seat. Would you like to look at my second table of results? JOHN BULL'S TABLE 2 Percentage Voting for Each Candidate Conservative 35% Liberal 33% Labour 32% Percentage preferring Liberal to Conservative = 57% Percentage preferring Labour to Conservative = 51 % S. I see. The Conservative wins the seat, although a majority of voters prefers Liberal to Conservative and a majority prefers Labour to Conservative. J.B. But I did not find any constituency in which the votes in the 1966 General Election fell within the required limits for this outcome to occur, although there were several very near misses indeed. And, I am bound to add, there were a number of constituencies in which one of the losing candidates, very often the Liberal, was preferred to the winner by a majority of the voters. This condition is met within a surprisingly wide range of voting results. S. Well, what general conclusions have you drawn from all these calculations, Mr. Bull? J.B. I have been thinking most deeply about our voting system, Socrates, and I fear that it may be less than ideal. I am reluctantly forced to concede that it may be necessary to introduce a new system in order to obviate these paradoxical outcomes, which are not in harmony with our traditionally British sense of fair play. S. Do you have a better system in mind? J.B. Yes. It seems that the fundamental flaw in our present system is that we consider a voter's first choice only. I think we ought to follow your suggestion, Socrates, and take into considera- 306

VOTING PARADOXES tion all the preferences among the available candidates which a voter can express. We should, in short, have the voter place all the candidates in order of/reference on the ballot paper. s. And how woul you then decide which candidate is to Le elected, Mr. Bull?,.B. I would have thought that was elementary, Socrates. From the individual preference rankings of the voters we would work out the group order of preference, and the candidate who is first in the group order of preference would be elected. s. I'm afraid I have not been able to keep pace with your thoughts, Mr. Bull. As you know, I am often slow to grasp a point. It would greatly help me if we were to construct another idealised example on which to base our further discussion.,.b. Very well, Socrates. S. I suggest we consider a constituency with a Labour, a Liberal and a Conservative candidate and three voters. The order of preference of the first voter is (Lab, Con, Lib); for the second voter it is (Lib, Lab, Con) and for the third (Con, Lib, Lab). Would you be so good as to explain to me exactly how you would select a winner in this simple case?,.b. It couldn't be easier, Socrates. We first establish whether the voters as a whole prefer Labour to Conservative or vice versa. In this case Labour is preferred to Conservative, since two out of the three voters prefer them in that order. Similarly, the group as a whole prefers Conservative to Liberal, since two out of three place them m that order of preference. Now, since the voters as a group prefer Labour to Conservative and Conservative to Liberal, it obviously follows that they prefer Labour to Liberal. In other words, the order of preference of the voters as a whole is (Lab, Con, Lib), and Labour would therefore be elected. With this system you could be quite sure that the most popular candidate would win, and the most unpopular would come last. It's quite straightforward, Socrates. S. I'm afraid I lost your train of thought at the point where you said it was obvious that the voters as a whole prefer Labour to Liberal. I'm sorry to be so tiresome. '.B. Well, really, Socrates! They prefer Labour to Conservative and they prefer Conservative to Liberal, so it follows logically that they must prefer Labour to Liberal. s. But let's make absolutely sure by counting how many prefer Labour to Liberal in our example, Mr. Bull.,.B. Oh, all right, if you insist. Let me see. Well, bless my soul! It's impossible: two out of the three voters prefer Liberal to Labour. 307

ANDREW M. COLMAN AND IAN POUNTNEY The voters as a group prefer Labour to Conservative, Conservative to Liberal, and (blow me down) Liberal to Labour. How can they do that? S. I can see no reason why they shouldn't, Mr. Bull. So under your proposed new method of voting the Labour Candidate would have been elected despite the fact that a majority of the voters prefers the Liberal candidate to the winner.,.b. Well, I'd say we were in a bit of a pickle, Socrates. I suppose we shall have to go through various voting systems which have been proposed until we find one which does not give rise to any undesirable paradoxes. And if we do not find a suitable system among those which have been proposed in the past, we shall have to invent one of our own. Perhaps we could start with the various complicated alternative voting and single transferrable voting systems which have been suggested from time to time. S. Is it necessary to do all that, Mr. Bull? I am not familiar with the methods you mention, and it is getting late. J.B. What alternative have we, Socrates? S. One alternative is to try to establish what can be said of voting systems in general which would apply to all methods, however complicated they may be. Tell me plainly, Mr. Bull, what paradoxes are you most determined to avoid? '.B. We need a system which will guarantee that the candidate elected is preferred to each of the others. Any system which allows one of the losing candidates to be preferred to the winner by a majority of the voters is unacceptable in a democracy. S. An acceptable system, then, would have to guarantee to select a winner who meets this requirement from any combination of individual preferences among the voters? J.B. It would have to do precisely that, Socrates. S. But have we not established that the imaginary group of voters we were discussing a moment ago preferred Labour to Conservative by a majority, Conservative to Liberal by a majority, and also Liberal to Labour by a majority?,.b. We did indeed establish that, although I still find it hard to comprehend. S. Then is it not true, Mr. Bull, that no voting system, not the ones you referred to nor any conceivable alternative, could produce a result from our simple example which you would consider to be acceptable in a democracy?,.b. Why is that, Socrates? S. Well, you said the system would have to guarantee to select a 308

VOTING PARADOXES winner. If it selected the Labour candidate as the winner, it would be unacceptable because a majority of voters prefers Liberal to Labour; if it selected the Conservative, it would be equally unacceptable because a majority prefers Labour to Conservative; and if it selected the Liberal it would be unacceptable because a majority prefers Conservative to Liberal. We can conclude that there is no candidate which any voting system could select in this case which would satisfy you, no matter how the system were devised. Since no conceivable voting system could select a democratically acceptable winner in this case, it follows that no system could guarantee to do so in every case. There is, therefore, no possible voting system which could meet your requirements of democratic acceptability. J.B. Well, then, Socrates, I suppose we may as well stick to the system we've got. I must say that's a consolation, anyway. REFERENCES Blin, Jean-Marie, "Intransitive Social Orderings and the Probability of the Condorcet Effect", Kyklos (1973), 26 (1),25-35. Butler, David and Stokes, D., Political Change in Britain (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1971). Luce, R. Duncan and Raiffa, H., Games and Decisions (New York: Wiley, 1957), Chap. 14. Rae, Douglas W., The Political Consequences ot Electoral Laws (New Haven: Yale U.P., 1%7 and 1971). Sen, Amartya K., Collective Choice and Social Weltare (London: Oliver and Boyd, 1970). 309