UTILITARIANISM AND POPULATION ETHICS

Similar documents
Ethics Handout 18 Rawls, Classical Utilitarianism and Nagel, Equality

A Set of Solutions to Parfit s Problems

Phil 115, May 24, 2007 The threat of utilitarianism

COWLES FOUNDATION FOR RESEARCH IN ECONOMICS YALE UNIVERSITY

The axiomatic approach to population ethics

Matthew Adler, a law professor at the Duke University, has written an amazing book in defense

OVERPOPULATION AND THE QUALITY OF LIFE

Suppose that you must make choices that may influence the well-being and the identities of the people who will

Can Negative Utilitarianism be Salvaged?

The Person-Affecting Restriction, Comparativism, and the Moral Status of Potential People

Primitivist prioritarianism. Hilary Greaves (Oxford) Value of Equality workshop, Jerusalem, July 2016

RAWLS DIFFERENCE PRINCIPLE: ABSOLUTE vs. RELATIVE INEQUALITY

Economic Growth and the Interests of Future (and Past and Present) Generations: A Comment on Tyler Cowen

Equality and Priority

Lecture 7 Act and Rule Utilitarianism. Based on slides 2011 Pearson Education, Inc. Publishing as Pearson Addison-Wesley

KAI DRAPER. The suggestion that there is a proportionality restriction on the right to defense is almost

Do we have a strong case for open borders?

Phil 290, February 8, 2011 Christiano, The Constitution of Equality, Ch. 2 3

Sufficiency or Priority?

Distributive Justice Rawls

24.03: Good Food 3/13/17. Justice and Food Production

1 Justice as fairness, utilitarianism, and mixed conceptions

Consequentialist Ethics

Elliston and Martin: Whistleblowing

Phil 108, April 24, 2014 Climate Change

Normative Frameworks 1 / 35

Why Rawls's Domestic Theory of Justice is Implausible

RECONCILING LIBERTY AND EQUALITY: JUSTICE AS FAIRNESS. John Rawls s A Theory of Justice presents a theory called justice as fairness.

ANALOGICAL ARGUMENTS FOR EGALITARIANISM. Ratio 27 (2014): Christopher Freiman College of William and Mary Department of Philosophy

Phil 115, June 13, 2007 The argument from the original position: set-up and intuitive presentation and the two principles over average utility

arxiv: v1 [physics.soc-ph] 13 Mar 2018

Dr. Mohammad O. Hamdan

Introduction to the declination function for gerrymanders

Towards Sustainable Economy and Society Under Current Globalization Trends and Within Planetary Boundaries: A Tribute to Hirofumi Uzawa

Assignment to make up for missed class on August 29, 2011 due to Irene

Population axiology. Hilary Greaves

Jus in Bello through the Lens of Individual Moral Responsibility: McMahan on Killing in War

The Limits of Self-Defense

At a time when political philosophy seemed nearly stagnant, John Rawls

Fill the gaps in the sentences using these key words from the text. The paragraph numbers are given to help you.

Bioethics: Autonomy and Health (Fall 2012) Laura Guidry-Grimes

John Rawls THEORY OF JUSTICE

IMPARTIAL JUSTICE: CONDITIONS AND IMPLICATIONS

Criminal Justice Without Moral Responsibility: Addressing Problems with Consequentialism Dane Shade Hannum

Are Second-Best Tariffs Good Enough?

What Is Unfair about Unequal Brute Luck? An Intergenerational Puzzle

Towards a Coherent Theory of Animal Equality ABSTRACT

PHI 1700: Global Ethics

Chapter 14. The Causes and Effects of Rational Abstention

Law & Economics Lecture 1: Basic Notions & Concepts

VALUING DISTRIBUTIVE EQUALITY CLAIRE ANITA BREMNER. A thesis submitted to the Department of Philosophy. in conformity with the requirements for

Utilitarianism and prioritarianism II David McCarthy

Meeting Need NICOLE HASSOUN. Carnegie Mellon University ABSTRACT

Voter Participation with Collusive Parties. David K. Levine and Andrea Mattozzi

Is Rawls s Difference Principle Preferable to Luck Egalitarianism?

Working paper n

DESERT: INDIVIDUALISTIC AND HOLISTIC. Thomas Hurka. University of Toronto

The Difference Principle Would Not Be Chosen behind the Veil of Ignorance

The limits of background justice. Thomas Porter. Social Philosophy & Policy volume 30, issues 1 2. Cambridge University Press

Tradeoffs in implementation of SDGs: how to integrate perspectives of different stakeholders?

Does The Knowledge Society Need Participation and Transparency? Dr. Jerzy Szeremeta UNDESA, New York

1 Aggregating Preferences

WHEN IS THE PREPONDERANCE OF THE EVIDENCE STANDARD OPTIMAL?

ESSENTIALLY COMPARATIVE CONCEPTS

The limits of background justice. Thomas Porter. Rawls says that the primary subject of justice is what he calls the basic structure of

Utilitarianism, Game Theory and the Social Contract

Distributive Justice Rawls

The Standard of Utility. What makes an action right?

Immigration. Average # of Interior Removals # of Interior Removals in ,311 81,603

U.S. Foreign Policy: The Puzzle of War

Running Head: The Consequentialism Debate 1. The Consequentialism Debate. Student s Name. Course Name. Course Title. Instructors name.

The Value of Equality and Egalitarianism. Lecture 1: The levelling down objection

Unemployment and the Immigration Surplus

EFFECTIVELY RECOVERING ATTORNEY S FEES

In The Law of Peoples, John Rawls contrasts his own view of global distributive

Equality and Division: Values in Principle 1

Utilitarianism Revision Help Pack

Capabilities vs. Opportunities for Well-being. Peter Vallentyne, University of Missouri-Columbia

Equality, Efficiency, and the Priority of the Worse Off. Peter Vallentyne. Economics and Philosophy 16 (2000): 1-19

Econ 551 Government Finance: Revenues Fall 2018

Comments on Justin Weinberg s Is Government Supererogation Possible? Public Reason Political Philosophy Symposium Friday October 17, 2008

Chinese University of Hong Kong Second Lecture 2017 Jonathan Jacobs John Jay College of Criminal Justice/CUNY

Canadian Journal of Philosophy

1100 Ethics July 2016

An example of public goods

Lord Ashcroft Polls EU Referendum Poll May 2016

Please do not cite; it s drafty in here.

Arrow s Impossibility Theorem on Social Choice Systems

The Value of Equality and Egalitarianism. Lecture 3 Why not luck egalitarianism?

What is fairness? - Justice Anthony Kennedy, Vieth v Jubelirer (2004)

Introduction to Philosophy Philosophy 110W Spring 2012 Russell Marcus

Rationality of Voting and Voting Systems: Lecture II

Aggregation and the Separateness of Persons

Enriqueta Aragones Harvard University and Universitat Pompeu Fabra Andrew Postlewaite University of Pennsylvania. March 9, 2000

SHOULD DESERT REPLACE EQUALITY? REPLIES TO KAGAN

II. Bentham, Mill, and Utilitarianism

Spurring Growth in the Global Economy A U.S. Perspective World Strategic Forum: Pioneering for Growth and Prosperity

Toward a Responsibility Catering Prioritarian Ethical Theory of Risk

Definition: Institution public system of rules which defines offices and positions with their rights and duties, powers and immunities p.

WHAT should a theory of justice look like? Any successful answer to this

Transcription:

Professor Douglas W. Portmore UTILITARIANISM AND POPULATION ETHICS I. Populations Ethics A. The Non Identity Problem 1. A Same People Choice (From Parfit 1981, 113) Handicapped Child 1 2. A Different Number Choice (From Parfit, 1981, 114) Handicapped Child 2 B. The Essentiality of Origin C. The Total Principle and Aggregative Utilitarianism The Total Principle: If other things are equal, it is better if there is a greater total sum of utility. Aggregative Utilitarianism: An act is morally permissible if and only if it maximizes aggregate utility. C. The Repugnant Conclusion The Repugnant Conclusion: Z is better than A. Last Updated: 4/16/08 Page 1 of 10

The Ridiculous Conclusion: It is impermissible to act so as to bring about Z instead of A. A B C Z The total principle implies the repugnant conclusion, and aggregative utilitarianism implies the ridiculous conclusion. D. The Mere Addition Paradox The average utility level in A+ Your average utility level A B A+ Divided B 1. Is A+ better than A? Page 2 of 10

Consider: A A Wouldn t you say that A is worse than A? If so, shouldn t you say that A+ is better than A? Isn t it better that these other people with lives that are well worth living exist? The sort of natural inequality that exists in A+ doesn t seem to count against the addition of lives that are well worth living, especially since we ll assume that the two populations in A+ are not even aware of each other s existence. It might seem that we should prefer A to A+ since the utility level of the worst off group is higher in A than it is in A+. But there are two ways in which the utility level of the worst off group could be higher in one situation than in another: (i) it could be higher in one situation than in another because in both situations that group exists and in one of the situations their utility level is higher or (ii) it could be higher in one situation than in another because in one situation the group that is the worst off in one situation doesn t exist in the other situation. The move from A+ to A is a case of (ii), not (i), but it seems that it is only (i) that is a morally good change. 2. Is Divided B better than A+? Page 3 of 10

Divided B is superior to A+ in terms all of the following: (1) equality, (2) average utility, (3) total utility, and (4) maximin utility (and this is a case of (i), not (ii). 3. Is B just as good as Divided B? Assume that the only difference is that whereas there is, in B, one large population on one large planet, there is, in Divided B, two half sized populations on two half sized planets. 4. Conclusion If Divided B is just as good as B, and Divided B is better than A+, then B is better than A+. And it seems that A+ is better than A. Therefore, B is better than A. Further, we can make the same sort of argument for all of the following conclusions: C is better than B, D is better than C, E is better than D, and so on and so forth. Ultimately, then, these arguments lead us to the conclusion that Z is better than A. E. Should we reject the repugnant and ridiculous conclusions? 1. Three Different Versions of the Repugnant Conclusion: (i) the conclusion that Drab Z is better than A; (ii) the conclusion that Roller Coaster Z is better than A, and (iii) the conclusion that Short lived Z is better than A. [T]here are three ways the lives in Z could be barely worth living: (1) they could be drab lives, free of pain but also devoid of all but a few simple pleasures; (2) they could be lives of extreme ups and downs, emotional roller coaster rides, where the ecstasies just barely outweigh the agonies; or (3) they could be lives which are qualitatively identical to those in A but very short lived. I will refer to these three possibilities as Drab Z, Roller Coaster Z, and Short lived Z, respectively. (Portmore 1999, 81) Clearly, we should reject (i), but the total principle does not, as we ll soon see, necessarily entail (i). What s more, it is not so clear that we should reject (ii) and (iii). 2. Superiority in Value and the Repugnant Conclusion a. Two Types of Superiority in Value (From Arrhenius 2005, 97) Let s say that A and B are two types of goods. Page 4 of 10

Strong Superiority: A is strongly superior to B if and only if any amount of A is better than any amount of B. Weak Superiority: A is weakly superior to B if and only if some amount of A is better than any amount of B. b. Why the Total Principle Does Not Imply (i) The total principle does not imply (i) if some of the values in A are weakly (or strongly) superior to some of the values in Drab Z. c. Why we should think that some of the values in A are weakly (or strongly) superior to some of the values in Drab Z Consider what [Parfit] says in his article Overpopulation and the Quality of Life concerning the analogue of the choice between A and Drab Z within a life, the choice between two futures: (1) the Century of Ecstasy, where one lives for a hundred years, all of an extremely high quality; and, (2) the Drab Eternity, where one lives forever, but where each year is only barely worth living although free of pain, these years contain only a few simple pleasures. Parfit claims that although each year of life in the Drab Eternity would be worth living and have value (and given that we are dealing with an infinite number of such years, the Drab Eternity would be of infinite value), the Century of Ecstasy would still be a better life. How can a life of finite value be better than a life of infinite value? Clearly, at least some of the values which would be realized by a person living the Century of Ecstasy must be [weakly or strongly superior to] the values which would be realised by a person living the Drab Eternity. (Portmore 1999, 85) 3. The Inverted Repugnant Conclusion: Hell Z is worse than Hell A. Consider The Two Hells: Hell A (Parfit s Hell One ) is a population consisting of ten people, who each undeservedly suffer terrible agony for fifty years. Their lives are much worse than non existence, and thus they would all kill themselves if they could. Hell B (Parfit s Hell Two ) is a population of ten million people, who each undeservedly suffer the same agony for fifty years minus a day (p. 406). Parfit believes that Hell B is worse than Hell A (p. 406). One way to justify this belief is to claim that a vast increase in the total sum of suffering within a population morally outweighs a very small reduction in the Page 5 of 10

average suffering per life within a population (p. 406). But this claim implies that there is a Hell Z an enormous population of people each of whom undeservedly suffer the same great agony for a little less than a day which would be the worst of all. We are lead from the position that Hell B is worse than Hell A to holding Hell Z to be the worst of all by the same parity of reasoning (the same slippery slope type argument) which lead us from the claim that B is better than A to its ultimate implication, that (Short lived) Z is the best of all. (Imagine Fig. 1 inverted with the blocks labelled Hell A through Hell Z except, in this case, you should imagine that each subsequent block is not just two, but a million, times wider than the former.) (Portmore 1999, 91) How can we deny the repugnant conclusion if we accept that Hell Z is worse than Hell A? 4. The Absurd Conclusion Thus far, we have seen that Parfit is committed to the position that Hell Z is worse than all of its alternatives. Now, unless Parfit holds that there is a difference between the valuation of pleasure and the valuation of pain, he must accept its converse, namely, that Short lived Z is better than all its alternatives (A being one of its alternatives). In fact, Parfit rejects the view that there is a difference between the valuation of pleasure and pain; Parfit rejects what he calls the Asymmetry (the view that states of affairs having a greater quantity of pleasure is of greater value up to a point, but states of affairs having a greater quantity of pain is of limitlessly increasing disvalue) because its acceptance implies the following absurdity: The Absurd Conclusion: For any large population of people almost all of whom have lives that are well worth living the exceptions being one in every fifty million who through sheer bad luck have lives that are not worth living there will be some much larger population whose existence would be a worse alternative even though there would be the same prevailing quality of life and proportionally no greater number of unfortunate people. (The limitless disvalue of the increase in the quantity of pain corresponding to the increase in the number of unfortunate people [one for every fifty million added to the population] would eventually come to outweigh the limited value of what is a proportionately greater increase in the quantity of pleasure.) (pp. 410 11) (Portmore 1999, 92 93) So, it would seem that if we assent to three claims (claims to which Parfit himself assents), namely, (1) that Hell B is worse than Hell A, (2) that there is no point (no quantitative limit) at which an increase in the amount of suffering can no longer be of added disvalue, and (3) that Page 6 of 10

there is no asymmetry between the valuation of pleasure and pain, then we are obliged, on pain of inconsistency, to accept the Short lived Z Conclusion. Either we accept that Short lived Z is better than A or we must deny one of these three claims. If we deny (1), we would have to hold Hell A to be worse than Hell B. If we deny (2), we would have to hold Hell Y to be worse than Hell Z. And, if we deny (3), we would have to accept the Absurd Conclusion. When faced with these alternatives, the Short lived Z Conclusion seems far less repugnant, that is, if it is repugnant at all. The Short lived Z Conclusion is, at the very least, much less repugnant than the Drab Z Conclusion; this much Parfit admits.19 But I believe that one must also admit that it is much less repugnant than the alternative, which is to reject either (1), (2), or (3). (Portmore 1999, 93) II. Two Types of Utilitarianism A. Aggregative Utilitarianism (AU): An act is morally permissible if and only if it maximizes aggregate utility. B. Person Based Utilitarianism (PBU): Person Affecting Intuition (PAI): An alternative X is morally permissible if and only if each person is treated in a morally permissible way in X, that is, if and only if no person is wronged in X. (Roberts 2002, 329) Exculpating Maximizing Principle (EMP): p is not wronged in X if there is no alternative Y in which p has more well being than p has in X. (Roberts 2002, 327) Inculpating Maximizing Principle (IMP): p is (or will be) wronged in X if there is some alternative Y in which p has more well being than in X and there is no q who does or will exist in Y who has more well being in X than in Y. (Roberts 2002, 328) Exculpatory Counting Principle (ECP): p is not wronged in X if, for each Y in which p has more well being than in X, there is some q who does or will exist in X and has more well being in X than in Y and (i) p and q merely reverse positions between X and Y; (ii) the number of people who occupy q s position in Y is at least as great as the number of people who occupy p s position in X; and (iii) for any r who does or will exist in X and occupies neither p s nor q s position in X or Y, r has at least as much well being in X as r has in Y. (Roberts 2002, 330) Inculpating Counting Principle (ICP): p is (or will be) wronged in X if there is some Y such that p has more well being in Y than in X and there is some q who does or will exist in Y and has more well being in X than in Y and (i) p and q merely reverse positions between X and Y; (ii) the number of people who occupy p s position in X is greater than the number of people who occupy q s position in Y; and Page 7 of 10

(iii) for any r who does or will exist in X and occupies neither p s nor q s position in X or Y, r has at least as much well being in Y as r has in X. (Roberts 2002, 331) Nonexistence Principle (NP): For any alternative X and person p, if p does not and will not ever exist in X, then it is not the case that p is or can ever be wronged in X. (Roberts 2002, 331) III. Problems for Aggregative Utilitarianism A. The Infinite Population Problem Example 1 depicts two alternatives, A and B, each of which contains personfor person identical, infinite populations (p1, p2,..., p_). Natural numbers represent levels of individual, overall, lifetime well being. Example 1: Infinite Population Problem A B p1 2 1 p2 2 1 p 2 1 In example 1, the amount of total aggregate well being in A is exactly the same as in B (under plausible mathematical assumptions) since both alternatives contain an infinite amount of aggregate well being. But this means that A and B equally maximize aggregate well being. Thus, [AU] implies that agents may permissibly choose either A or B. (Roberts 2002, 320) PBU, by contrast, implies that agents may not permissibly choose B. This follows from PAI and IMP. B. The Genesis Problem Consider two people, Mom and Dad, who have a single child, Victoria. Suppose that Mom does not want to have a second child since having a second child will adversely affect her health. Suppose that whether a second child is produced or not will on a net basis have no effect at all on the levels of well being of either Dad or Victoria. Suppose, finally, that Mom puts her concerns to the side (perhaps a highly respected philosopher has explained to her what her moral obligations really are) and the couple produce Chuck. Since the couple in fact does choose to have the second child, A represents the road not taken. An asterisk is used to indicate that Chuck does not exist at all in A; and Chuck s level of well being at A is given as zero on the theory that nonexistence is accompanied by neither benefits nor burdens of any kind whatsoever. Alternative B represents the couple s actual choice. Page 8 of 10

Example 2: Genesis Problem A B Dad 5 5 Mom 5 3 Victoria 5 5 Chuck 0* 5 Since B contains more aggregate well being than A does, [AU] is committed to the result that B is better than A and, hence, that B is the morally obligatory choice. (Roberts 2002, 321) PBU, given NP, avoids the implausible verdict that choosing B over A is morally obligatory. However, PBU, given IMP, implies that choosing B over A is morally impermissible. But it seems to me that this too is an implausible verdict. C. The Equality Problem Suppose that the choice to be made is how resources (which are plausibly distinct from well being) are to be distributed across a given population. Suppose further that there is no particular reason why one member of that population should be accorded more well being than another. This is not a case, for example, where the choice is whether to reward persons who work hard or punish those who don t in order to give the population at large a strong incentive to work hard and produce additional wellbeing for many. Then: Example 3: Equality Problem A B p1 9 16 p2 9 3 Because aggregate well being in B is 19 and only 18 in A, [AU] implies that B is the morally correct result. But this implication is implausible. (Roberts 2002, 322) PBU does not imply that it is permissible for agents to choose B over A. D. The Ridiculous Conclusion Problem As we saw, AU implies the ridiculous conclusion. PBU, given NP, avoids this implication. But, as we saw above, this may not be such a big problem depending on whether we re imagining Z to be Drab Z or Short lived Z. IV. A Problem for Person Based Utilitarianism: The Non Identity Problem Page 9 of 10

PBU implies that there is nothing wrong with the choosing the risky policy or with refusing to wait to conceive a normal child in Handicapped Child 2. The combination of NP and IMP imply that choosing the risky policy and refusing to wait to conceive a normal child are morally obligatory. Roberts s treatment of Kavka s Slave Child Case. How this case isn t a true nonidentity problem case. Page 10 of 10