Ordoliberalism and Ordnungspolitik A Brief Explanation

Similar documents
Comparative Study on Liberalism of Friedrich von Hayek and Walter Eucken 1)

Enlightenment of Hayek s Institutional Change Idea on Institutional Innovation

CEREMONY OF CONFERMENT. Friday, 8 November 2013 THESSALONIKI. Presentation by PROFESSOR NICOLAS MOUSSIOPOULOS of PROFESSOR FRANZ JOSEF RADERMACHER

Systematic Policy and Forward Guidance

CENS 2017 PAPER SERIES. Shifts in Poland s alliances within the European Union

Communicating a Systematic Monetary Policy

WHAT YOU OUGHT TO EAT ORIENTATION VERSUS PATERNALISM

A Perspective on the Economy and Monetary Policy

The United States & Latin America: After The Washington Consensus Dan Restrepo, Director, The Americas Program, Center for American Progress

As Joseph Stiglitz sees matters, the euro suffers from a fatal. Book Review. The Euro: How a Common Currency. Journal of FALL 2017

From Bounded Rationality to Behavioral Economics: Comment on Amitai Etzioni Statement on Behavioral Economics, SASE, July, 2009

The judicial power and democratic polity

ECONOMICS AND COMPARATIVE POLITICS FORM IV

econstor Make Your Publications Visible.

The Competitiveness of Financial Centers: A Swiss View

Jurisdictional control and the Constitutional court in the Tunisian Constitution

ECO 171S: Hayek and the Austrian Tradition Syllabus

Keynes as an Interpreter of Classical Economics

We the Stakeholders: The Power of Representation beyond Borders? Clara Brandi

Overview of the Austrian School theories of capital and business cycles and implications for agent-based modeling

Prof. Dr. Bernhard Neumärker Summer Term 2016 Albert-Ludwigs-Universität Freiburg. Constitutional Economics. Exam. July 28, 2016

Economic Reforms and the Indirect Role of Monetary Policy

The Israeli Constitutionalism: Between Legal Formalism and Judicial Activism

by the former President of Germany, Prof. Dr. Horst Köhler on November 17 th, 2013 in Freiburg Check against delivery! ...

Strengthening Competitiveness and Growth in Europe

Any non-welfarist method of policy assessment violates the Pareto principle: A comment

The German Association for the Protection of Intellectual Property (GRUR)

Re: CSC review Panel Consultation

The Law of EC State Aid, Seminar organised by the Centre of European Law at King s College and the European State Aid Law Institute (EStALI)

Address given by Lars Heikensten on the euro (Stockholm, 4 September 2003)

The Social Market Economy in Germany and in Europe - Principles and Perspectives

Willem F Duisenberg: From the EMI to the ECB

Discussion Paper. The Slovak Republic on its Way into the European Union. Eduard Kukan

Choose one question from each section to answer in the time allotted.

Keynesianism in Germany

Weekly Geopolitical Report

SYLLABUS. Economics 555 History of Economic Thought. Office: Bryan Bldg. 458 Fall Procedural Matters

TUSHNET-----Introduction THE IDEA OF A CONSTITUTIONAL ORDER

David Rosenblatt** Macroeconomic Policy, Credibility and Politics is meant to serve

The Petersberg Declaration

Introduction. Bernard Manin, Adam Przeworski, and Susan C. Stokes

Prior to 1940, the Austrian School was known primarily for its contributions

Original citation: (Caldwell, Bruce (2014) George Soros: Hayekian? Journal of Economic Methodology, 20 (4). pp

Myanmar Customary Law as a Standard of Morality

VIDEO STUDY GUIDE > COMMANDING HEIGHTS THE BATTLE FOR THE WORLD ECONOMY - PART 1 - THE CLASH OF IDEAS

Exploring Migrants Experiences

Robust Political Economy. Classical Liberalism and the Future of Public Policy

The following brief sketch of the Swedish legal history and the court system may serve as an introduction to the Swedish answers to the questionnaire.

Why Monetary Freedom Matters Ron Paul

THE CZECH REPUBLIC AND THE EURO. Policy paper Europeum European Policy Forum May 2002

Ideologies of Individualism & Collectivism

The future of abuse control in a more economic approach to competition law Meeting of the Working Group on Competition Law on 20 September 2007

OPINION OF ADVOCATE GENERAL Mengozzi delivered on 7 July 2011 (1) Case C-545/09

Economics is at its best when it does not worship technique for technique s sake, but instead uses

Friedrich Hayek on Social Justice: Taking Hayek Seriously

POLITICAL SCIENCE (POLI)

Themes and Scope of this Book

The Politics of Egalitarian Capitalism; Rethinking the Trade-off between Equality and Efficiency

Call for applications Redistribution and the Law in an Antagonistic World

Meeting Plato s challenge?

Codes of conduct at Canadian multinational enterprises (MNEs): at the confines of private regulation and public policy on labour

Using the Index of Economic Freedom

MARCO SASSÒLI & ANTOINE A. BOUVIER UN DROIT DANS LA GUERRE? (GENÈVE : COMITÉ INTERNATIONAL DE LA CROIX-ROUGE, 2003) By Natalie Wagner

Andreas Dombret: Addressing proportionality in Europe

8 December The EPO-FLIER wants to provide staff with uncensored, independent information at times of social conflict.

A Critique on the Social Justice Perspectives in the Works of Friedrich A. Hayek

NEW CHALLENGES FOR STATE AID POLICY

Magnifizenz, spectabiles, Ladies and gentlemen,

Resistance to Women s Political Leadership: Problems and Advocated Solutions

STATUTE OF THE FRAUNHOFER-GESELLSCHAFT

Political Obligation 3

Comments on Prof. Hodgson s The Evolution of Institutions: An Agenda for Future Theoretical Research

Analysing the relationship between democracy and development: Basic concepts and key linkages Alina Rocha Menocal

Address of Ukrainian President Viktor Yushchenko to the students of the College of Europe in Natolin, Poland

CIEE Global Institute Paris

Economic Assistance to Russia: Ineffectual, Politicized, and Corrupt?

PROFESSIONAL EXPERIENCE

Course Title. Professor. Contact Information

Global Employment Policy - Delocalisation of Labour in Development and Transformation Countries

Written evidence submitted by Hans Peter Ulrich, Civio Public Policy Consulting and Publisher of website

Yearly Report 2011 Wien, December 2011

Politics between Philosophy and Democracy

SCHOOLS OF ECONOMICS. Classical, Keynesian, & Monetary

10/7/2013 SCHOOLS OF ECONOMICS. Classical, Keynesian, & Monetary. as Neo- Classical Supply Side Trickle Down Free Trade CLASSICAL THEORY

The Reformation in Economics

SOURCES OF GOVERNMENTAL FAILURE AND IMPERFECT INFORMATION AS POLITICAL FAILURE

Like many other concepts in political science, the notion of radicalism harks back to the


FRED S. MCCHESNEY, Northwestern University, Chicago, IL 60611, U.S.A.

Presentation Pro. American Government CHAPTER 1 Principles of Government

Oral Hearings Neither a Trial Nor a State of Play Meeting

Sebastian Mallaby is the Paul A. Volcker Senior Fellow for International. Book Review. The Man Who Knew: The Life and Times of Alan Greenspan

PURPOSES AND RESPONSIBILITIES OF COURTS. INTRODUCTION: What This Core Competency Is and Why It Is Important

Papers of the Second International Conference on Development Studies in Ethiopia. Sisay Asefa

Adam Smith and Government Intervention in the Economy Sima Siami-Namini Graduate Research Assistant and Ph.D. Student Texas Tech University

Human Action. Towards a Coordinationist Paradigm of Economics

Be afraid of the Chinese bearing gifts

Northampton Primary Academy Trust

Bluster Notwithstanding, China s Bargaining Position Will Weaken

POLITICS AND LAW ATAR COURSE. Year 12 syllabus

Transcription:

Ordoliberalism and Ordnungspolitik A Brief Explanation by Viktor J. Vanberg With a Foreword by Karl von Wogau, Honorary Member of the European Parliament Published by Aktionskreis Freiburger Schule Initiative für Ordnungspolitik e.v. Freiburg i. Br.

Ordoliberalism and Ordnungspolitik A Brief Explanation by Viktor J. Vanberg Published by Aktionskreis Freiburger Schule Initiative für Ordnungspolitik e.v. Freiburg i. Br., 2017

Foreword The decision of the United Kingdom to leave the European Union and the new policy of the United States concerning the Atlantic Alliance seem to lead to a new movement in European affairs. The European Union shows the ambition to move from a Monetary Union towards an Economic Union between the countries of the Eurozone. Progress in this field can only be reached if common proposals are agreed upon by France and Germany. Again we will have to make choices between an industrial policy French style and the German approach based on rules The fundamental decisions concerning the Euro were made in May 1998. As chairman of the Economic and Monetary Committee of the European Parliament I was involved in the preparation of these decisions. I often remarked at this time that our notions of Ordnungspolitik and Social Market Economy were systematically misunderstood by our friends and allies of other Member Countries. Only few like Mario Monti and André Fourcans had been in contact with these ideas. Therefore I am very grateful to Viktor Vanberg for his brief explanation of the heritage of the Freiburg School of Economics. It will help us to answer the question why Germans are obsessed with rules for their own sake and names the arguments for following time-tested rules. The Maastricht criteria, the no-bailout clause and the independence of the European Central Bank will be battlegrounds in the coming months where these different fundamental perceptions will be confronted. Now that the Euro has weathered its first storms, we will have to learn from this experience. The arguments put forward by Viktor Vanberg will be very useful for those who want to build the Economic and Monetary Union on the basis of time-tested rules. Dr. Karl von Wogau Honorary Member of the European Parliament (Member of the European Parliament 1979 2009) Secretary General, Kangaroo Group

Curriculum Vitae KARL VON WOGAU Born 18. 7. 1941 in Freiburg (Germany). Studies in Law and Economics in Freiburg, Munich, Bonn and Fontainebleau. Doctorate on the constitutional history of Vorderösterreich. Diploma Insead. 1971 1984 Manager at Sandoz ltd in Basel. Since 1984 partner in the law firm Friedrich Graf von Westphalen & Partner in Freiburg. Member of the European Parliament from 1979 2009. In 1984 co-author of the Moreau- Wogau report which was the parliamentary starting point of the Internal Market Programme. 1994-1999 Chairman of the European Parliament s Committee on Economic and Monetary Affairs and Industrial Policy. Spokesman for the European Parliament at the Extraordinary Plenary Meeting of the European Parliament on 2. May 1998 when the final decisions concerning the introduction of the Euro were taken. 2004 2009 Chairman of the newly instituted Subcommittee on Security and Defence of the European Parliament.

Content Ordoliberalism and Ordnungspolitik A Brief Explanation by Viktor J. Vanberg 97 About the Author 19 18 Der Aktionskreis Freiburger Schule The Freiburg School Circle 21 20

Ordoliberalism and Ordnungspolitik A Brief Explanation Viktor J. Vanberg Walter Eucken Institut, Freiburg, Germany INTRODUCTION In the debate surrounding the Eurozone crisis, Germany s rule-based legal approach 1 has become a target of criticism by many of its European partners. Searching for the reason or ideology behind this approach, a number of commentators have pointed to the lasting influence of Ordoliberalism, exemplified by titles such as The Long Shadow of Ordoliberalism: Germany s Approach to the Euro Crisis 2 or Of Rules and Order Germany s Ordoliberalism has had a big influence on policy during the Euro crisis. 3 The purpose of this little booklet is to offer a brief introduction into the tradition of Ordoliberalism, its roots in the so-called Freiburg School, and the rationale behind the concept of Ordnungspolitik that is at the core of this tradition. THE FREIBURG SCHOOL 4 The Freiburg School was founded in the early 1930s by the economist Walter Eucken (1891-1950) and the jurists Franz Böhm (1895-1977) and Hans Großmann-Doerth. They were colleagues in Freiburg University s Faculty of Law and Economics ( Fakultät für Rechts- und Staatswissenschaften ) which provided a most conducive environment for integrating the legal and economic perspectives that are the trademark of the Freiburg School tradition, a tradition for which later the name Ordoliberalism was coined. 1 Volker Berghahn and Brigitte Young 2013, 11. 2 Sebastian Dullien and Ulrike Guérot 2012, 1. 3 The Economist, May 9th 2015, 21-22. 4 For a more detailed discussion of the Freiburg School tradition see Viktor Vanberg 1998. 9

While the founders of the Freiburg School placed themselves firmly in the tradition of classical liberalism, they emphasised, in contrast to some varieties of liberalism, that a market order is not a natural event but a legal-institutional order, an order that requires careful cultivation for its maintenance and proper functioning. They distanced themselves from a laissez-faire liberalism that fails to appreciate the essential role that government has to play in defining and enforcing what they called the economic constitution, that is the legal-institutional framework within which markets operate. How markets function, they insisted, is to a significant extent a matter of constitutional choice, the choice of rules that define the constraints within which market participants can pursue their own purposes. After the Second World War, the Freiburg School assumed a decisive role in the creation of the Social Market Economy in post-war Germany. Ludwig Erhardt who, as West Germany s first economics minister and later chancellor, orchestrated the post-war economic and monetary reforms that lead to the socalled German economic miracle was very much influenced by the Freiburg tradition and relied on its advocates as advisors. Eucken and Böhm emphasised that their interest was not in developing a re-search program as a purely academic enterprise, but in helping to solve the practical question of how a desirable economic order may be created and maintained. The joint efforts of law and economics were to them an indispensable prerequisite for what they called constitutional economic policy ( Wirtschaftsverfassungspolitik ), a policy that seeks to improve the economic order in an indirect manner, by shaping the rules of the game. They contrasted such Wirtschaftsverfassungspolitik or Ordnungspolitik with an economic policy that aims at improving outcomes directly by intervening into the playing of the game, that is by specific interventions into the economic process. The general aim that, in their view, Ordnungspolitik ought to pursue is to create and enforce a framework of rules that guides the market participants self-interested efforts into socially beneficial directions. In other terms, they considered it the task of Wirtschaftsverfassungspolitik or Ordnungspolitik to create conditions under which the invisible hand that Adam Smith had described can be expected to do its beneficial work. 10

The desirable working properties that the classical liberals attributed to market competition, so the Freiburg ordoliberals emphasized, cannot be expected from a competitive process per se. It requires the creation and maintainance of rules of the game that assure what they called Leistungswettbewerb, that is a competition in which success can only be had through better service to consumers. And to create conditions conducive to such Leistungswettbewerb is, in their view, a genuine and indispensible political task, i.e. the task of Ordnungspolitik. A major focus of the Freiburg ordoliberals was on a problem that they described as refeudalisation, a problem that in contemporary economics is discussed under the label rent-seeking. For them the constitutive requirement for a beneficially working competitive market order was that it must be a privi lege-free order, an order in which all persons enjoy the same legal status. As the essential liberal principle they regarded that the state should on no account be allowed to confer privileges, to grant preferential treatment to particular persons or groups from which others are excluded. 5 In no lesser clar-ity than modern public-choice contributions on the problem of rent-seeking, the Freiburg ordoliberals described the fatal political dynamics that inevitably unfolds where governments and legislators are empowered to grant privileges and where, in consequence, interest groups seek to obtain such privileges. Such a government, so Böhm phrased it, is constantly faced with a considerable temptation to meet the contradictory demands of many pressure groups that seek preferential treatment at the expense of other participants or groups of participants. 6 In assigning to the state the task of acting as Hüter der Wettbewerbsord-nung, i.e. as guardian of the competitive order, the Freiburg ordoliberals did not naively expect an unqualified state to serve the common interest. A phrase that the founders of the Freiburg tradition used, and that is a continuing source of controversy, is that a strong state is needed to fend off interest-group pres-sures. This was clearly not meant, as critics have charged, as an argument in favour of an authoritarian state with extensive powers. To the contrary, the formula strong state was meant by them as a shorthand for a state that is constrained by a political constitution that prevents government from becom-ing 5 Franz Böhm 1989, 57. 6 Ibid., 64. 11

the target of special-interest rent-seeking. They regarded the constraints on government that they pleaded for as an instrument that weakens the influence of special interests and works to make ordinary politics more responsive to citi zens common interests. While the ordoliberals stressed the need for provisions that prevent governments and legislators from granting privileges to special interests, they did not discuss in detail the constitutional safeguards that ought to be installed in order to effectively prevent the perverse dynamics of privilege seeking and privilege granting. The principal remedy they saw, though, in strictly limiting government s discretionary power, its authority to intervene with special measures into the economic process. Goverment s ambition to shape or structure the economy should be confined to Ordnungspolitik, to government by general rules rather than discretion. THE REASON OF RULES IN INDIVIDUAL CONDUCT AND IN SOCIAL INTERACTION 7 The ordoliberal postulate that politics should be constrained by rules as op-posed to be given discretionary authority to do what is deemed to be expedient under the given circumstances is surely not self-evident. It naturally invites the question why one may want to be bound by rules rather than being allowed to do in every choice situation what, all things considered, promises to produce the best consequences. Before looking specifically at the reason of rules in poli tics it is useful to consider first the reason of rules in personal conduct and in social interaction. The ultimate reason for rule-following behaviour lies in the fact that, even if in an ever-changing world every choice situation we face is in a sense unique, there are kinds or types of problems we confront repeatedly. For recurrent problems, experience can accumulate over time as to how one can deal with them successfully, notwithstanding the uniqueness of each particular instance. The most general argument for rules is, in this sense, that by following time-tested 7 The Reason of Rules is the title of G. Brennan s and J.M. Buchanan s (1985) treatise on constitutional political economy, a modern research program with apparent affinities to the ordoliberal research tradition. On these affinities, see Viktor Vanberg 1988. 12

rules we may do better overall than if we tried to pick discretionarily in every instance what appears to us to be the best option, given the specific circumstances of each particular case. A recurrent theme in F.A. Hayek s social and economic theory is that the incurable limits of our knowledge and powers of reason require us to rely on rules. The reliance on rules, so he argues, is a device we have learned to use because our reason is insufficient to master the full detail of complex reality. 8 Rules are typically if-then instructions, telling us that if we encounter problem situations of type X, then actions of type Y are called for, such as the traffic-light rule that tells us to stop at red and go at green. Rules instruct us to focus on specified aspects of a choice situation, such as the colour of the traffic light, and to ignore other aspects. Rules are, in other words, selective in what they instruct us to pay attention to, and an obvious question is why it can be advantageous to disregard in one s choices circumstances one may know. The answer to this question lies in the comparison between the selectivity of rules and the unavoidable selectivity of the choices we make when we mean to consider all things. As Hayek argues, in face of the inexhaustible complexity of everything it is impossible for us actually to consider all things and correctly to anticipate all the direct and indirect effects of our actions. In our discretionary choice, we will inevitably pay selective attention to particular aspects of the situations we confront and ignore others the significance of which we would recognize if we were in fact able to consider all things. Neither discretionary choice nor rule following can be perfect in the sense of guaranteeing that in every single instance we do what would be best, all things considered. Under discretionary choice as well as under rule following we will, in this sense, make mistakes. The relevant comparison is in terms of the rate of mistakes, i.e. between the overall pattern of outcomes that is likely to result from discretionary choice as opposed to rule following. The argument for the latter is that time-tested rules are likely to provide in this regard better guidance than our discretionary choices because they incorporate experience that has been accumulated over numerous generations. 8 F.A. Hayek 1960, 66. 13

Closely connected with the knowledge problem is a further reason of rules, the incentive problem. As experience tells us, and psychological research confirms, in discretionary choice we may be tempted to give disproportionate weight to our current needs and to short-term effects of our actions at the expense of their long-term consequences. We are tempted, for instance, to postpone unpleasant but necessary tasks. The very rationale of many of the traditional rules of conduct is to remedy this deficiency in our motivational makeup. As Hayek has put it, they often make us do what we should wish to do from a long-term point of view. 9 As much as we need to rely on rules in organizing our personal conduct, the reason of rules is even more obvious in our dealings with other persons. As Hayek observes, where our conduct will directly affect not ourselves but others and where our primary concern is to adjust our actions to the actions and expectations of others. 10 Rule following is an essential pre-condition for predictability and effective coordination in social interaction. Without rules, we could not form reliable expectations about each other s behaviour. Of particular significance in this context is a reason of rules that has to do with how our own choices affect how other people perceive us, and what that means in turn for our prospects of achieving our goals. This reason, classified under the rubric reputation problem, is apparent when we consider, for instance, the question of whether one should always keep one s promises or rather decide on each particular occasion, considering the specific circumstances of the case, whether one should do so or not. Obviously, discretionary case-by-case choice would allow one to capture opportunities to gain that a principled person will miss. Yet, it is surely also true that a person with a reputation for always keeping her promises will be a much more attractive partner in social dealings, compared to a discretionary opportunist. Being a more attractive partner for cooperative endeavours such a person will have opportunities for mutually beneficial dealings that the opportunist will be excluded from. 9 F.A. Hayek 1960, 66. 10 Ibid. 14

THE REASON OF RULES IN POLITICS The previous section has looked at the reasons why we may benefit in our personal conduct and in our interactions with others from following rules. The same reasons of rules apply at the level of politics with no lesser force than in the private realm. The issue of industrial policy, an issue that has since long marked a division between French political attitudes and German Ordnungspolitik, can serve to exemplify the knowledge problem in politics. If governments were perfect in identifying future winners, and in properly assessing the overall balance of desi-rable and undesirable consequences of granting privileges such as tax exemptions for, or direct subsidies to particular firms or industries, citizens might wish to grant their governments the authority to engage in such policies. Yet, if governments are not perfect predictors of future economic development and are susceptible to lobbying by special-interest groups, citizens have reasons to fear that such discretionary authority may be misused and mal-applied. In the face of such risks citizens interests will be better served by denying government the authority for such discretionary interventions and limiting its authority to a rule-based policy, a policy that aims at providing a conducive legal framework for economic activity in general. If government is given the authority to decide in a discretionary manner which industries to support, which firms to save from bankruptcy, or which banks to bail out, they face not only a knowledge problem but also the incentive problems that come from inviting rent-seeking by special-interest groups. Reelection-seeking politicians will be tempted to seek the support of the groups that are favoured by their discretionary interventions, especially if the costs to the rest of the citizenry are widely dispersed and not obvious to the economically untrained eye. Even if politicians are aware of the long-term damage that such interventions cause, the competition for votes may well induce them to act counter to such insights. Again, considering such risks citizens will be well advised to prefer rule-governed politics over discretionary intervention even if, theoretically, there might be cases in which government interventions could do some good, if they were taken in full consideration of all relevant facts and unaffected by interest-group 15

lobbying a qualification that is unlikely to be fulfilled in real-world politics. This is exactly the problem that, as noted before, the founders of the Freiburg School addressed with their formula of the strong state, meaning a state that is constrained by constitutional rules that do not allow it to give in to interestgroup demands for privileged treatment. No less important than the knowledge and the incentive problem is, in the political as much as in the private realm, the reputation problem. The reputation effect of rule following in politics has found particular attention in the context of fiscal and monetary politics. As F.E. Kydland and E.C. Prescott have argued in a famous article, entitled Rules Rather than Discretion, a discretionary policy which seeks to select the decision which is best, given the current situation is likely to fail to reach its objectives in a dynamic economic system in which the economic players will adjust their expectations. Because of how it affects the expectations of these players, so Kydland and Prescott reason, a policy of aggregate demand management, for instance, tends to result in excessive levels of inflation without lowering unemployment. The general policy conclusion they draw from their analysis is that policymakers should follow rules rather than have discretion... (and) that economic theory should be used to evaluate alternative policy rules and the one with good characteristics should be selected. 11 This corresponds exactly to the central message of the German Ordnungspolitik tradition. It is worth noting that the American economist Henry Simons argued already in the 1930s for an approach to economic policy that comes close to the German conception of Ordnungspolitik. In his paper Rules versus Authorities in Monetary Policy Simons spoke about the danger of substituting authorities for rules which especially deserves attention among students of money. He explicitly argued: An enterprise system cannot function effectively in the face of extreme uncertainty as to the action of monetary authorities... We must avoid a situation where every business decision becomes largely a speculation on the future of monetary policy 12. Without principles ruling over expediency, Simon concluded, political control must degenerate into endless concessions 11 Kydland and Prescott 1977: 487. - Kydland and Prescott add an important argument when they state: In a democratic society it is probably preferable that selected rules are simple and easily understood, so it is obvious when a policymaker deviates from the policy. 12 Simons, 1948 [1936]: 161. 16

to organized minorities, with gradual undermining of the constitutional structure under which free-enterprise economy and representative government can function. 13 CONCLUSION As noted at the beginning, Germany s rule-based legal approach to the Eurozone crisis has been the target of critical comments, and Ordoliberalism has been blamed as its ideological basis. Critics refer to the ordoliberal tradition as Germany s iron cage, 14 and in its above mentioned article The Economist posed the question Why are Germans obsessed with rules for their own sake. 15 The purpose in writing this short essay has been to show that the Freiburg School with its ordoliberal concept of Ordnungpolitik advocates rules not for their own sake but for important reasons and that there is a rationale for the alleged iron cage. It is worth quoting what Hayek said on this issue in his 1962 inaugural lecture at the University of Freiburg: This attitude is likely to be criticized as a dogmatic adherence to rigid principles. This, however, is a reproach which ought not to deter us because principles are the most important contributions we can make to the question of policy. Especially so far as economic policy is concerned, principles are practically all that we have to contribute. 16 13 Ibid.:. 170. 14 Denord, Knaebel and Rimbert 2015. 15 So The Economist in the above (fn. 3) mentioned article. 16 Hayek, 2014 [1963]: 227. 17

REFERENCES Berghahn, Volker and Brigitte Young 2013: Reflections on Werner Bonefeld s Freedom and the Strong State: On German Ordoliberalism and the Continuing Importance of the Ideas of Ordoliberalism to Understand Germany s (Contested) Role in Resolving the Euro Zone Crisis, New Political Economy 18, 768-778. Böhm, Franz 1989. Rule of Law in a Market Economy, in Peacock, A. and Willgerodt, H. (eds) 1989a, 46-67 (abbreviated English translation of Privatrechtsgesellschaft und Marktwirtschaft; in Böhm, Freiheit und Ordnung in der Marktwirtschaft, Baden-Baden: Nomos 1980, 105-168). Brennan, Geoffrey and James M. Buchanan 1985: The Reason of Rules Constitutional Political Economy, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Denord, François, Rachel Knaebel and Pierre Rimbert 2015: Germany Iron Cage, Le Monde diplomatique, English Edition, August 2015. Dullien, Sebastian and Ulrike Guérot 2012: The Long Shadow of Ordoliberalism: Germany s Approach to the Euro-Crisis, Policy Brief, European Council on Foreign Relations, ECFR/49, February. Hayek, F.A. 1960: The Constitution of Liberty, Chicago: The University of Chicago Press. Hayek, F.A. 2014 [1963]: The Economy, Science and Politics, in: Hayek, F.A. 2014: The Market and Other Orders, ed. by Bruce Caldwell, The Collected Works of F.A. Hayek, Vol. XV, Chicago: University of Chicago Press; London: Routledge, 213-231. Kydland, Finn E. and Edward C. Prescott 1977: Rules Rather than Discretion: The Inconsistency of Optimal Plans, Journal of Political Economy 85, 473-491. Simons, Henry C. 1948 (orig. 1936): Rules versus Authorities in Monetary Policy, in: Economic Policy for a Free Society. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 160-183. Vanberg, Viktor J. 1988: Ordnungstheorie as Constitutional Economics The German Conception of a Social Market Economy, ORDO Jahrbuch für die Ordnung von Wirtschaft und Gesellschaft 39, 17-31. Vanberg, Viktor J. 1998: The Freiburg School of Law and Economics: Predecessor of Constitutional Economics, in: Peter Newman (ed.,), The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics and the Law, Vol. 2, London: MacMillan, 172-179. 18

About the Author Viktor J. Vanberg is Prof. em. of the University of Freiburg, Germany, and Senior Research Associate and Member of the Board of the Walter Eucken Institute, Freiburg. Born in 1943 in Aachen, Germany, he earned his academic degrees at the University of Münster (Diplom-Soziologe 1968), the Berlin University of Technology (Dr. phil. 1974) and the University of Mannheim (Dr. phil. habil. 1981). In 1983 he joined the Center for Study of Public Choice in Fairfax, Virginia, USA, as Research Associate. From 1985 to 1995 he taught as Professor of Economics at George Mason University, the Public Choice Center s home. After twelve years of collaboration with Nobel Laureate James Buchanan, Founder and Director of the Center, Viktor Vanberg returned to Germany to take the chair in Economics at Freiburg University that F.A. Hayek had held from 1962 to 1969. In addition to his university appointment, which he held until 2009, he served from 2001 to 2010 as director of the Walter Eucken Institute. His main research interests are in the areas of constitutional political economy, institutional and evolutionary economics, and the behavioural foundations of the social sciences. His publications include Rules and Choice in Economics, London and New York 1994, and The Constitution of Markets, London and New York 2001. For a complete list of publications and further information see: http://www. eucken.de/institut/mitarbeiter/prof-dr-viktor-j-vanberg.html As a sociologist by training in his early career in Germany, and researching and teaching as an economist in later years in the United States, Viktor Vanberg was in a unique position to combine the American public choice theory with the German ordo-liberal Freiburg school and the evolutionary perspective of Hayek s economics. In identifying the similarities of the economic analysis developed by Walter Eucken, main protagonist of the Freiburg School, and the research program of Buchanan s constitutional economics, Viktor Vanberg not only strengthened the international recognition of this academically fruitful research program, but he was also able to clarify important aspects of the Freiburg tradition, such as the question of how to legitimize the economic constitution that Walter Eucken envisioned. Viktor Vanberg showed convincingly that Buchanan s strictly individualist and contractarian approach to constitutional economics can serve as the methodological underpinning of the ordo-liberal 19

school. The voluntary consent of the citizens concerned is the ultimate measuring rod against which the legitimacy of the framework of rules shaping the economy, as well as of revisions in these rules is to be judged. Lars Feld, the successor of Viktor Vanberg as holder of Hayek s chair and director of the Walter Eucken Institute, wrote about his predecessor: In the past years Viktor Vanberg has shown how the traditional (German) Ordnungsökonomik can be connected to today s economics and thus be modernized. The research program of Ordnungsökonomik can build on this important scientific achievement and demonstrate its relevance for constitutional economic analysis and economic policy. 1 The Walter Eucken Institut, Annual Report 2010/2011, Freiburg 2012, 5. 20

AKTIONSKREIS FREIBURGER SCHULE THE FREIBURG SCHOOL CIRCLE About Us The Freiburg School Circle is an initiative of like-minded individuals and corporations who are dedicated to the promotion of the ordo-liberal tradition of thought in economics and society at large. This tradition which has at its core the concept of Ordnungspolitik, that is rule-based economic policy, has been instrumental in shaping the post-war social market economy in Germany founded by Walter Eucken, Ludwig Erhardt and others. The Walter Eucken Institute which cooperates with the University of Freiburg is the foremost center of academic discourse and research in this field. It is regularly ranked among the top economics research institutions in Germany. The Freiburg School Circle proudly supports the Walter Eucken Institute through sponsoring academic conferences, lecture series for the general public, student grants, publications, and the organization of the annual Walter Eucken lecture as well as the biannual award of the Walter Eucken Medal. Executive Board of the Freiburg School Circle with Viktor Vanberg 21

Why support the Freiburg School Circle? The ordo-liberal tradition of thought in economics emphasizes the importance of appropriate rules for all economic participants, including private citizens and corporate actors. These rules constitute the economic order (hence the term Ordo from the Latin term for order). They encompass most importantly but not exclusively: the rule of law, private property and freedom of contract, freedom of competition, an incentive-compatible taxation regime, strong liability rules. The concept of Ordnungspolitik holds that government s foremost responsibility is to create and maintain such a framework of rules. The members of the Freiburg School Circle are deeply convinced of, and committed to the idea that the precepts of the Freiburg School continue to be equally important at both the European and national levels. Our aim therefore is to promote a European discourse on the relevance of the ordo-liberal Freiburg school of thought regarding the challenges that our nations and the European Union face today. If you want to... ensure responsible citizenship in a social and democratic Europe, advocate appropriate reforms in a federally organized Europe, be part of a group of people and organizations dedicated to the promotion of ordo-liberal principles in a globalized world, further these goals through supporting sound academic research, enlightened public discourse, and social events that bring together like-minded people, then consider becoming a member of the Freiburg School Circle. Visit our website www.aktionskreis-freiburger-schule.de for information about possible levels of support and our membership form. 22

Publisher: Aktionskreis Freiburger Schule Goethestraße 10 D-79100 Freiburg Fon: +49-761-79097-0 Fax: +49-761-79097-97 info@ aktionskreis-freiburger-schule.de www.aktionskreis-freiburger-schule.de

www.aktionskreis-freiburger-schule.de www.eucken.de