Political Norms and Moral Values

Similar documents
Can Realism Move Beyond a Methodenstreit?

Reply to Professor Klosko

Facts and Principles in Political Constructivism Michael Buckley Lehman College, CUNY

Justice and collective responsibility. Zoltan Miklosi. regardless of the institutional or other relations that may obtain among them.

Comments on Justin Weinberg s Is Government Supererogation Possible? Public Reason Political Philosophy Symposium Friday October 17, 2008

Rawls versus the Anarchist: Justice and Legitimacy

A political theory of territory

Do we have a strong case for open borders?

Recover it from the facts as we know them

Playing Kant at the Court of King Arthur

S.L. Hurley, Justice, Luck and Knowledge, (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2003), 341 pages. ISBN: (hbk.).

Incentives and the Natural Duties of Justice

Two Pictures of the Global-justice Debate: A Reply to Tan*

DEMOCRACY AND EQUALITY

A Response to Tan. Christian Schemmel. University of Frankfurt; Forthcoming in The Journal of Philosophy

Last time we discussed a stylized version of the realist view of global society.

Though several factors contributed to the eventual conclusion of the

CONTEXTUALISM AND GLOBAL JUSTICE

INTERGENERATIONAL JUSTICE AND COERCION AS A GROUND OF JUSTICE

Legitimacy beyond Consent: State Justification in Context * Alex Levitov Ph.D. Candidate, Department of Politics Princeton University

The Justification of Justice as Fairness: A Two Stage Process

THE POST RAWLSIAN POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY: A CRITIQUE OF THE REALIST STANDPOINT

Political Obligation 3

Power, norms and theory. A meta-political inquiry. Click for updates

Pos 419Z Seminar in Political Theory: Equality Left and Right Spring Peter Breiner

Playing Fair and Following the Rules

POLITICAL AUTHORITY AND PERFECTIONISM: A RESPONSE TO QUONG

STEVEN WALL. Associate Professor. Department of Philosophy, University of Connecticut (2008 to 2010)

Phil 115, June 20, 2007 Justice as fairness as a political conception: the fact of reasonable pluralism and recasting the ideas of Theory

Problems of political anthropology A brief history of political anthropology The subject matter of political anthropology Purposes of political

Pos 500 Seminar in Political Theory: Political Theory and Equality Peter Breiner

Samaritanism and Political Obligation: A Response to Christopher Wellman s Liberal Theory of Political Obligation *

E-LOGOS. Rawls two principles of justice: their adoption by rational self-interested individuals. University of Economics Prague

Multiculturalism and Contextualism: How is Context Relevant for Political Theory?

HUMAN RIGHTS AS POLITICAL DEMAND

At a time when political philosophy seemed nearly stagnant, John Rawls

Philosophy 267 Fall, 2010 Professor Richard Arneson Introductory Handout revised 11/09 Texts: Course requirements: Week 1. September 28.

Great Philosophers: John Rawls ( ) Brian Carey 13/11/18

Introduction 478 U.S. 186 (1986) U.S. 558 (2003). 3

Social and Political Philosophy Philosophy 4470/6430, Government 4655/6656 (Thursdays, 2:30-4:25, Goldwin Smith 348) Topic for Spring 2011: Equality

The Tyranny or the Democracy of the Ideal?

Justifying Punishment: A Response to Douglas Husak

Global Justice and Two Kinds of Liberalism

Brute Luck Equality and Desert. Peter Vallentyne. In recent years, interest in desert-based theories of justice has increased, and this seems to

Libertarianism, GOVT60.14

Laura Valentini Ideal vs. non-ideal theory: a conceptual map

Review of Christian List and Philip Pettit s Group agency: the possibility, design, and status of corporate agents

Rawls and Gaus on the Idea of Public Reason

Republicanism: Midway to Achieve Global Justice?

Is Rawls s Difference Principle Preferable to Luck Egalitarianism?

Justice As Fairness: Political, Not Metaphysical (Excerpts)

Key words: basic liberties; social basis of self-respect; theory of justice.

PH 3022 SOCIAL AND POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY UK LEVEL 5 UK CREDITS: 15 US CREDITS: 3/0/3

Book Prospectus. The Political in Political Economy: from Thomas Hobbes to John Rawls

Introduction to Equality and Justice: The Demands of Equality, Peter Vallentyne, ed., Routledge, The Demands of Equality: An Introduction

Business Ethics Journal Review

THE POSSIBILITY OF A FAIR PLAY ACCOUNT OF LEGITIMACY. Justin Tosi

Justice and Democracy

24.03: Good Food 3/13/17. Justice and Food Production

A Critical Theory of Transnational (In-) Justice: Realistic in the Right Way* Rainer Forst

Advanced Political Philosophy I: Political Authority and Obligation

The character of public reason in Rawls s theory of justice

Democracy and Common Valuations

John Rawls. Cambridge University Press John Rawls: An Introduction Percy B. Lehning Frontmatter More information

What Does It Mean to Understand Human Rights as Essentially Triggers for Intervention?

Rawls, Islam, and political constructivism: Some questions for Tampio

The Debate of Immigration: Democracy, Autonomy, and Coercion

Philosophy and Real Politics, by Raymond Geuss. Princeton: Princeton University Press, ix pp. $19.95 (cloth).

DEMOCRACY, JUDICIAL REVIEW AND DISAGREEMENTS ABOUT JUSTICE

4AANB006 Political Philosophy I Syllabus Academic year

Libertarianism and the Justice of a Basic Income. Peter Vallentyne, University of Missouri at Columbia

Business Ethics Journal Review

Counterfactual justifications of the state

Immigration and freedom of movement

realizing external freedom: the kantian argument for a world state

The Values of Liberal Democracy: Themes from Joseph Raz s Political Philosophy

THE debate between liberalism and republicanism has hitherto concentrated

Robust Political Economy. Classical Liberalism and the Future of Public Policy

From the veil of ignorance to the overlapping consensus: John Rawls as a theorist of communication

Problems with the one-person-one-vote Principle

Normative behaviourism and global political principles

Is the Private Provision of Public Goods Illegitimate? Ted Lechterman Interdisciplinary Ethics Postdoctoral Fellow

Commentary on Idil Boran, The Problem of Exogeneity in Debates on Global Justice

Criminal Justice Without Moral Responsibility: Addressing Problems with Consequentialism Dane Shade Hannum

Definition: Institution public system of rules which defines offices and positions with their rights and duties, powers and immunities p.

Politics between Philosophy and Democracy

Legal Reasoning, the Rule of Law, and Legal Theory: Comments on Gerald Postema, Positivism and the Separation of the Realists from their Skepticism

MAJORITARIAN DEMOCRACY

Disagreement, Error and Two Senses of Incompatibility The Relational Function of Discursive Updating

When I first began studying political philosophy, nearly half a century ago, the question on

Why Majority Rule Cannot Be Based only on Procedural Equality*raju_

THE AGONISTIC CONSOCIATION. Mohammed Ben Jelloun. (EHESS, Paris)

Rawls, Reasonableness, and International Toleration

A Liberal Defence of Compulsory Voting : Some Reasons for Scepticism.

Co-national Obligations & Cosmopolitan Obligations towards Foreigners

Academic Editor: Bernadette Rainey Received: 1 September 2016; Accepted: 13 June 2017; Published: 16 June 2017

INSTITUTIONAL ISSUES INVOLVING ETHICS AND JUSTICE Vol.I - Economic Justice - Hon-Lam Li

Constitutional Democracy and World Politics: A Response to Gartzke and Naoi

John Rawls's Difference Principle and The Strains of Commitment: A Diagrammatic Exposition

Democracy and Justice

Transcription:

Penultimate version - Forthcoming in Journal of Philosophical Research (2015) Political Norms and Moral Values Robert Jubb University of Leicester rj138@leicester.ac.uk Department of Politics & International Relations University Road LE1 7RH U.K. Enzo Rossi University of Amsterdam e.rossi@uva.nl Department of Political Science OZ Achterburgwal 237 1012DL Netherlands Is genuinely normative political theory necessarily informed by distinctively moral values? Eva Erman and Niklas Möller (2013) answer that question affirmatively, and highlight its centrality in the debate on the prospects of political realism, which explicitly eschews pre- political moral foundations. In this comment we defend the emerging realist current. After briefly presenting Erman and Möller's position, we (i) observe that freedom and equality are not obviously moral values in the way they assume, and (ii) argue that a non- moral distinction between politics and sheer domination can give us a distinctively political normativity. The two points are related but freestanding. Against realism, Erman and Möller claim that all coherent and plausible conceptions of political legitimacy must hold onto the ethics first premise and so begin with foundational moral claims (p. 2). Realists cannot consistently insist on the priority of politics to morality and criticize views that invert that relation if it is impossible for them to find some distinctively political normative ground to explain why some orders are legitimate and others not. Erman and Möller also argue that allowing some distinctively moral claim to ground the appropriateness of a political order does not have to reduce politics to the implementation of moral claims; that is, they admit there are sources of practical normativity apart from morality, and that these may be 1

politically relevant ( the political domain includes institutional aspects and practical concerns that do not follow from the moral justificatory basis : p. 15) 1. The autonomy of the political is compatible with adopting an ethics first view. Realism has been disarmed. The central question here is whether realists can avoid holding an ethics first view. Is the ideal of free(ish) and equal(ish) agreement to a political order they use as a criterion of legitimacy inevitably morally grounded? Erman and Möller rightly point out that orders do not have to be freely and equally agreed upon to be stable, since the most oppressive tyrannies can be stable. If mere stability is the realists only distinctively political virtue, an ideal of free and equal agreement is not immanent in it. That does not show that they must have an ethics first view though. To show realists must have an ethics first view, we need to show both that freedom and equality are always distinctively moral values and that realists distinctive virtue is mere stability. Erman and Möller see morality as about how we, as individuals, ought to live our lives (pp. 9-10). The question is then whether this obviously contains the values of freedom and equality that realists need. Erman and Möller say very little about why we should see freedom and equality as moral values, more or less assuming that since they are not political in the sense of being related to mere stability, they must be moral. Is our experience of everyday life and the appropriate forms of interaction with others in it somehow committed to the elimination of hierarchy and individual autonomy, though? Judgments of character, desert, and of duties to family and friends often seem both to bind us without our consent and to draw distinctions between those who have claims on us and those who lack standing. Neither being bound to others involuntarily nor erecting hierarchies of concern seem particularly egalitarian or sensitive to freedom. Given that Erman and Möller admit that there are other sources of normativity, why must realists invocation of the values of freedom and equality be moralistic? To assert that freedom and equality must be moral values is to straightforwardly beg the question 1 It is worth noting that we agree with Erman and Möller that some realists (e.g. Raymond Geuss) incorrectly accuse Rawls of ignoring all or most relevant empirical and contextual information. G.A. Cohen and Robert Nozick are clearer exemplars of political moralism. For a brief discussion of the genesis of their moralistic methodology and its relation to Rawls see Rossi (2014). Arguably moral values play less of a foundational role in Rawls theory of legitimacy (1993), as opposed to his theory of justice (1971). For a realist- friendly reading of Political Liberalism see Sangiovanni (2008), Gledhill (2012), and Jubb (forthcoming). 2

against realists, particularly when much of morality does not seem to be egalitarian or liberal. We can firm up that point by illuminating the potential sources of political, non- moralistic values that realists can appeal to that go beyond stability in a minimal sense. The challenge for realists is to individuate normative principles that do not have to be grounded in pre- political moral claims. Bernard Williams claim that his Basic Legitimation Demand does not represent a morality which is prior to politics but is instead inherent in there being such a thing as politics indicates how this is possible. (2005, p. 5). The thought is that morality is not required to add a normative dimension to our understanding of politics, because there is a conceptual distinction between politics and sheer domination both 'thick' evaluative concepts, in Williams' parlance. 2 In other words, we don't need to draw on pre- political moral beliefs in order to know that might is not right and so have a non- moral foundation for our political theorising. Realists will tend to maintain that right requires might; but that isn't to say that they are one and the same. Realist political normativity can then be carved out by interpreting the practice of politics in a given context. So realists have at least a two- stage process through which they can question the exercise of coercive power. They ask: what is the point and purpose of political authority here and now? And is this specific exercise of power in line with our best answer to the first question? Note how those questions aren't merely descriptive. Though they have a factual component, and so the basis for a discussion which can move beyond countering one moral intuition with another, they also leave room for the normative task of interpretation. 3 To be sure, moral values may inform interpretation, but any moral values realism invokes are filtered through of the role of politics in providing an order for creatures like us. Contra Erman and Möller, realists do not need an ethics first view. Erman and Möller may wish to resist the conceptual distinction between politics and sheer domination, but it is not clear that such resistance would be compatible with their defence of the role of morality in normative political theory. Two considerations are in order here. First, if there is no distinction between politics and sheer domination, then 2 The rough point being that, for thick concepts, normative valence and meaning are closely related one cannot understand such a concept without agreeing on the appropriateness of its use in a given context. See Williams 1985, p. 140-142. 3 Cf. Walzer 1987. 3

an ethics first view would have to think of itself as the justification of brute force through that force s realization of certain moral ends. Can justice and mutual respect really be achieved through naked coercion though? 4 That leads to our second consideration. Typically, the view that all orders are unmitigated domination is suspicious of moral thought in those orders, seeing it necessarily tainted by the circumstances of its production, at best false and more often a justification for and part of the very apparatus of oppression moralists hope to hold up to its standards. If ethics is usually dead politics (Geuss 2008, p. 42) moralists hopes for escaping brute power will be chimerical. Indeed, in a sense realists seem to be less cynical that moralists. They believe our politics, if far from perfect, is not straightforwardly tyrannical, and hope to use its combination of coercion and consent to generate norms to govern it. Moralists on the other hand demand that politics accord with their private moral views and tend to see it as an arena of brute force when it does not, denying that the act of providing an order itself has a normativity. References Erman, E. and Niklas Möller, Niklas. Political Legitimacy in the Real Normative World: The Priority of Morality and the Autonomy of the Political, British Journal of Political Science FirstView Article (June 2013): 1-19. DOI: 10.1017/S0007123413000148, URL: http://journals.cambridge.org/abstract_s0007123413000148 Geuss, R. Philosophy and Real Politics. (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2008). Gledhill, J. Rawls and Realism, Social Theory and Practice 38 (2012): 55-82. Jubb, R. Playing Kant at the Court of King Arthur, Political Studies, forthcoming. 4 Some liberal moralists may claim that, thanks to public justification, their theories of legitimacy don't envisage morally salient coercion. Whatever public justification s merits, its importance must rest on that of freedom and equality, whose character as distinctly moral values we have cast doubt on. Conversely, a self- professed moralist like Col. Kurtz in Francis Ford Coppola's Apocalypse Now (say) won't see a tension between his moral values and brute coercion hardly an appealing position. 4

Rawls, J. A Theory of Justice. (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1971). Rawls, J. Political Liberalism. (New York: Columbia University Press, 1993). Rossi, E. Justice, legitimacy and (normative) authority for political realists. Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 15 (2012): 149-164. Rossi, E. Legitimacy, Democracy, and Public Justification: Rawls Political Liberalism vs Gaus Justificatory Liberalism, Res Publica 20 (2014): 9-25. Sangiovanni, A. Justice and the Priority of Politics to Morality, Journal of Political Philosophy 16 (2008): 137-164. Walzer, M. Interpretation and Social Criticism. (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1987). Williams, B. Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy. (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1985). Williams, B. In the Beginning Was the Deed: Realism and Moralism in Political Argument, edited by Geoffrey Hawthorn. (Oxford: Princeton University Press, 2005). 5