A Rawlsian Paradigm Case

Similar documents
Game-Theoretic Remarks on Gibbard's Libertarian Social Choice Functions

UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA, SAN DIEGO DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS

John Rawls THEORY OF JUSTICE

1 Electoral Competition under Certainty

Problems with Group Decision Making

A Theory of Spoils Systems. Roy Gardner. September 1985

"Efficient and Durable Decision Rules with Incomplete Information", by Bengt Holmström and Roger B. Myerson

Definition: Institution public system of rules which defines offices and positions with their rights and duties, powers and immunities p.

Bargaining and Cooperation in Strategic Form Games

Political Economics II Spring Lectures 4-5 Part II Partisan Politics and Political Agency. Torsten Persson, IIES

Coalitional Game Theory

VALUING DISTRIBUTIVE EQUALITY CLAIRE ANITA BREMNER. A thesis submitted to the Department of Philosophy. in conformity with the requirements for

Problems with Group Decision Making

Rawls versus the Anarchist: Justice and Legitimacy

Phil 115, June 13, 2007 The argument from the original position: set-up and intuitive presentation and the two principles over average utility

(67686) Mathematical Foundations of AI June 18, Lecture 6

Topics on the Border of Economics and Computation December 18, Lecture 8

Do we have a strong case for open borders?

Cambridge University Press The Cambridge Rawls Lexicon Edited by Jon Mandle and David A. Reidy Excerpt More information

SHAPLEY VALUE 1. Sergiu Hart 2

In Elections, Irrelevant Alternatives Provide Relevant Data

AN EGALITARIAN THEORY OF JUSTICE 1

Mathematics and Social Choice Theory. Topic 4 Voting methods with more than 2 alternatives. 4.1 Social choice procedures

Economic philosophy of Amartya Sen Social choice as public reasoning and the capability approach. Reiko Gotoh

GAME THEORY. Analysis of Conflict ROGER B. MYERSON. HARVARD UNIVERSITY PRESS Cambridge, Massachusetts London, England

VI. Rawls and Equality

Economic Staff Paper Series

E-LOGOS. Rawls two principles of justice: their adoption by rational self-interested individuals. University of Economics Prague

Assignment to make up for missed class on August 29, 2011 due to Irene

The Restoration of Welfare Economics

Experimental Computational Philosophy: shedding new lights on (old) philosophical debates

Enriqueta Aragones Harvard University and Universitat Pompeu Fabra Andrew Postlewaite University of Pennsylvania. March 9, 2000

Introduction to Equality and Justice: The Demands of Equality, Peter Vallentyne, ed., Routledge, The Demands of Equality: An Introduction

Any non-welfarist method of policy assessment violates the Pareto principle: A comment

Game Theory and the Law: The Legal-Rules-Acceptability Theorem (A rationale for non-compliance with legal rules)

The Veil of Ignorance in Rawlsian Theory

VOTING ON INCOME REDISTRIBUTION: HOW A LITTLE BIT OF ALTRUISM CREATES TRANSITIVITY DONALD WITTMAN ECONOMICS DEPARTMENT UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA

The Integer Arithmetic of Legislative Dynamics

Voting Systems That Combine Approval and Preference

Introduction to Political Economy Problem Set 3

RATIONAL CHOICE AND CULTURE

2. Welfare economics and the rationale for public intervention 2.3. Equity: From Social Efficiency to Social Welfare

Lecture 7 A Special Class of TU games: Voting Games

David R. M. Thompson, Omer Lev, Kevin Leyton-Brown & Jeffrey S. Rosenschein COMSOC 2012 Kraków, Poland

Notes for Session 7 Basic Voting Theory and Arrow s Theorem

ONLINE APPENDIX: Why Do Voters Dismantle Checks and Balances? Extensions and Robustness

Learning and Belief Based Trade 1

DISSENTING OPINIONS. Yale Law Journal. Volume 14 Issue 4 Yale Law Journal. Article 1

MATH4999 Capstone Projects in Mathematics and Economics Topic 3 Voting methods and social choice theory

Sampling Equilibrium, with an Application to Strategic Voting Martin J. Osborne 1 and Ariel Rubinstein 2 September 12th, 2002.

Voter Sovereignty and Election Outcomes

Justice As Fairness: Political, Not Metaphysical (Excerpts)

Incentives and the Natural Duties of Justice

1 Aggregating Preferences

Proceduralism and Epistemic Value of Democracy

Authority versus Persuasion

Arrow s Impossibility Theorem on Social Choice Systems

The Effects of the Right to Silence on the Innocent s Decision to Remain Silent

Social Choice Theory. Denis Bouyssou CNRS LAMSADE

David Rosenblatt** Macroeconomic Policy, Credibility and Politics is meant to serve

Global Fairness and Aid

Economic Perspective. Macroeconomics I ECON 309 S. Cunningham

HOFSTRA JAW REVIEW SYMPOSIUM: THE IMPLICATIONS OF SOCIAL CHOICE THEORY FOR LEGAL DECISIONMAKING INTRODUCTION: THE SOCIAL CHOICE PERSPECTIVE

Phil 115, June 20, 2007 Justice as fairness as a political conception: the fact of reasonable pluralism and recasting the ideas of Theory

In Defense of Liberal Equality

What is Fairness? Allan Drazen Sandridge Lecture Virginia Association of Economists March 16, 2017

RAWLS DIFFERENCE PRINCIPLE: ABSOLUTE vs. RELATIVE INEQUALITY

BOOK REVIEW BY DAVID RAMSEY, UNIVERSITY OF LIMERICK, IRELAND

'Wave riding' or 'Owning the issue': How do candidates determine campaign agendas?

A THEORY OF JUSTICE. Revised Edition JOHN RAWLS

Social Science and History: How Predictable is Political Behavior?

Planning versus Free Choice in Scientific Research

Aggregation and the Separateness of Persons

2.2. From social efficiency to social welfare - Equity issues (Stiglitz ch.5, Gruber ch.2)

Reconciling Educational Adequacy and Equity Arguments Through a Rawlsian Lens

In his theory of justice, Rawls argues that treating the members of a society as. free and equal achieving fair cooperation among persons thus

Published in Canadian Journal of Economics 27 (1995), Copyright c 1995 by Canadian Economics Association

Justice as fairness The social contract

The Role of the Trade Policy Committee in EU Trade Policy: A Political-Economic Analysis

Tradeoffs in implementation of SDGs: how to integrate perspectives of different stakeholders?

Voting Criteria April

The Proper Metric of Justice in Justice as Fairness

The mathematics of voting, power, and sharing Part 1

John Rawls's Difference Principle and The Strains of Commitment: A Diagrammatic Exposition

Social choice theory

THE EFFECT OF OFFER-OF-SETTLEMENT RULES ON THE TERMS OF SETTLEMENT

The uses and abuses of evolutionary theory in political science: a reply to Allan McConnell and Keith Dowding

The Entitlement Theory 1 Robert Nozick

Random tie-breaking in STV

Social Justice in the Context of Redistribution*

Essays on Incentives and Regulation

THREATS TO SUE AND COST DIVISIBILITY UNDER ASYMMETRIC INFORMATION. Alon Klement. Discussion Paper No /2000

RECONCILING LIBERTY AND EQUALITY: JUSTICE AS FAIRNESS. John Rawls s A Theory of Justice presents a theory called justice as fairness.

Social Rankings in Human-Computer Committees

Safe Votes, Sincere Votes, and Strategizing

Political Selection and Persistence of Bad Governments

Immigration and Conflict in Democracies

Are Second-Best Tariffs Good Enough?

Voting and preference aggregation

The Conflict between Notions of Fairness and the Pareto Principle

Transcription:

Economic Staff Paper Series Economics 3-1976 A Rawlsian Paradigm Case Ray Gardner Iowa State University Follow this and additional works at: http://lib.dr.iastate.edu/econ_las_staffpapers Part of the Economic Policy Commons, Economic Theory Commons, Policy History, Theory, and Methods Commons, and the Public Policy Commons Recommended Citation Gardner, Ray, "A Rawlsian Paradigm Case" (1976). Economic Staff Paper Series. 154. http://lib.dr.iastate.edu/econ_las_staffpapers/154 This Report is brought to you for free and open access by the Economics at Iowa State University Digital Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Economic Staff Paper Series by an authorized administrator of Iowa State University Digital Repository. For more information, please contact digirep@iastate.edu.

A Rawlsian Paradigm Case Abstract This paper considers the problem of applying a theory of justice, especially that of Rawls, to appraise the justice of social institutions. In the first place, one must have a measure of the reasonable expectations of members of society. The measure proposed in this paper is the Shapley value of game theory. One can argue on behalf of this measure that it is consistent both with Rawls' notion of pure procedural justice and with Rawls' conception of the background institutions of justice. In the second place, one must have and defend a rule which judges the basic structures of societies on the basis of the reasonable expectations of their members. Disciplines Economic Policy Economic Theory Policy History, Theory, and Methods Public Policy This report is available at Iowa State University Digital Repository: http://lib.dr.iastate.edu/econ_las_staffpapers/154

A RAWLSIAN PARADIGM CASE Roy Gardner No. 29 March 1976

A RAWLSIAN PARADIGM CASE This paper considers the problem of applying a theory of justice, especially that of Rawls, to appraise the justice of social institutions. In the first place, one must have a measure of the reasonable expectations of members of society. The measure proposed in this paper is the Shapley value of game theory. One can argue on behalf of this measure that it is consistent both with Rawls' notion of pure procedural justice and with Rawls' conception of the background institutions of justice. In the second place, one must have and defend a rule which judges the basic structures of societies on the basis of the reasonable expectations of their members. The paradigm case consists of four different basic structures appraised by six different rules. The major comparison, however, is between Rawls* Difference Principle and Bentham's utilitarian rule. The main argument for any rule is that, within a basic structure, it lead to a social equilibrium, and that the basic structure itself be an equilibrium with respect to alternative basic structures. Equilibrium in the latter sense means the absence of revolutionary tendencies. A society which satisfies the Difference Principle but not necessarily one which satisfies the utilitarian rule achieves such an equilibrium. This then is one sense in which a social order satisfying the Difference Principle is a rational social order. 1. The paradigm case to be considered is that of a society whose members are avid to protect and promote their interests. Different societies can be imagined; the argument to follow need not work for them. The paradigm case is framed in such a way that the theory of games applies to society.

-2~ The members of society shall be referred to as the set N of the first n Integers. The members of society are held fixed in any comparison of different social structures. Since the paper does not deal with the difficult problem of justice between generations, it is best to think of the members of society as contemporaries of one another. In the Rawlsian interpretation, the members of society also constitute the assembly in the Original Position. 2. The strong assumption is made initially that the primary social goods can be measured by a utility which is transferable. Not only can the utilities of two individuals be compared, but utility between them can be transferred by means of the primary social goods. The medium of utility exchange is best called "money." Relaxing the transferabillty assumption is possible, but it complicates things considerably. It is far from clear whether comparability can be relaxed; no attempt in that direction will be made here. 3. The basic structure of society is "the way in which the major social institutions distribute fundamental rights and duties and determine the division of advantages from social cooperation." [7, p. 7] Formally, the basic structure is represented by the function v from the set of subsets of N to the real numbers. Let S be a logically possible group of members of society; then v(s) represents the utility which the members of S collectively can guarantee themselves. Of course, the existence of such guarantees is predicated upon the legal system, property relations, markets, and government In a word, the major social institutions. Thus different basic structures correspond, in general, to different functions v. Requiring that v be superaddltive that is, for any groups S and T

-3- v(s) + v(t) S v(s U T) then captures the idea of gains from social cooperation. Other formal representations of the basic structure are possible, but this one has the virtue of simplicity. 4. Rawls* Difference Principle belongs to the class of rules which appraise the justice of societies according to the reasonable expectations of their members. The essential problem with any such rule is Co get the data necessary for applying the rule. Interpersonal comparisons are made in terms of expectations of primary social goods...! define these expectations simply as the index of these goods which a representative individual can look forward to. One man's expectations are greater than another's if this index for someone in his position is greater. (7, p. 92] Rawls mentions two difficulties confronting such a comparison; One problem clearly is the construction of the index itself. How are the different primary social goods to be weighed? Assuming Chat the two principles of justice are serially ordered, this problem is greatly simplified...the only index problem that concerns us is that for the least advantaged group. [7, p. 93] Another difficulty is this. It may be objected that expectations should not be defined as an index of primary goods anyway but rather as the satisfactions to be expected when plans are executed using these goods. [7, p. 94] Now as long as the primary social goods can be measured by a utility which is transferable, neither of these problems arises. The first problem does not arise because a single primary social good, money, stands proxy for all; the second, because utility is synonymous with money. However, the first problem does arise when utility cannot be transferred by means of money. In any case, one still faces the problem of forming reasonable expectations, given the basic structure of society.

-A- Since the idea of representing the basic structure of society by a real valued function is due to game theory [6, Chapters 4 & 25], it is natural to look to game theory for possible measures of reasonable expectation. The measure of reasonable expectation this paper advances is the Shapley value of a game [2, Appendix A], 5. The Shapley value is a mathematical operation defined on a game (N,v), consisting of the members and the basic structure of society. One finds the Shapley value of a player by computing the expected value of his marginal contribution in a random ordering of ail the players. The Shapley value of a game, then, is the vector of the values of the individual players 9ov - ( cpovd). 9ov(2),... ^ov(n)). In the case of transferable utility, the Shapley value of a player is a unique real number. An example will help clarify the calculation underlying the Shapley value. Consider a society consisting of three members, with the following basic structure: v( ill ) - v{ i2! ) - v( isl ) = 0 v( il,2l ) = 9 v( il,3! ) - 3 v( i2.3i ) - 0 v( ll,2.3l ) - 9 Represented here is a situation with a hypothetical orlgin no player can guarantee himself utility and with gains from cooperation which are not

-5- distributed uniformly atnofig the players. Indeed, players 2 and 3 do not gain at all from cooperation; but all other groups do gain from cooperation, though not to the same extent. Suppose that a player is paid his marginal contribution to a group that is, what the group can achieve with him less what the group can achieve without him. Then a player's marginal contribution depends on what group he joins. This wealth of possibilities is accounted for by the idea of a random ordering of society namely, all the logically possible permutations of the members of the set N. If one considers all random ordering^ equally possible, then a player's rational expectation in a social game is the mathematical expectation of his marginal contribution in a random ordering. The required calculations for the example are set out in Table I. The reasoning for the first line of the table is as follows. Since player 1 is the first to join a coalition, his marginal contribution is 0 =v( 11 I); then player 2 joins player 1, his marginal contribution being 9 = v( 1,2 ) - v( {1 I ); finally, when player 3 joins players 1 and 2, his marginal contribution is 0 = v( j 1,2,3 \) - v( j 2,3 j ). This reasoning is then repeated for each line of the table, and the resulting marginal contributions are averaged. The Shapley value of the game v, cpov, turns out to be the vector of utilities (5, 3.5,.5). Thus, player 1 can reasonably expect to do the best in this society, followed by player 2 and then player 3.

-6- TABLE I. Calculation of Kcasonable lixpectation (Shapioy Value) Marginal Marginal Marginal Random ordering of players contribution, player 1 contribution, player 2 contribution, player 3 12 3 0 9 0 13 2 0 6 3 2 13 9 0 0 2 3 1 9 0 0 3 12 3 6 0 3 2 1 9 0 0 average marginal contribution, player 1 30/6 =5 = 9ov(l) average marginal contribution, player 2 = 21/6 = 3.5 = 9ov(2) average marginal contribution, player 3 = 3/6 =.5 = 9ov(3) 6. It is clear that calculating a Shapley value to find one*s reasonable expectation is not the most obvious thing to do. However, in a Rawlsian paradigm case, the ideas of pure procedural justice and the back ground institutions of justice lend some credence to such a calculation. First consider Rawls* idea of pure procedural justice: Pure procedural justice obtains when there is no independent criterion for the right result: instead there is a correct or fair procedure such that the outcome is likewise correct or fair, whatever it is, provided that the procedure has been properly followed. In order to apply the notion of pure procedural justice to distributive shares it is necessary to set up and to administer impartially a just system of institutions. Only against the back ground of a just basic structure, including a just political constitution and a just arrangement of economic and social insti tutions, can one say that the requisite just procedure exists. [7, pp. 86-7] In pure procedural justice, then, distributions of advan tages are not appraised in the first instance by confronting a stock of benefits available with given desires and needs of

-7- known individuals. The allotment of the items produced takes place in accordance with the public system of rules, and this system determines what is produced, how much is produced, and by what means. Thus in this kind of procedural justice the correctness of the distribution is founded on the justice of the scheme of cooperation from which it arises and on answering the claims of individuals engaged in it, A distribution cannot be judged in isolation from the system of which it is the outcome or from what individuals have done in good faith in the light of established expectations. If it is asked in the abstract whether one distribution of a given stock of things to definite individuals with known desires and preferences is better than another, then there is simply no answer to this question. The conception of the two principles does not interpret the primary problem of distribu tive justice as one of allocative justice. [7, p. 88] Rawls' notion here is that of a mechanism which, once set in motion, generates procedurally just distributions. Ruled out are all compensations and redistributions after the mechanism has worked itself out. In particular, if the background institutions in fact generate a distribution of primary social goods equivalent to that given by the Shapley value, then reasonable expectations have been realized and the Shapley value must correspond to a purely just procedure. Consider then Rawls' background institutions of justice; The ideal scheme sketched in the next several sections makes considerable use of market arrangements. It is only in this way, I believe, that the problem of distribution can be handled as a case of pure procedural justice...at the start I assume that the regime is a property-owning democracy since this case is likely to be better known. But, as I have noted, this is not intended to prejudge the choice of regime in particular cases. [7, p. 274] This account of distributive shares is simply an elaboration of the familiar idea that income and wages will be just once a (workably) competitive price system is properly organized and embedded in a just basic structure. These conditions are sufficient. The distribution that results is a case of back ground justice on the analogy with the outcome of a fair game. [ 7, p. 304 ] Since the decision-makers in the Original Position know the general facts of social theory, they know that the Shapley value reproduces the distribution

-8- of income (money, utility) yielded by a perfectly competitive economy. [ 2,3 ] In pure procedural justice, given the background of institutions of justice, the price system actually performs the Shapley value calculation, 7. A Rawlsian paradigm case requires that there exist more than one possible basic structure for society. The paradigm case here will consist of the basic structure given in //5, hereafter denoted v^, and three others Vji, The basic structures of the latter three are as follows; Group Vjj 1,2( 4 3 2 l,3j 2 2 1.5 2,3] 1 1.5 1.2,3j 6 5 3 All four basic structures share a hypothetical origin, at which no individual guarantees himself any utility. The reasonable expectation for a player in each of these four baislc structures (recall Table I) is given in Table XI. This is the data that ultimately enables those in the Original Position to choose a basic structure for society. Notice that regardless of which social structure is chosen, player 1 is best off and player 3 is worst off. This fixed inequality in life, one might say, is due to inequalities in native ability. Different social structures may frame these inequalities differently, but no social structure can overturn them. Thus there exists an identifiable leaat-priviliged class, the same for every possible society. This feature of the paradigm case proves crucial later on.

-9- TABLE II. Reasonable expectations Reasonable Expectation of society Player 1 Player 2 Player 3 5 3.5 0.5 ^11 ^iii 2.666 2.166 1.166 2.166 1.666 1.166 1.416 0.916 0.666 8. There are two choices that can be made in the Original Position: either choice of a basic structure of society, or choice of a rule for choosing a basic structure. The second of these choices is the more fundamental, in the sense that it rationalizes choices of a first kind. In Rawls theory, for instance, the latter choice comes first in a sequence of choices. In this paper, attention is restricted to rules for choosing a basic structure that depend only on the information on reasonable expectation. > > The following list of such rules is hardly exhaustive, but it is suggestive of the inherent possibilities. Rule 1 (Difference Principle) v^ is more just than v^^ if and only if min 9oVj (i) ^ xnin ^ov^^ (i) i i This is the choice of rule that Rawls is keen to defend. Rule 2 (Classical Utilitarianism) v^ is more just than if and only if E %v (i) > S qtov (i) i i i

-10- This Is the rule that Rawls sees as the chief coiq}etition for the Difference Principle, since for fixed K, classical utilitarianism and average utilitarianism coincide. Noteworthy is the profound simplicity of these two rules. This simplicity takes the form of a one-dimensional inference: the judgment of societies boils down to a single number, measured on a single dimension. Applying Rule 1 to the paradigm case, one has the ordering: ^III more just than v_, more just than v-. The lexical version of Rule 1 J J j- breaks the tie between v^^ and in favor of By contrast. Rule 2 leads to the ordering: v^ more just than more just than more Just than The important disagreement between Rule 1 and 2 in the paradigm case is that the former finds v^ the least just, while the latter finds v^ the most just. Rule 3 (Efficiency) v^ is more just than v^^ if and only if, for all i e N, 9ov^ (1) ^ VoVjj (i) This rule appeals to unanimity for its support. Unlike Rules 1 and 2, it leads to an incomplete ordering. The only judgment it makes in the paradigm case is that is more just than Notice that it agrees on this judgment with both Rule 1 and Rule 2; it is easy to prove that this agree ment is a general fact. This is a reason for saying that Rule 3 represents a minimal conception of justice. The following three rules make interesting contrasts with Rule 1. Rule 4 (Perfectionism) v^ is more just than v^^ if and only if

-11- max ^ov (i) > max "^ov (i) il jl ^ Under this rule, the best-off are made as well off as they can be. In the paradigm case, but not in general. Rule 4 agrees with the judgments of Rule 2. Rule 5 (Envy) Vj. is more just than if and only if max 9ov (i) max ^ov (i). i ^11 This rule calls for the bringing down of the best-off. It leads to judgments exactly opposite of those of Rule 4. Rule 6 (Misanthropy) is more just than if and only if min ^ov^ (i) ^ min 9ov (i). i i This rule captures some of the psychology behind "the vice of hating mankind." It leads to judgments exactly opposite of those of Rule 1. For easy reference, one may call Rules 1, 4, 5 and 6 the max-min, min-max, and min-min rules respectively. It is hard to see how either Rule 5 or Rule 6 can be a stable conception of justice; and this may explain Rawls* neglect of them. The meaning of these six rules is better grasped by looking at the choices of social structure which each of them justifies: Choice of Justified by Rule(s) Vj 2,3,4,6 1,3 1,3 Viv 5

-12- There are other conceivable rules for instance, rules of a statistical nature or rules that are concerned with the median reasonable expectation- but from now on Rules 1 and 2 will occupy the center of attention. 9. This section considers arguments bearing on the choice between Rule 1 and Rule 2, something which any paradigm case calling itself Rawlsian should be able to do. The main argument for any rule is that it should lead to an equilibrium situation, both reflectively those choosing do not regret their choice and socially the social structure and its attendant distribution of primary social goods are equilibria. The main argument for Rule 2 runs as follows. Consider two social structures, only the first of which maximizes the sum of reasonable expectations. Let (B^, B^) be any distribution of money in the second social structure. Then there exists a distribution of money (A^, A^, A^) in the first society such that for every individual i, A. is greater than B.. Thus one may say that the stability underlying Rule 2 is that of redistributive unanimity. On this argument, Rule 2 contains within itself a compensation principle, which is hardly surprising in view of the originators of such principles. [4, 5] However, nothing in the above argument suggests that the distribution of money ^2'» is an equilibrium distribution. above and beyond the equilibrium. It may require compensations to be paid, That such compensations will actually be paid runs counter to the idea of pure procedural justice. There, when all the social institutions are accounted for and not just the economic ones, the outcome is what the agents can reasonably expect. In pure procedural justice, there is no extra mechanism for making redistributions

-liafter the process has worked itself out. ('omparc this to tlic typical applications of the compensation principle, where non-economic Institutions provide just such a mechanism. How convincing counterfactual redistributive unanimity will be to those in the Original Position must remain a contingent question. This is a good reason, then, for turning attention to Rule 1. The argument for Rule 1 is to show how a social equilibrium in the presence of Rule 1 leads to a reflective equilibrium. That a distribution of primary social goods within a social structure is an equilibrium means that there are no forces within the social structure to upset such a distribution it is the outcome of all the tendencies inherent within the system. An example, for a private-ownership economy, is the competitive equilibrium, at which the forces of demand and supply are equal in every market. As seen above, in perfect competition such an equilibrium corresponds to the reasonable expectations of every agent. Thus, the very framework within which Rule 1 operates pure procedural justice guarantees that the distribution of primary social goods is itself an equilibrium. The idea that a basic structure of society is an equilibrium requires a wider notion of equilibrium, namely, equilibrium with respect to other basic structures of society. The transformation of one basic structure of society into another is precisely what is called revolution. Thus, a basic structure of society is an equilibrium if it is free of revolu tionary tendencies. The question that arises is whether a basic structure chosen under Rule 1 is an equilibrium with respect to revolutionary tendencies.

-14- Comparing basic structures and the case where Rule 1 and 2 disagree, gives one a better grasp of revolutionary tendency. Now the reasonable expectations in Table II are taken as representative of those of members of the high, middle, and low classes, respectively. Suppose the ruling basic structure is v^. Then the lowest class has a very real revolutionary incentive nothing to lose, something to gain by transforming that basic structure into Even as the lowest class, their situation is greatly improved. On the other hand, one could assert that v^^ is vulnerable to the counterrevolutionary tendencies of the middle and upper classes. As always, the theory of justice presupposes the theory of the modem state; but in the modern state, it is typically the lowest class that entertains revolutionary tendencies. As a first approximation, at least, one is entitled to disregard the counterrevolutionary tendencies of the higher classes. Now it is clear that a basic structure chosen by Rule 1 is a full social equilibrium. The revolutionary class has nothing to gain by revolution, because for it there exists no revolutionary alternative. It remains to connect the reasoning for social equilibrium with that for reflective equilibrium. To this end, it suffices to connect the above argument with Rawls' argument based on the strains of commitment. parties in the Original Position...consider the strains of commitment. They cannot enter into agreements that may have consequences they cannot accept. They will avoid those that they can adhere to only with great difficulty. [7, p. 176] In particular, the parties must consider the revolutionary temptation they will be under if they belong to the lowest class of society, supposing Rule The

-15-1 is not applied. What of the counterrevolutionary strains of commitment? Here is where Rawis' duty to uphold just institutions enters the argument. For if parties in the Original Position accept such a duty and choose Rule 1, then they are coinmiting themselves to resist the temptation of counter revolutionary tendencies. Thus, the duty to uphold just institutions expresses in another way the asymmetry between revolution and counter revolution. One may say, after Rawls, that "A society's being good is its having the properties it is rational to want in any society." If it is rational to want a society which realizes reasonable expectations and resists revolutionary temptations, then societies satisfying the Difference Principle are truly good ones. Put a different way, the Difference Principle proposes a society which is rational when it is actually chosen. 10. Two of the main features of the paradigm case were the transferability of utility and the existence of a unique least-priviliged class. It is worth considering how sensitive the results of the paradigm case are to these features. When utility is no longer transferable, Rawl's first index number problem (see page 3) arises. The previous analysis of reasonable expec tation is considerably complicated. Now it may turn out that the reasonable expectation of an individual is not a unique number, but a set of numbers--each attaching to a different competitive price system. Thus, the one-dimensionality of Rules 1 and 2 is lost: what one is comparing is no longer a single number, but a set of numbers. The problem arising with such comparisons is rather tricky and will not be settled here, since in any event it goes beyond the bounds of a paradigm case.

-16- When there no longerexlsts a unique least-priviliged class, it need no longer be the case that a society satisfying the Difference Principle is one free of revolutionary tendencies. To see this, consider Table III of the reasonable expectations for the (unspecified) basic structures Vv. and TABLE III. Cyclic Reasonable Expectations reasonable expectation, reasonable expectation, reasonable expectation, player 1 player 2 player 3 ^v 3 1 2 ^VI 2 3 1.1 ^11 ^ ^ ^ Of these three basic structures, clearly only satisfies the Difference Principle. Nevertheless, it is subject to revolutionary temptation on the part of all classes of society except for the highest class (of which player 2 is representative). For player 3, both v^ and are revolutionary alternatives to v^^; for player 1, v^. What makes this possible is the fact that a different class is least-priviliged in each basic structure. In fact, the basic structures here form a cycle, just as in Condorcet's paradox of voting [1, p. 3], The existence of such cycles is the heart of Arrow's problem of social choice [1, p. 59]; examples like those of Table 3 suggest that the connection between Arrow's problem and Rawls' problem is closer than the latter himself believes [7, p. 134], In the last resort, whether there exists a least-priviliged class common to all basic structures of society must itself remain an open question.

-17- BIBLIOGRAPHY 1. K. J. Arrow, "Social Choice and Individual Values," Yale, New Haven, Conn., 1963. 2. R. J, Auinann, Values of Markets with a Continuum of Traders, Econometrica XXXII (1975), 611-646. 3» R. J. Aumann and L. S. Shapley, "Values of Non-Atomic Games," Princeton University Press, Princeton, New Jersey, 1974. 4. R. Harrod, "Scope and Method of Economics," Economic Journal XLVIII (1938), 383-412. 5. N. Kaldor, Welfare Propositions of Economics and Interpersonal Comparisons of Utility, Economic Journal XLIX (1939), 549-52. 6. J. von Neumann and 0. Morgenstem, "Theory of Games and Economic Behavior," John Wiley and Sons, New York, N.Y., 1964. 7. J. Rawls, "A Theory of Justice," Harvard, Caiii>ridge, Mass., 1971.