Comment on Andrew Walton The Basic Structure Objection and the Institutions of a Property-Owning Democracy

Similar documents
The Concept of Property in Rawls's Property-Owning Democracy

Newcastle University eprints

Why Does Inequality Matter? T. M. Scanlon. Chapter 8: Unequal Outcomes. It is well known that there has been an enormous increase in inequality in the

Reply to Arneson. Russel Keat. 1. The (Supposed) Non Sequitur

The Place of the Market in a Rawlsian Economy

Rawls versus the Anarchist: Justice and Legitimacy

Incentives and the Natural Duties of Justice

Background Justice over Time: Property-Owning Democracy versus a Realistically Utopian Welfare State

Democratic Rights and the Choice of Economic Systems

Commentary on Idil Boran, The Problem of Exogeneity in Debates on Global Justice

Global Justice and Two Kinds of Liberalism

Book Reviews. Julian Culp, Global Justice and Development, Palgrave Macmillan, Basingstoke, UK, 2014, Pp. xi+215, ISBN:

SPECIAL ISSUE ON TRANSITIONAL JUSTICE

S.L. Hurley, Justice, Luck and Knowledge, (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2003), 341 pages. ISBN: (hbk.).

Politics in the United States *

MIRIAM RONZONI Two Concepts Of The Basic Structure, Global Justice*

Do we have a strong case for open borders?

The Justification of Justice as Fairness: A Two Stage Process

John Rawls THEORY OF JUSTICE

The Determinacy of Republican Policy: A Reply to McMahon

CONTEXTUALISM AND GLOBAL JUSTICE

AN ASSESSMENT OF COHEN'S CRITIQUE ON RAWLS: IS THE EGALITARIAN ETHOS EMBEDDED IN THE RAWLSIAN SOCIETY?

Social Practices, Public Health and the Twin Aims of Justice: Responses to Comments

Comment on Véronique Zanetti. On Moral Compromise

Is Rawls s Difference Principle Preferable to Luck Egalitarianism?

'Wave riding' or 'Owning the issue': How do candidates determine campaign agendas?

In his account of justice as fairness, Rawls argues that treating the members of a

OpenStax-CNX module: m Immigration * OpenStax. Abstract. By the end of this section, you will be able to:

Why Rawls's Domestic Theory of Justice is Implausible

-Capitalism, Exploitation and Injustice-

The Theory of Marxian Liberalism

Political Authority and Distributive Justice

Two Pictures of the Global-justice Debate: A Reply to Tan*

A Response to Tan. Christian Schemmel. University of Frankfurt; Forthcoming in The Journal of Philosophy

The limits of background justice. Thomas Porter. Rawls says that the primary subject of justice is what he calls the basic structure of

At a time when political philosophy seemed nearly stagnant, John Rawls

Definition: Institution public system of rules which defines offices and positions with their rights and duties, powers and immunities p.

In his theory of justice, Rawls argues that treating the members of a society as. free and equal achieving fair cooperation among persons thus

Rawls and Natural Aristocracy

Strategic Insights: Getting Comfortable with Conflicting Ideas

The limits of background justice. Thomas Porter. Social Philosophy & Policy volume 30, issues 1 2. Cambridge University Press

POLITICAL AUTHORITY AND PERFECTIONISM: A RESPONSE TO QUONG

WORLD HEALTH ORGANIZATION

When Transaction Costs Restore Eciency: Coalition Formation with Costly Binding Agreements

Economic philosophy of Amartya Sen Social choice as public reasoning and the capability approach. Reiko Gotoh

CHAPMAN v. THE UNITED KINGDOM JUDGMENT 1. Note of judgment prepared by the Traveller Law Research Unit, Cardiff Law School 1.

Notes from discussion in Erik Olin Wright Lecture #2: Diagnosis & Critique Middle East Technical University Tuesday, November 13, 2007

In Defense of Rawlsian Constructivism

IS THE PERSONAL POLITICAL?:

Contract law as fairness: a Rawlsian perspective on the position of SMEs in European contract law Klijnsma, J.G.

Comments: Individual Versus Collective Responsibility

RECONCILING LIBERTY AND EQUALITY: JUSTICE AS FAIRNESS. John Rawls s A Theory of Justice presents a theory called justice as fairness.

INTERGENERATIONAL JUSTICE AND COERCION AS A GROUND OF JUSTICE

Official Journal of the European Union. (Legislative acts) DIRECTIVES

Precluding Wrongfulness or Responsibility: A Plea for Excuses

SOCIAL JUSTICE AND THE MORAL JUSTIFICATION OF A MARKET SOCIETY

The Rawlsian justification of a property-owning democracy

Reforming the speed of justice: Evidence from an event study in Senegal

Phil 115, June 20, 2007 Justice as fairness as a political conception: the fact of reasonable pluralism and recasting the ideas of Theory

Applied Economics. Department of Economics Universidad Carlos III de Madrid

Lecture I: Political Economy and Public Finance: Overview. Tim Besley, LSE. Why should economists care about political economy issues?

Effective and Accountable Judicial Administration

Civil Disobedience and the Duty to Obey the Law: A Critical Assessment of Lefkowitz's View

SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES

Great Philosophers: John Rawls ( ) Brian Carey 13/11/18

Thoughts on G. A. Cohen's Final Testament

Equality of opportunity: Definitions and testable conditions, with an application to income in France

John Rawls, Socialist?

Robbins as Innovator: the Contribution of An Essay on the Nature and Significance of Economic Science

LIBERAL EQUALITY, FAIR COOPERATION AND GENETIC ENHANCEMENT

Friedrich Hayek on Social Justice: Taking Hayek Seriously

E-LOGOS. Rawls two principles of justice: their adoption by rational self-interested individuals. University of Economics Prague

Bridging Ideal and Non-ideal Theory. An Incrementalist Approach to Normative Theorising

Social and Political Philosophy Philosophy 4470/6430, Government 4655/6656 (Thursdays, 2:30-4:25, Goldwin Smith 348) Topic for Spring 2011: Equality

nagler, niemann - apsa97.tex; August 21, Introduction One of the more robust ndings over the last 50 years in research on elections has been

Herman, Gabriel Morality and Behaviour in Democratic Athens: A Social History

Corruption and Anti-Corruption Poli Title China

DEMOCRACY AND EQUALITY

Jan Narveson and James P. Sterba

Philosophy 285 Fall, 2007 Dick Arneson Overview of John Rawls, A Theory of Justice. Views of Rawls s achievement:

ECON 4270 Distributive Justice Lecture 4: Rawls and liberal equality

A Rawlsian Perspective on Justice for the Disabled

Justice As Fairness: Political, Not Metaphysical (Excerpts)

Key words: basic liberties; social basis of self-respect; theory of justice.

Introduction. Cambridge University Press Rawls's Egalitarianism Alexander Kaufman Excerpt More Information

1. The definition of historically disadvantaged persons (clause 1: section 1);

Philosophische Winterakademie 07. bis 10. Februar 2017 Wettbewerb Philosophischer Essay. 2. Platz

IV. GENERAL RECOMMENDATIONS ADOPTED BY THE COMMITTEE ON THE ELIMINATION OF DISCRIMINATION AGAINST WOMEN. Thirtieth session (2004)

The Importances of Economic Development to Consolidate Political Stability in Oromia

Justice and the Egalitarian Ethos

Reconciling Educational Adequacy and Equity Arguments Through a Rawlsian Lens

Republicanism: Midway to Achieve Global Justice?

Comments on Justin Weinberg s Is Government Supererogation Possible? Public Reason Political Philosophy Symposium Friday October 17, 2008

Executive summary 2013:2

Crime Victims Rights Act: A Sketch of 18 U.S.C. 3771

INTRODUCING SOCIAL ACTION AND COOPERATION

Meena Krishnamurthy a a Assistant Professor, Department of Philosophy, Associate

The Human Rights Committee established under article 28 of the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights:

Institutional Boundaries on the Scope of Justice

International Relations. Policy Analysis

Transcription:

Analyse & Kritik 01/2013 ( Lucius & Lucius, Stuttgart) S. 187192 Carina Fourie Comment on Andrew Walton The Basic Structure Objection and the Institutions of a Property-Owning Democracy Abstract: Andrew Walton argues that a Rawlsian property-owning democracy (POD) requires a fraternal ethos and certain forms of social interaction, such as high trade union membership. The basic structure objection could be used to challenge these claims as it indicates that Rawls's principles of justice should only be applied to the basic structure of society, and not, for example, to an ethos. Walton has two responses to the objection: rstly, that it does not apply to his argument, and, secondly, even if it were to apply, the objection itself is unconvincing. In this article I argue however that (1) the basic structure objection does apply as a fraternal ethos is dicult to reconcile with Rawls's understanding of what should be included as part of the basis structure, and (2) although I do not defend the basic structure objection, it is not made explicit in Walton's argument why the objection should be dismissed as unconvincing. John Rawls's claim that the principles of justice should apply to the basic structure of society (as the primary subject of justice) is considered to be a dening element of his theory of justice. Rawls has described the basic structure as the way in which the main political and social institutions of society t together into one system of social cooperation and the way they assign basic rights and duties and regulate the division of advantages that arise from social cooperation over time (Rawls 2001, 9; see also 1999, 610; 2005, 11). Precisely what this emphasis on institutions implies, however, is somewhat contentious. A rst question to address is what is meant by the notion of institution, and which institutions are included as part of the basic structure. The second is to consider what it means that the basic structure is the primary subject of justice: does this imply that principles of justice only apply to institutions or is there room for them to apply elsewhere? What would `elsewhere' be in this case? Andrew Walton aims to describe what a property-owning democracy (POD), as a society characterized by Rawlsian justice, would look like, claiming particularly that it might require (1) a sense of fraternity and (2) certain forms of social interaction, such as high trade union membership and a public education system. I am broadly sympathetic to his attempt to characterize a Rawlsian society, and I also believe that Walton's analysis can help to provide substance to the notion

188 Carina Fourie of an egalitarian ethos. His argument, however, does not critically assess what is meant by `institution' in Rawls's theory, and is too quick in brushing over a signicant objectionthe basic structure objection. In order to be convincing, Walton cannot claim, as he does, that the basic structure objection does not apply to his argument, and he would need to provide better reason to demonstrate why the basic structure objection should not be heeded. Despite being critical, I hope that my analysis can be understood, ultimately, as a friendly recommendation on how the argument may need to be developed further. We can say that Walton is claiming, at least partially, that a POD requires a fraternal ethos, 1 making his argument at least somewhat similar to claims such as those made by G. A. Cohen, who argues that Rawlsian justice requires an egalitarian ethos (Cohen 2001, 11747). Walton concedes that his emphasis on a fraternal ethos could make his argument (at least seem to be) vulnerable to the basic structure objection. He phrases the objection as follows: ethoi are incompatible with Rawlsian justice because the latter is concerned with only the institutional structure of a society. (Walton, 179) I do not nd this an entirely convincing description of the basic structure objection. It is not the case that ethoi are necessarily incompatible with Rawlsian justice. After all, an ethos may emerge as a result of Rawlsian justice and I doubt Rawlsians would say in this case that the ethos is incompatible with Rawlsian justice. Rather, I would describe the objection as consisting of two parts, with potential implications for ethoi: (1) the positive claim that the principles of justice apply to the basic structure, and (2) the negative claim that the principles of justice do not apply outside of the basic structure, for example to norms, or personal choice (Rawls 1999, 47; Fourie 2007, 1870). 2 In relation to ethoi, one could say that according to the basic structure objection, the principles of justice do not apply to ethoi as they are not part of the basic structure. One can respond to the basic structure objection in various ways, including (i) by claiming it does not apply because, actually, one's argument complies with both the negative and the positive claims or (ii) by questioning the objection itself, for example, claiming that the denition of basic structure needs to be widened to include social norms and personal choice. 3 Walton appears to adopt both of these responses, however, as I will argue, I do not think option i. is open to him. Furthermore, he would need to provide a much more extensive argument for option ii. to be convincing. Firstly, Walton claims that the objection does not apply as his argument is also concerned with institutions (and thus the basic structure of society). Secondly, he claims that the basic structure objection is not itself entirely convincing. For example, if it is dened as applying only to the coercive framework of society it seems that it would not to be able to condemn sexist attitudes which should clearly, Walton claims, be the subject of justice. 1 An ethos can be described as a set of norms that determines (and is also inuenced by) pervasive patterns of attitudes, expectations and behaviour in a particular society or community. 2 For one of the most inuential descriptions and critiques of the basic structure objection, see also Cohen 2001, 12947. 3 Cohen 2001 opts for the latter.

Basic Structure Objection and Institutions of a POD 189 Let's consider more specically why he claims that the basic structure objection, even if we agree with it, does not pose a problem for his argument. He maintains that his argument is linked to considering what form of institutional framework should be deemed appropriate for realizing Rawlsian justice. In this respect, my arguments can be read as proposing a particular set of institutions in virtue of links to particular ethoi. (Walton, 179) There are two questions that this raises. The rst is: which institutions are being proposed? The second is: precisely what is the relationship between these institutions, ethoi and Rawlsian justice? I am going to assume that trade unions and a public education system are examples of (a commonsense understanding of) institutions in Walton's argument, although this claim is not made explicitly. Walton can only maintain that the basic structure objection does not apply to his claims, rstly, if what he means by institutions, as part of the basic structure, and what Rawls means are something similar. A problem is that it is not entirely clear what Rawls means by these conceptions either. While it is impossible to go into any detail in the scope of this comment, I claim that at least one feasible interpretation of Rawls is the following: The basic structure seems to consist of the institutions of political form, the economic system, the constitution, and legislation, where such legislation is specically concerned with assigning rights and distributing social goods. Other institutions, specic policies and laws, associations and behaviours, such as the family, rms and universities are only included in or aected by the basic structure in so much as the public rules applicable to them are determined and regulated by the application of the principles of justice to the institutions of the basic structure (Fourie 2007, 1870). 4 According to this interpretation, the most obvious institutions of a POD are the constitutional and legislative elements that determine that it is both property-owning in the requisite way, and that it is a democracy. In this case, however, a public education system and, to some extent, trade unions could also be includedthrough legislation. While we would not want trade unions themselves to be organs of the state, I am assuming that market and employment laws will make a dierence to the possibility for and the strength of trade unions. To try to make Walton's argument t into a Rawlsian framework more precisely we could say that in order to secure the basic rights and liberties of the rst Rawlsian principle, certain market and employment regulations, with inuence on, among other things, trade unions, as well as legislation to ensure a public education system, will be necessary. Perhaps this is justiable purely from the perspective of the rst principle but fair equality of opportunity could also be brought in. If it is correct that these forms of legislation are necessary and this alone were Walton's argument, it would indeed be doubtful that he would need to respond to the basic structure objection: I think the claim made here would be relatively uncontroversial and seems to violate neither the negative nor 4 While Rawls seems to include the family explicitly as part of the basic structure, this is actually misleading as he does not seem to believe that the principles of justice should apply directly to the family, as they should to the basic structure.

190 Carina Fourie positive claims of the objection. However, this is not how Walton's argument goes overall. The problem comes in with a sense of fraternity. Using empirical evidence, Walton claims that a sense of fraternity (operationalized as trust) is correlated with income equality, and thus what he takes to be a characteristic of Rawlsian justice (he claims that notwithstanding the prioritarianism of the dierence principle, there is a presumption of income equality expressed in the Rawlsian principles of justice). The forms of interaction among citizens that he believes would be valued in a Rawlsian POD are high trade union membership and a public education system, which have been correlated with a sense of fraternity. The claim seems to be that a sense of fraternity might be necessary to achieve Rawlsian justice, and that in turn, trade unions and a public education system are necessary to achieve a sense of fraternity. I am setting aside as an empirical question the causality implicit for the argument to work (to claim that a sense of fraternity is necessary for Rawlsian justice it would need to be the fraternity that is inuencing income equality, rather than the other way around). With this argument, Walton cannot side-step the basic structure objection by claiming that his argument applies to institutions. The `institutions' here, understood as the legislation behind trade unions and a public education system, are only instrumentally necessary to achieve a sense of fraternity. So it seems that Walton is using the principles of justice to justify why we need a fraternal ethos, and he is not applying these principles to institutions. It seems in this case, then, that the basic structure objection would indeed be relevant to his argument. Walton, as we have seen, however, has a further response to the objection, which is to question the objection itself. I believe in order for his argument to work, he must indeed question the basic structure objection (and should simply jettison his claim that the objection does not apply to his argument). However, I do not think that as it stands, his criticism of the basic structure objection is adequate. Relying on G. A. Cohen's criticism of the objection, Walton argues that sexist attitudes are clearly subject to justice, and if the basic structure cannot accommodate concern about the justice of sexist attitudes, then we should be skeptical of the basic structure objection. The discussion of sexist attitudes does not, however, make the problem with the basic structure objection clear. One can agree with the claim that sexist attitudes are clearly `subject to justice' and still defend the basic structure objection. It does not follow from the claim that sexist attitudes are subject to justice, that the Rawlsian principles of justice should apply outside of the basic structure (where basic structure is understood to exclude attitudes). We could be concerned that sexist attitudes are unjust but we still do not believe that we need to apply the principles of justice directly to attitudes. For example, rstly, perhaps we believe that sexist attitudes will be mitigated or decreased by the application of the principles of justice to the basic structure, and we do not need to (or should not) interfere with attitudes, even if they do seem unjust. The claim could be something like this: once formal, institutional justice has been achieved in a POD (through the application of the principles

Basic Structure Objection and Institutions of a POD 191 of justice to institutions such as the constitution and relevant legislation), sexist attitudes are likely to dissipate or no longer have much inuence. Alternatively, for example, we could argue that Rawls's principles of justice (explicitly designed for institutions) should only apply to the basic structure, and we require other principles to apply to personal choice and attitudes (see Fourie 2007). I do not aim here to defend the basic structure objection, nor even to defend the claims described here in these two examples. However, I am arguing that Walton's concerns about sexist attitudes do not adequately indicate why the basic structure objection should be ignoredat the least, more work would need to be done to indicate this. Walton also claims that his argument is not vulnerable to Andrew Williams' formulation of the basic structure objection. Williams claims that justice should regulate only the `public system of rules' and these rules need to be subject to the publicity condition meaning that `individuals are able to attain common knowledge of the rules' (i) general applicability, (ii) their particular requirements, and (iii) the extent to which individuals conform with those requirements' (Williams; cf. Walton, 179). Walton claims that his notion of a fraternal ethos, operationalized as social trust, is quantiably measurable and thus, he claims that it seems to be compatible with the criteria of the publicity condition. However, the fact that we can measure social trust is beside the point. The question is whether what Walton refers to as institutions can conceivably be referred to as institutions which specify public rules in the requisite sense. As discussed, it seems fairly uncontroversial to claim that Rawlsian justice may require certain market and employment regulations, and the legislation to ensure a public education system. In relation to Williams' claims, these seem to t the notion of a public system of rulesthus the basic structure objection, where basic structure is dened according to a public system of ruleswould not apply to this part of Walton's argument. However, considering that his argument is ultimately that we need a fraternal ethos to achieve Rawlsian justice it seems he would have to show that this ethos can be described as a public system of rules, but this, however, he has not done. On the basis of this discussion, it is dicult to see why we should accept Walton's claims that the basic structure objection does not apply to his argument or that the objection is incorrect. I do not believe that the questions I have raised in this comment provide any kind of knock-down argument of Walton's view. I do want to highlight, however, that without further critically examining the notion of institution, and providing a more extensive and critical discussion of the basic structure objection, Walton's argument is incomplete. Bibliography Cohen, G. A. (2001), If You're an Egalitarian, How Come You're so Rich?, Cambridge/MA Fourie, C. (2007), Justice and the Duties of Social Equality, unpublished Diss., University College London

192 Carina Fourie Rawls, J. (1999), A Theory of Justice, revised edition, Oxford (2001), Justice as Fairness: A Restatement, Cambridge/MA (2005), Political Liberalism, New York Walton, A. (2013), Fraternal Society in Rawls' Property-Owning Democracy, in: Analyse & Kritik 35, 163186