Topic Page: Democracy

Similar documents
Democratic Theory 1 Trevor Latimer Office Hours: TBA Contact Info: Goals & Objectives. Office Hours. Midterm Course Evaluation

CHAPTER 2: MAJORITARIAN OR PLURALIST DEMOCRACY

Rawls versus the Anarchist: Justice and Legitimacy

Proceduralism and Epistemic Value of Democracy

Problems with the one-person-one-vote Principle

POL 190B: Democratic Theory Spring 2017 Room: Shiffman Humanities Ctr 125 W, 2:00 4:50 PM

Public Opinion and Democratic Theory

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at

Problems in Contemporary Democratic Theory

The Justification of Justice as Fairness: A Two Stage Process

Chantal Mouffe On the Political

CHANTAL MOUFFE GLOSSARY

William Riker s Liberalism Against Populism. CMSS seminar, Tuesday 15 October

Theorising the Democratic State. Elizabeth Frazer: Lecture 4. Who Rules? I

Department of Political Science Fall, Political Science 306 Contemporary Democratic Theory Peter Breiner

Last time we discussed a stylized version of the realist view of global society.

The Forgotten Principles of American Government by Daniel Bonevac

Introduction to Equality and Justice: The Demands of Equality, Peter Vallentyne, ed., Routledge, The Demands of Equality: An Introduction

Multiculturalism Sarah Song Encyclopedia of Political Theory, ed. Mark Bevir (Sage Publications, 2010)

Rawls, Islam, and political constructivism: Some questions for Tampio

CONCEPTUAL FOUNDATIONS OF INTERNATIONAL POLITICS QUESTION 4

Carleton University Winter 2014 Department of Political Science

Political Science 306 Contemporary Democratic Theory Peter Breiner

Democratic Theory. Wednesdays, 3:30-6:00pm Room: 1115 BSB

We the Stakeholders: The Power of Representation beyond Borders? Clara Brandi

Direct Democracy. A philosophical point of view. 11 April 2016

Definition: Institution public system of rules which defines offices and positions with their rights and duties, powers and immunities p.

Is the Ideal of a Deliberative Democracy Coherent?

A Critique on Schumpeter s Competitive Elitism: By Examining the Case of Chinese Politics

Political Science 423 DEMOCRATIC THEORY. Thursdays, 3:30 6:30 pm, Foster 305. Patchen Markell University of Chicago Spring 2000

GLOBAL DEMOCRACY THE PROBLEM OF A WRONG PERSPECTIVE

John Rawls. Cambridge University Press John Rawls: An Introduction Percy B. Lehning Frontmatter More information

Københavns Universitet. Legitimacy and Democracy Rostbøll, Christian F. Published in: Introduction to Political Sociology. Publication date: 2013

Direct Voting in Normative Democratic Theories

Philosophy 267 Fall, 2010 Professor Richard Arneson Introductory Handout revised 11/09 Texts: Course requirements: Week 1. September 28.

Republicanism: Midway to Achieve Global Justice?

Law and Philosophy (2015) 34: Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2015 DOI /s ARIE ROSEN BOOK REVIEW

Problems with Group Decision Making

Political Obligation 4

MEDICAL MARIJUANA ANALYZED USING PRINCIPLISM

B DEMOCRACY: A READER. Edited by Ricardo Blaug and John Schwarzmantel EDINBURGH UNIVERSITY PRESS

Politics between Philosophy and Democracy

Episteme: A Journal of Social Epistemology, Volume 5, Issue 1, 2008, pp. 1-4 (Article) DOI: /epi

Introduction 478 U.S. 186 (1986) U.S. 558 (2003). 3

Københavns Universitet. Democracy as good in itself Rostbøll, Christian F. Publication date: Document Version Other version

Justice As Fairness: Political, Not Metaphysical (Excerpts)

Introduction. Bernard Manin, Adam Przeworski, and Susan C. Stokes

The Epistemic Conception of Deliberative Democracy Defended Reasons, Rightness and Equal Political Autonomy

[UPDATED DECEMBER 2015] University of Sydney, Sydney, Australia Sesquicentenary Fellow in Government and International Relations,

THE AGONISTIC CONSOCIATION. Mohammed Ben Jelloun. (EHESS, Paris)

DELIBERATIVE DEMOCRACY AND CITIZENSHIP. by Dorota Pietrzyk-Reeves

SAMPLE CHAPTERS UNESCO EOLSS POWER AND THE STATE. John Scott Department of Sociology, University of Plymouth, UK

Topics in Political Thought I: Democratic Theory POL 484H (F) Fall 2006, University of Toronto

Rousseau s general will, civil rights, and property

[UPDATED JULY 2017] University of Sydney, Sydney, Australia Sesquicentenary Fellow in Government and International Relations,

In Nations and Nationalism, Ernest Gellner says that nationalism is a theory of

The State of Democratic Theory: A Reply to James Fishkin

Rousseau, On the Social Contract

POL 10a: Introduction to Political Theory Spring 2017 Room: Golding 101 T, Th 2:00 3:20 PM

Deliberative Democracy and the Deliberative Poll on the Euro

Democracy and American Politics. The best argument against democracy is a fiveminute conversation with the average voter.

The Metamorphosis of Governance in the Era of Globalization

The Arrow Impossibility Theorem: Where Do We Go From Here?

ALEXIS DE TOCQUEVILLE

73 The Idea of Freedom in Radical and Deliberative Models of Democracy

Hannah Arendt ( )

1 L. Pratchett, «Local Autonomy, Local Democracy and the «New Localism», Political. Studies, Vol. 52, 2004, p. 361.

Global Justice. Course Overview

Problems with Group Decision Making

Plural Voting and J. S. Mill s Account of Democratic Legitimacy

A Liberal Defence of Compulsory Voting : Some Reasons for Scepticism.

Jus in Bello through the Lens of Individual Moral Responsibility: McMahan on Killing in War

Vol. 7, no. 2 (2012) Category: Conference paper Written by Sari Roman-Lagerspetz

POLI 111: INTRODUCTION TO THE STUDY OF POLITICAL SCIENCE

Chapter One: The Democratic Republic

Strengthening the Foundation for World Peace - A Case for Democratizing the United Nations

Power: A Radical View by Steven Lukes

A Rawlsian Idea of Deliberative Democracy

Ideas for an intelligent and progressive integration discourse

Ph.D. Politics, September 2005 Princeton University Fields: Political Theory, Public Law, Comparative Politics

Towards a Global Civil Society. Daniel Little University of Michigan-Dearborn

1 Introduction. Laura Werup Final Exam Fall 2013 IBP Pol. Sci.

CHAPTER 9 Conclusions: Political Equality and the Beauty of Cycling

POL 343 Democratic Theory and Globalization February 11, "The history of democratic theory II" Introduction

Penalizing Public Disobedience*

Enlightenment of Hayek s Institutional Change Idea on Institutional Innovation

DEMOCRACY AND POLITICAL KNOWLEDGE IN ANCIENT ATHENS

DEMOCRACY AND EQUALITY

Political Science The Political Theory of Capitalism Fall 2015

The character of public reason in Rawls s theory of justice

Political Norms and Moral Values

DEMOCRACY. Takamaro Hanzawa Tokyo Metropolitan University, Japan

Why Majority Rule Cannot Be Based only on Procedural Equality*raju_

4 INTRODUCTION Argentina, for example, democratization was connected to the growth of a human rights movement that insisted on democratic politics and

Comments on Schnapper and Banting & Kymlicka

Review of Michael E. Bratman s Shared Agency: A Planning Theory of Acting Together (Oxford University Press 2014) 1

Deliberation and Democratic Legitimacy I

Natural Law and Spontaneous Order in the Work of Gary Chartier

The Politics of Emotional Confrontation in New Democracies: The Impact of Economic

Chapter 1 The Study of American Government

Transcription:

Topic Page: Democracy Definition: democracy from Collins English Dictionary n pl -cies 1 government by the people or their elected representatives 2 a political or social unit governed ultimately by all its members 3 the practice or spirit of social equality 4 a social condition of classlessness and equality 5 the common people, esp as a political force [C16: from French démocratie, from Late Latin dēmocratia, from Greek dēmokratia government by the people; see demo-, -cracy] Summary Article: Democracy from Encyclopedia of Political Theory Democracy is a form of collective decision making that presupposes some form of equality among the participants. The term is used Image from: The Athenian empirically and normatively, often simultaneously. It is often used to acropolis, from a describe or distinguish one kind of political regime from another. A nineteenth-century... in democratic system, for example, is one in which there are Science in the Ancient World: procedures and institutions for capturing the views of citizens and An Encyclopedia translating them into binding decisions. At the same time, however, these empirical descriptions often contain within them normative claims about the way institutions ought to be structured or behave. Thus, it can be said that one society (whether now or in the past) is more (or less) democratic than another. The ideal of equality is particularly important to the normative evaluation of democracy. A democratic political system, on this view, is one that manifests in its institutions and procedures a conception of its members as free and equal and thus owed equal respect. If we look to the Greek roots of democracy (demokratia), demos refers to the people and kratos to power, capacity, or rule. Democracy, therefore, refers to the power or the capacity of the people to do certain things in the public realm. These simple definitions, however, betray deep complexities. Who are the people? What kind of power do they exercise, and what is it, exactly, that they are supposed to do? It is particularly difficult to establish just who the people ought to be. Are they simply the mass of the adult population sharing the territory in question? Or should we define them as all those whose most important interests are affected by the law or policy under consideration? How and where do we draw the distinction between who is in and who is out? Even if the people can be so identified, what is it that they do when they exercise their power? In

general, we can distinguish between direct and indirect forms of democratic rule. Direct democracy implies that the people exercise some kind of direct control, or authority, over their society. Indirect democracy, on the other hand, implies that the people are represented by others who make decisions on their behalf (but who remain accountable to them in various ways). According to the former, exercising authority or control might entail not only participating in deliberations about the best course of action but having control over and responsibility for implementation. According to the latter, being able to validate the decision-making processes of others without necessarily having participated in the deliberations themselves is enough. Winston Churchill once quipped that democracy is the worst form of government, except for all the other forms that had been tried. Recent work in political science has investigated the conditions in which democratic government can emerge, produce coherent outcomes, and remain stable over time. The results of this research often seem to confirm Churchill's suspicion; democracy is the least bad of a range of possible systems, but it remains deeply imperfect. Political theorists, on the other hand, have generally focused on the normative evaluation of democracy. How can democracy be justified? Which kinds of democracy are morally desirable and why? What is the relation between democracy and other important values, such as liberty, equality, and social justice? What is the scope of democracy? Just if ying Democracy Democracy can be justified in two general ways. First, we might consider democracy valuable in terms of the outcomes it tends to produce and thus offer instrumental arguments for its value. Second, we might think of democracy as intrinsically valuable. Political theorists almost always believe that political institutions have to be evaluated in some way in relation to the outcomes they produce. However, as we'll see, some think democracy needs to be defended in terms independent of the evaluation of its consequences. Ins tr umental Ar guments John Stuart Mill (1806-1873) and John Dewey (1859-1952) thought that democratic decision making was valuable (in part) because it forced decision makers to take into account the interests of the many as opposed to the few. This meant that the interests of the many were better protected against the biases and indulgences of a self-serving elite. Widespread suffrage, open elections, and a free press forced elites and politicians to pay attention to more than simply narrow sectional interests. Both Mill and Dewey also thought that democratic decision-making had positive epistemic benefits for society as a whole. Mill, for example, thought that the greater the variety of opinions canvassed and expressed, the more robust and meaningful the values of a liberal society would become for its members. He also thought people would become more tolerant and accommodating the greater the range of views they encountered. Dewey thought that given the nature of social and political problems, the greater the range and diversity of input into decision-making processes, the more likely decision makers would be able to arrive at the right answer. Dewey had a particularly rich conception of this aspect of democracy, which he sometimes referred to as a form of organized intelligence. For him, democracy was as much a mode of inquiry or activity as it was a mode of decision making. Democracy not only channels the diverse interests of the people but also helps them discover what their real (public) interests are. Contemporary political theorists, drawing on formal political science and theories of institutional design, have argued in a similar vein. This research has attempted to show that democracies are

best at organizing and mobilizing the dispersed knowledge of their societies in such a way that it enables them to remain dynamic, innovative, and self-correcting. Democracies, therefore, have a distinct advantage over authoritarian political systems: According to these arguments, they tend to be more stable and prosperous over the long term. Another influential instrumental argument in favor of democracy is that it has positive benefits on the character of individuals. The opportunities a democratic system opens up for political participation call for and at the same time help to cultivate valuable capacities and skills. The cultivation of these virtues, in turn, ensures that the interests of the participants are protected in the course of democratic deliberation and decision making. One problem with a purely instrumental approach to democracy, however, is that it might turn out that other (less democratic) political arrangements are much better at producing the outcomes we value. If what matters, for example, is the quality of decision making, then it might be that sealing off that discussion from nonexperts promotes better deliberation overall. Indeed, critics of democratic rule from Plato onward have exploited this line of argument. This has led some political theorists to think there is more to the value of democracy than the outcomes it tends to produce. Intrinsic Arguments Democracy can be defended on intrinsic grounds. Recall the overlap between empirical and normative accounts of democracy. Democratic political arrangements are those that manifest, in their institutions and processes, a conception of the members as equals owed equal respect. The claim here is that only democratic political arrangements can deliver equal respect, and thus nondemocratic systems hierarchical or authoritarian regimes, even if relatively benign are inherently unjust. The connection between democracy and equality was strongly emphasized by Jean-Jacques Rousseau (1712-1778). For Rousseau, when the people assemble as a sovereign body, they do so as equals. If each of us is fundamentally free and equal, then any political association in which one is subject to authority must be consistent with these premises. The only form of political association that meets this standard, thinks Rousseau, is one in which each individual remains self-governing and is subject only to those laws of which he or she is the author. Interestingly, Rousseau was doubtful the conditions for genuine self-government could ever be met in the modern world, but his normative ideal has remained influential ever since (as well as a target for extensive criticism). Robert Dahl referred to the relationship between a society of equals and democratic political arrangements as the logic of equality. A similar argument is made in relation to the ideal of public justification. If the laws and policies of a political community are legitimate only if they can be justified to each and every citizen, assuming a plurality of worldviews, then this too entails a commitment to democratic political arrangements. Democracy is valuable according to these arguments, not because of the outcomes it produces, but because of the way it manifests a commitment to the basic freedom and equality of each citizen. There are, however, a number of challenges to this line of argument. First, there is the issue of interpreting and specifying the relevant ideals of freedom and equality. What kind of equality are we talking about when we say that democracy advances or protects the interests of all equally? Another related problem is the persistence of disagreement. If we interpret the Rousseauian standard strictly, it is hard to imagine how anything other than consensus or unanimity could count

as the appropriate standard for legitimacy because otherwise some people are being coerced against their will. However, disagreement is a permanent feature of politics. We need political decision-making procedures precisely because disagreement is so prevalent. One solution is to weaken the requirement for consensus and aim for only reasonable consensus or minimal consensus. The challenge then, however, is to distinguish between the reasonable and unreasonable and to show that even minimal consensus is possible against a background of deep disagreement. Majority rule, for example, might be one way to proceed in the face of disagreement because it holds out the promise of being part of a future majority if on the losing side today. However, we then face the problem of persistent minorities (the same group losing every time) and the tyranny of the majority, problems that cut against the logic of equality at the heart of this conception of democracy. Minimalist Democracy Given the difficulty of identifying what exactly the general will of the people might be, and given the nature of large-scale, complex, and deeply diverse modern political societies, many theorists have suggested abandoning Rousseau's ideal. Joseph Schumpeter (1883-1950) provided a robust defense of a more minimalist or elite democracy. In Capitalism, Socialism, and Democracy, Schumpeter defined the democratic method as that institutional arrangement for arriving at political decisions in which individuals acquire the power to decide by means of a competitive struggle for the people's vote (p. 269). Applying a mode of analysis borrowed from neo-classical economics, Schumpeter denied there was any coherent general will to be discovered in the first place, and thus the idea that a society could be self-governing in Rousseau's sense was literally nonsense. Because individuals were driven by a jumble of ever-changing preferences and desires easily manipulated by elites and demagogues, what was required was responsible political leadership. Citizens still had an important role to play in electing and holding political leaders to account. But the development of policy was to be driven by elites, not citizens. Electoral competition between political parties, not participation by individuals, was the mechanism for ensuring that proper decision making occurred. For Schumpeter then, the value of democracy lay in the institutionalization of the competition for power. When working properly, democratic competition converts stones into paper ballots and ensures a peaceful transition of power between different groups. To ask for anything more of democracy is to ask for trouble. Subsequent work in political science and social choice theory seemed to confirm many of Schumpeter's suspicions. Kenneth Arrow's famous impossibility theorem seemed to show that there was no universally workable way of aggregating individual preferences and values into coherent and stable collective decisions. Others questioned the rationality of voting, let alone greater participation, given the likelihood of your vote having any substantial impact on the actual outcome of an election. In short, democracy was chaotic, irrational, and strictly speaking, impossible. Deliberat ive Democracy Despite these challenges, and partly inspired by them, there has been a remarkable resurgence in the idea of deliberative democracy in recent years. Deliberative democrats accept that in large, complex societies, democracy will have to be organized in some way as a system of competitive representation. But they reject that this is all we can expect of democracy. For deliberative democrats, democracy provides the best means through which laws and policies can be justified to

citizens considered as free and equal. Deliberative democracy represents an idea of political association in which the legitimacy of its terms and conditions proceed through public argument and reasoning among equal citizens. The ideal is a demanding one. Deliberative democrats presuppose that members of such an association recognize each other as possessing the appropriate deliberative capacities and as capable of participating in the exchange of public reasoning and acting on the basis of that reasoning. They assume that there is a plurality of interests and preferences accepting the challenge to Rousseau by minimalist conceptions of democracy but suggest that deliberative institutions can be designed in such a way that preferences can be shaped and transformed through deliberative processes prior to voting. And they insist that deliberation can be genuinely free only when the parties are formally and substantially equal. Citizens seek to advance their own interests and also to discover reasons that others can share when justifying the exercise of public political power. Thus, legitimacy is a product of common deliberation. But note that this does not necessarily mean direct participation. Indirect or mediated deliberation in the wider public sphere can be linked to the competitive process (exactly how is an important question). One major objection to deliberative democracy, however, is that it is simply unrealizable in modern conditions and repeats the delusional vision of Rousseau. In response, there have been interesting attempts at designing real-world applications of deliberative principles, often with striking results. Nevertheless, it's not clear that these highly controlled experiments such as citizens' juries, or deliberation days really vindicate the applicability of the ideal to large-scale political processes. The relationship between these small-scale exercises in deliberation and the larger, competitive representation system (assuming it can't be abandoned entirely) remains unclear. Agonist ic Democracy Another major concern is that deliberative democracy isn't democratic enough. First, because if citizens are expected to be reasonable in order to participate in common deliberation, then who decides what is reasonable? There is a tension between rule by deliberative reasons and rule by democratic deliberative reasons. For more radical critics of deliberative democracy, the demand for consensus lying behind the deliberative ideal no matter how thin or indirect is not only unrealistic but misconstrues a fundamental paradox at the heart of democracy: namely, the clash between freedom and equality. For these critics, we need to relinquish the ideal of consensus and embrace a more agonistic approach. According to this account, dissensus is a constitutive feature of democratic politics that can never be overcome. Persistent disagreement and contestation should, instead, be seen as markers of democratization itself and harnessed in such a way that antagonism is converted into agonistic respect for pluralism. Democracy is uncertain and contingent, given the inherent tensions between freedom and equality, self-government and the rule of law, human rights and popular sovereignty. However, unlike the minimalists, pluralist and agonistic democrats take the unavoidability of these tensions not as a reason to downplay the promise of democracy, but as a constant invitation to renew its possibility. See also Cosmopolitan Democracy, Dewey, John, Mill, John Stuart, Participatory Democracy, Rawls, John, Representation, Rousseau, Jean-Jacques Further Readings

Ackerman, B., & Fishkin, J. (2004). Deliberation day. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. Cohen, J. (2002). Procedure and substance in deliberative democracy. In T. Christiano (Ed.), Philosophy and democracy. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. Connolly, W. (2005). Pluralism. Durham, NC: Duke University Press. Dahl, R. (1998). On democracy. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. Mackie, G. (2004). Democracy defended. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Mill, J. S. (1862). Considerations on representative government. New York: Harper. Mouffe, C. (2000). The democratic paradox. London: Verso. Ober, J. (2008). Democracy and knowledge. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Rawls, J. (1996). Political liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press. Rousseau, J. (1968). The social contract (M. Cranston, Ed.). Harmondsworth, UK: Penguin. (Original work published 1762). Schumpeter, J. (1956). Capitalism, socialism, and democracy. New York: Harper & Row. Ivison, Duncan APA Chicago Harvard MLA Ivison, D., & Ivison. (2010). Democracy. In M. Bevir (Ed.), Encyclopedia of political theory. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage Publications. Retrieved from Copyright 2010 by SAGE Publications, Inc. Copyright 2010 by SAGE Publications, Inc.

APA Ivison, D., & Ivison. (2010). Democracy. In M. Bevir (Ed.), Encyclopedia of political theory. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage Publications. Retrieved from Chicago Ivison, Duncan, and Ivison. "Democracy." In Encyclopedia of Political Theory, edited by Mark Bevir. Sage Publications, 2010. Harvard Ivison, D. and Ivison. (2010). Democracy. In M. Bevir (Ed.), Encyclopedia of political theory. [Online]. Thousand Oaks: Sage Publications. Available from: [Accessed 3 October 2018]. MLA Ivison, Duncan, and Ivison. "Democracy." Encyclopedia of Political Theory, edited by Mark Bevir, Sage Publications, 1st edition, 2010. Credo Reference,. Accessed 03 Oct. 2018.