Against Positive Rights Feature

Similar documents
Changing Constitutional Powers of the American President Feature: Forum: The Evolving Presidency in Eastern Europe

Management prerogatives, plant closings, and the NLRA: A response

TUSHNET-----Introduction THE IDEA OF A CONSTITUTIONAL ORDER

Compassion and Compulsion

Market, State, and Community

What Should We Know About American Government?

Ehrenzweig on the Law of Conflict of Laws

Women s Role in Developing Economies: Case of Georgia

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Follow this and additional works at: Part of the Law Commons

The Iraqi Constitution from an Economic Perspective. Interview with Noah Feldman New York University School of Law

EUROBAROMETER 71 PUBLIC OPINION IN THE EUROPEAN UNION SPRING

Democracy, and the Evolution of International. to Eyal Benvenisti and George Downs. Tom Ginsburg* ... National Courts, Domestic

CHAPTER 19 MARKET SYSTEMS AND NORMATIVE CLAIMS Microeconomics in Context (Goodwin, et al.), 2 nd Edition

UNITED STATES INSTITUTE OF PEACE...

ATTACKS ON JUSTICE CZECH REPUBLIC

WHY NOT BASE FREE SPEECH ON AUTONOMY OR DEMOCRACY?

KYRGYZSTAN PARLIAMENTARY STRENGTHENING PROGRAM (KPSP)

Economic Assistance to Russia: Ineffectual, Politicized, and Corrupt?

Portfolio Committee on Women, Children and People with Disabilities Parliament of the Republic of South Africa CAPE TOWN.

Voters Interests in Campaign Finance Regulation: Formal Models

Survey of US Voters Issues and Attitudes June 2014

LAWS1205 Australian Public Law 1 st Semester 2011

The realities of daily life during the 1970 s

South Carolina s Exposition Against the Tariff of 1828 By John C. Calhoun (Anonymously)

Are Second-Best Tariffs Good Enough?

Pleading Guilty in Lower Courts

On the Expressive Function of Law Special Reports

Written evidence submitted by Hans Peter Ulrich, Civio Public Policy Consulting and Publisher of website

A Comparative Study of the Competency and Authorities of Legislatures in Iran, France and America

Volume 60, Issue 1 Page 241. Stanford. Cass R. Sunstein

Proceduralism and Epistemic Value of Democracy

Civics Lesson Objectives

Ethics Handout 18 Rawls, Classical Utilitarianism and Nagel, Equality

Session 4 - The law and the individual Key-note speech by Mr Christoph Grabenwarter, Judge, Constitutional Court, Austria

The Free State Foundation's TENTH ANNUAL TELECOM POLICY CONFERENCE

Prentice Hall: Magruder s American Government 2002 Correlated to: Arizona Standards for Social Studies, History (Grades 9-12)

The 2014 elections to the European Parliament: towards truly European elections?

1100 Ethics July 2016

Phil 116, April 5, 7, and 9 Nozick, Anarchy, State, and Utopia

First Amendment Entitlements and Government Motives: A Reply to Professor Merrill

President Jacob Zuma: Broad-Based Black Economic Empowerment Summit

IN DEFENSE OF THE MARKETPLACE OF IDEAS / SEARCH FOR TRUTH AS A THEORY OF FREE SPEECH PROTECTION

The Two Faces of Federalism

Can human rights make aids agencies more accountable?

At a time when political philosophy seemed nearly stagnant, John Rawls

The Evolution of the Constitutional System in Albania

EU (Withdrawal) Bill- Committee stage

Critical Assessment of the Implementation of Anti Trafficking Policy in Bolivia, Colombia and Guatemala Executive Summary

Foreign policy is the sum total of the processes and actions that regulate the relations between a given state and its international environment.

Definition: Institution public system of rules which defines offices and positions with their rights and duties, powers and immunities p.

Measuring Presidential Power in Post-Communist Countries: Rectification of Mistakes 1

Improving democracy in spite of political rhetoric

PRE-CONFERENCE MEETING Women in Local Authorities Leadership Positions: Approaches to Democracy, Participation, Local Development and Peace

Factsheet on the judiciary in the Netherlands

STATE OF WISCONSIN CIRCUIT COURT MILWAUKEE COUNTY

N o t e. The Treaty of Lisbon: Ratification requirements and present situation in the Member States

2010 Proposed Constitutional Amendments to the 1982 Constitution of Turkey. PhD. Levent Gönenç

Resistance to Women s Political Leadership: Problems and Advocated Solutions

Civil Society Organizations in Montenegro

Common ground in European Dismissal Law

Lecture Notes Atkins v. Virginia, 536 U.S (2002) Keith Burgess-Jackson 29 April 2016

A Conversation with a Communist Economic Reformer

Public policy Analysis. Prof S.M Omodia and Mr Ozekhome Igechi LECTURE 1. Objectives

Annex 3 NIS Indicators and Foundations. 1. Legislature

The Appellate Courts Role in the Federal Judicial System 1

We the People: The Role of the Citizen in the United States

The Rt. Hon. Sir Ninian Stephen on Why Judicial Independence?

of strengthening democracy through market-oriented reform Article at a glance

POLI 359 Public Policy Making

Reconciling Educational Adequacy and Equity Arguments Through a Rawlsian Lens

QUESTIONS CONCERNING INDEPENDENCE OF CONSTITUTIONAL COURT AS BODY OF STATE AUTHORITY. 1. Concerning execution of Constitutional Court decisions

Section-by-Section Analysis S. 584 The Small Business Regulatory Flexibility Improvement Act of 2017

A MEMORANDUM ON THE RULE OF LAW AND CRIMINAL VIOLENCE IN LATIN AMERICA. Hugo Frühling

Introduction to Comparative Constitutionalism

THE KARIBA DRAFT CONSTITUTION

Youth, Democracy, and Politics: Poland

JUDICIAL APPOINTMENTS. Revised discussion paper prepared by the Secretariat for the meeting of the Sub-commission on the Judiciary.

THE INDEPENDENCE OF THE COURTS AND JUDICIAL INDEPENDENCE FROM THE EUROPEAN UNION LAW PERSPECTIVE *1

Constitutional Declaration 8 July 2013 [unofficial translation] Table of contents

PERSONNEL PROBLEMS IN THE ADMINISTRATION OF JUSTICE IN NIGERIA

Why Does Inequality Matter? T. M. Scanlon. Chapter 8: Unequal Outcomes. It is well known that there has been an enormous increase in inequality in the

Introduction. Australian Constitution. Federalism. Separation of Powers

California Judges Association OPINION NO. 43. (Originally issued: February 5, 1994) (Revised: August 1996)

Magruder's American Government 2008 Correlated to: Washington EALRs for High School Civics (Grade 12)

Notes from discussion in Erik Olin Wright Lecture #2: Diagnosis & Critique Middle East Technical University Tuesday, November 13, 2007

In my brief presentation I would like to touch upon some basic liberal principles and link

EUROBAROMETER 72 PUBLIC OPINION IN THE EUROPEAN UNION

Problems with Group Decision Making

Study Questions for George Reisman's Capitalism: A Treatise on Economics

REMEDIES IN CONSTITUTIONAL LITIGATION UNDER THE KENYAN CONSTITUTION OF 2010

Gender quotas in Slovenia: A short analysis of failures and hopes

We Need to Reclaim the Second Bill of Rights

REPORT FROM THE COMMISSION TO THE EUROPEAN PARLIAMENT AND THE COUNCIL

Public Interest in the Case Law of the Constitutional Court of the Czech Republic

Last time we discussed a stylized version of the realist view of global society.

Postscript: Subjective Utilitarianism

9770 COMPARATIVE GOVERNMENT AND POLITICS

Advocacy Cycle Stage 4

CIVICS Participating in Government. Chapter Outlines CHAPTER 1

Transcription:

University of Chicago Law School Chicago Unbound Journal Articles Faculty Scholarship 1993 Against Positive Rights Feature Cass R. Sunstein Follow this and additional works at: http://chicagounbound.uchicago.edu/journal_articles Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation Cass R. Sunstein, "Against Positive Rights Feature," 2 East European Constitutional Review 35 (1993). This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Faculty Scholarship at Chicago Unbound. It has been accepted for inclusion in Journal Articles by an authorized administrator of Chicago Unbound. For more information, please contact unbound@law.uchicago.edu.

WiNrm 1993 lature in times of emergency and when the Parliament is incapable of forming a cabinet. Some provisions indicate that dissolution is considered a solution of last resort to conflicts between the executive and legislative branches, one which is to be avoided by all means. In fact, the detailed preconditions in the Hungarian and Slovak constitutions seem to make dissolution almost impossible. In Hungary, Parliament must vote no confidence at least four times during a twelve-month period, and in Slovakia the cabinet policy statement must be rejected at least three times in six months for the Assembly to be dissolved. These prerequisites coexist with other limitations. The Romanian and Yugoslav constitutions prohibit dissolution in the last months of the terms of President and the parliament. The Hungarian President can dissolve the Assembly only twice during his term, while Romanian President can use it only once a year. Almost all the constitutions of the emerging democracies stipulate that the President must consult with other high officials and politicians before opting for dissolution. While the typical procedure is to consult the Speaker of the House, in Hungary the President must confer with the Prime Minister, the Speaker and the leaders of all the parliamentary factions. Some of the constitutions prohibit dissolution in time of presidential succession. Even if all the necessary preconditions are satisfied, an interim President does not possess this power. The 1992 Interim Constitution in Poland, among other novelties, contains a provision of crucial importance-the President is under obligation to dissolve the Parliament if the Legislature fails to adopt a budget bill in the three months following its introduction. Due to lack of space, this brief survey of the features of rationalized parliamentarism is by no means exhaustive. Two conclusions, however, seem clear. First, rationalized parliamentarism requires great political skill of the principals in the difficult process of transition from totalitarianism to democracy. Second, the new parliamentarism strengthens cabinets and prevents easy no-confidence motions that can threaten political stability and when used improperly might even invite government paralysis, if unpopular officials use these techniques to prevent the necessary changes that are underway. Evgeni Tanchev is a visiting scholar at the University of Virginia Law School Why social and economic rights don't belong in the new constitutions of post-communist Europe. AGAINST POSITIVE RIGHTS By Cass Sunstein If we look at the actual and proposed constitutions for Eastern Europe, we will find a truly dazzling array of social and economic rights. The Hungarian constitution, for example, protects not merely the right to equal pay for equal work, but also the right to an income conforming with the quantity and quality of work performed. The Slovak constitution guarantees the right to a "favorable living environment." Almost all of the actual and proposed drafts include the rights to recreation, to paid holidays, to food and shelter, to a minimum wage, and to much more. A chaotic catalogue of abstractions from the social welfare state coexists with the traditional rights to religious liberty, free speech, and so on. (For details, see my "Something Old, Something New," EECR, Spring 1992, page 18.) I think that this is a large mistake, possibly a disaster. It seems clear that Eastern European countries should use their constitutions to produce two things: (a) firm liberal rights-free speech, voting rights, protection against abuse of the criminaljustice system, religious liberty, barriers to invidious discrimination, property and contract rights; and (b) the preconditions for some kind of market HeinOnline -- 2 E. Eur. Const. Rev. 35 1993

EAST EUROPEAN CONsTrruTIoNAL REVIEW economy. The endless catalogue of what I will be calling "positive rights," many of them absurd, threatens to undermine both of these important tasks. Three qualifications are necessary at the outset. First, the argument against these rights applies with distinctive force to countries in the unique position of transition.from Communism to a market economy. Other countries, especially in the West, are in a much different situation, and here it is by no means clear that social and economic rights would be harmful. We may draw an important and general conclusion from this suggestion. It is often said that constitutions, as a form of higher law, must be compatible with the culture and mores of those whom they regulate. But in one sense, the opposite is true. Constitutions can be understood as precommitment strategies, in which nations use a founding document to protect against the most common problems in their usual political processes. Constitutions should therefore work against a nation's most threatening tendencies. If this is so, there may be a good case for subsistence rights in (say) the United States, but not in Poland or Russia. On this view, it is irrelevant, even if true, that many international human rights documents contain positive rights. While it is unclear whether these rights have done much good, it is also hard to argue that they have produced any real harm; but they may do exactly this for countries making the transition from Communist rule. Constitutions as legal documents Second, there is a big difference between what a decent society should provide and what a good constitution should guarantee. A decent society ensures that its citizens have food and shelter; it tries to guarantee medical care; it is concerned to offer good education, good jobs, and a clean environment. It undoubtedly makes sense for nations in Eastern Europe to experiment with diverse kinds of market arrangements and with various strategies for redistribution (see John Roemer and Jon Elster's article on page 38). But a constitution is in large part a legal document, with concrete tasks. If the Constitution tries to specify everything to which a decent society commits itself, it threatens to become a mere piece of paper, worth nothing in the real world. (Hence I think that Herman Schwartz is incorrect to suggest that the opposition to positive rights in the constitution actually amounts to opposition to programs creating such rights; see "In Defense of Aiming High," EECR, Fall 1992, page 25.) Opposition to social and economic rights in the Constitution does not entail a belief that nations in Eastern Europe should eliminate social and economic programs that provide crucial protection against the vicissitudes of the free market. Third, not all positive rights are the same. The right to education, for example, is more readily subject tojudicial enforcement than the right to a clean environment. Some of the relevant rights pose especially severe risks; others are relatively harmless. But I believe that few of them belong in Eastern European constitutions. Here's why: Governments should not be compelled to interfere with free markets. Some positive rights establish government interference with free markets as a constitutional obligation. For countries that are trying to create market economies, this is perverse. A constitution that prevents the operation of free labor markets may defeat current aspirations in Eastern Europe. Recall that the Hungarian Constitution protects not merely the right to equal pay for equal work, but also the right to an income conforming with the quantity and quality of work performed. This provision will have one of two consequences. (a) If the provision is to mean something, courts will have to oversee labor markets very closely, to make sure that every bargain produces the right wage. We know enough to know that government is ill-equipped to undertake this task. Courts are in an even worse position to do so. If courts are going to oversee the labor market, it will be impossible to have a labor market. (b) The relevant provisions will be ignored-treated as goals or aspirations not subject to legal enforcement. This is a better outcome than (a), and courts in Eastern Europe should be encouraged to reach this conclusion. But it is far from ideal to have a system in which many constitutional rights are ignored. The Hungarian provision is an extreme example, but similar problems are raised by provisions calling for specified maximum hours, for paid parental leave, for paid holidays, and much else. Many of these provisions may make sense if they are placed in ordinary legislation. But this is where they belong-not in the constitution. The constitution should not undertake close control of the private sphere, of civil society and economic markets. In the West, the constitution generally does not apply to the private sphere at all; it only regulates government. (The HeinOnline -- 2 E. Eur. Const. Rev. 36 1993

WiNTRr 1993 emphasis on positive rights in the Eastern European documents suggests the remarkable and quite general absence of any distinction between the private and public spheres.) Perhaps some small companies in the East should be allowed to get ahead by paying their workers a great deal in return for long hours, or for less in the way of leave; perhaps not. Perhaps medical care should not be freeespecially for people who have the money to pay for it. These issues should be subject to democratic debate, not constitutional foreclosure. Many positive rights are unenforceable by courts. Courts lack the tools of a bureaucracy. They cannot create government programs. They do not have a systematic overview of government policy. In these circumstances, it is unrealistic to expect courts to enforce many positive rights. Consider, for example, another provision in the Hungarian Constitution: "People living within the territory of the Republic of Hungary have the right to the highest possible level of physical health." How could courts enforce this right? The same problem appears for many (not all) of the positive rights, including the right to work, the right to a clean environment, and the right to training for the disabled. To be sure, constitutions are not only legal documents, as Schwartz points out. In the United States, the identification of the Constitution with the decisions of courts has been damaging to democratic deliberation. Constitutions can be a catalyst for public discussion. But in Eastern Europe, it is crucial to establish very soon that whatever else they are, constitutions are indeed legal documents-in the sense that an individual citizen may count on the constitution to protect rights, whatever a police officer, a legislature, or even a prime minister or President may say. One of the enduring legacies of Communism is a large degree of cynicism about constitutions-a belief that constitutions may be pretty, but that they do not have meaning in the real world. If the right to "the highest possible level of physical health" is not subject to judicial enforcement, perhaps the same will become true of the right to free speech and to due process of law. Undoing the culture of dependency The inclusion of many positive rights could work against general current effort to diminish sense of entitlement to state protection and to encourage individual initiative. I have said that a decent society provides its citizens with food, shelter, and much more. But if positive dispensations from the state are seen as a matter of individual entitlement, there can be corrosive effects on individual enterprise and initiative. This effect can be seen in both the West and the East. The risk of corrosion is no reason to eliminate programs that provide for subsistence. But in today's Eastern Europe, it is important to undertake a cultural shift through which people will look less to the state for their support, and more to their own efforts and enterprise. One way to help do this is to provide social welfare guarantees through ordinary legislation, and to reserve the constitution for other matters. In this cultural shift, it will be understood that the state furnishes, among other things, a safety net for those who are unable to make provision for themselves. A constitution that indiscriminately merges guarantees of "just pay" and "recreation" with traditional liberal rights is likely to sendjust the wrong signals. Many positive rights would do no afirmative good, and this is a serious problemfor incipient constitutionalism. Even if all of the foregoing is overstated, most of the positive rights would not make things better for anyone. To be sure, it is possible that such rights would affect legislative deliberations, quite apart from judicial action. Perhaps the existence of a right to a safe environment would prompt legislatures to attend to environmental issues when they otherwise might not. It is also possible that the existence of positive rights or social aspirations will affectjudicial interpretation of existing statutory provisions. We cannot rule out the prospect of some beneficial effects. But if the likelihood is small, there is an independent argument against social and economic rights: If they will probably not make things better, they are mere surplusage, and constitutional surplusage is itself bad for nations that are trying to create a culture of constitutionalism. It is true that some of these arguments depend on somewhat speculative assumptions. Analysis of what belongs in a constitution is not like mathematics. Perhaps the positive rights would have little adverse affect on individual initiative; perhaps their existence would not affectjudicial attitudes toward more readily enforceable rights, like the right to free speech. In the end these are empirical questions on which we have no hard evidence. The ultimate question is how to proceed in the absence of such evidence. Here the most we can do is to assess the magnitude of therelevant risks. If what I have said is correct, it seems hard to believe that positive rights would HeinOnline -- 2 E. Eur. Const. Rev. 37 1993

EAST EUROPEAN CONSTITUTIONAL REVIEW actually help the lives of citizens in Eastern Europe, and it seems very possible that such rights would undermine the prospects for a form of constitutionalism that offers firm protection to basic rights and that furnishes the preconditions for the transition to a market economy. In these circumstances, what ought to be done? I suggest three routes for the future. First, people now drafting constitutions for Eastern Europe should delete or minimize provisions that call for positive rights. At least, they should eliminate those rights that fare worst under the criteria I have set out here, and restrict such rights to those that fare best (perhaps the right to social security). Second, those now drafting constitutions for Eastern Europe might put the positive rights in a separate section, as President Walesa's draft bill of rights has done in Poland, making clear that such rights are not for judicial enforcement, that they occupy a separate status, and that they are intended to set out general aspirations for public officials and for the citizenry at large. Third, judges and lawyers in Eastern Europe should now be at work developing a jurisprudence that minimizes the potential risks and maximizes the potential benefits of positive rights. As a key part of this task, they might adopt the notion that rights are "nonjusticiable"- not subject to judicial enforcement-when they call for large-scale interference with the operation of free markets, or when they call for managerial tasks not within judicial competence. Any such notion must, however, make it clear that courts will vigorously enforce the basic political and civil rights whose violation was a daily affair under Communist rule-rights such as free speech, religious liberty, freedom from police abuse, due process, and nondiscrimination on grounds of ethnicity, race, religion, and sex. With constitutional rights, as with much else, less may be more. A constitution that purports to guarantee a decent society may, in the process, guarantee nothing at all. This was a central problem with Communist constitutionalism. It would be a cruel irony if the problem were to be duplicated in the emerging democracies of Eastern Europe. Constitutional issues in market socialism. A THIR WAY? By John Roemer andjon Elster The separation of powers is a central issue in constitutional thought. The separation of executive and legislative powers, discussed elsewhere in this issue, is a prominent case. An independent judiciary is another. In a broader sense, the independence of the central bank and of the state-owned media can also be seen in this perspective. The argument for separation of powers rests both on positive and negative considerations. On the one hand, the separation of powers is a form of division of labor that enhances the efficiency of the political system. On the other, it serves to prevent total usurpation of power by any one state agency. One special problem with separation of powers-or lack of separation-plagues a number of political systems. It may be briefly characterized as the need to separate the instruments of economic policy from the tools of social policy. In theory, and in the long run, both economy and society will benefit if policies are oriented towards economic efficiency, thus maximizing the revenues that can be used to alleviate problems of unemployment and poverty. In practice, because policy-makers are often influenced by short-term considerations, there is a temptation to make economic choices on the basis of their immediate social consequences. To maintain employment, governments all over the world support declining industries and inefficient firms, blunting the edge of competition. The bailout of Chrysler in United States and the subsidization of the mining industry in Britain are two prominent examples from the West. With regard to the planned Communist economies, Janos Kornai coined the phrase "soft budget constraint" to describe the position of managers who know that banks or local governments have a strong vested interest in keeping their firms afloat-and the political clout to do so. The results in Eastern Europe, as we know, were disastrous. To be more precise, the economic crisis of the Communist countries was due largely to their failure to solve various principal-agent problems. A principal-agent problem arises when one actor or group relies on another to carry out orders or provide informatioh, but where the two HeinOnline -- 2 E. Eur. Const. Rev. 38 1993