Flanagan s Status Quo. Lindsay Swinton. April 12, 2007 ISCI 330

Similar documents
Supporting Information for Competing Gridlock Models and Status Quo Policies

Electing the President. Chapter 12 Mathematical Modeling

An example of public goods

Sincere versus sophisticated voting when legislators vote sequentially

Research Note: Gaming NAFTA. March 15, Gaming NAFTA: Trump v. Nieto

Sincere Versus Sophisticated Voting When Legislators Vote Sequentially

Problems with Group Decision Making

I assume familiarity with multivariate calculus and intermediate microeconomics.

Goods, Games, and Institutions : A Reply

Sampling Equilibrium, with an Application to Strategic Voting Martin J. Osborne 1 and Ariel Rubinstein 2 September 12th, 2002.

Supporting Information Political Quid Pro Quo Agreements: An Experimental Study

Answers to Practice Problems. Median voter theorem, supermajority rule, & bicameralism.

The Role of the Trade Policy Committee in EU Trade Policy: A Political-Economic Analysis

Modernizing Canada s Electoral System: Instant Runoff Voting as the Best Alternative. By Maxime Dubé, as an individual

ELECTIONS, GOVERNMENTS, AND PARLIAMENTS IN PROPORTIONAL REPRESENTATION SYSTEMS*

APPLICATION: PIVOTAL POLITICS

Problems with Group Decision Making

GRADE 9 Social Studies Canada: Opportunities and Challenges

On Preferences for Fairness in Non-Cooperative Game Theory

Electing the President. Chapter 17 Mathematical Modeling

Social Rankings in Human-Computer Committees

EXTENDING THE SPHERE OF REPRESENTATION:

On the Rationale of Group Decision-Making

ONTARIO SUPERIOR COURT OF JUSTICE. JOAN RUSSOW and THE GREEN PARTY OF CANADA. - and -

The California Primary and Redistricting

Canadian electoral reform involves a befuddling

Committee proposals and restrictive rules

Chapter 1: How Effectively Does Canada s Federal Political System Govern Canada for all Canadians?

Enriqueta Aragones Harvard University and Universitat Pompeu Fabra Andrew Postlewaite University of Pennsylvania. March 9, 2000

Poll Results: Electoral Reform & Political Cooperation

Median voter theorem - continuous choice

Introduction to Game Theory

Agendas and sincerity: a second response to Schwartz

Election Theory. How voters and parties behave strategically in democratic systems. Mark Crowley

LEARNING FROM SCHELLING'S STRATEGY OF CONFLICT by Roger Myerson 9/29/2006

THE MEDIAN VOTER THEOREM (ONE DIMENSION)

REFORMING THE ELECTORAL SYSTEM IN ALBERTA: THE CASE FOR DUAL- MEMBER MIXED PROPORTIONAL Sean Graham

A Spatial Theory of Party Formation.

The Problem with Majority Rule. Shepsle and Bonchek Chapter 4

Electoral Reform Questionnaire Field Dates: October 12-18, 2016

Homework 6 Answers PS 30 November 2012

Trump, Condorcet and Borda: Voting paradoxes in the 2016 Republican presidential primaries

Voting rules: (Dixit and Skeath, ch 14) Recall parkland provision decision:

Chapter 4: Voting and Social Choice.

1 Electoral Competition under Certainty

Examples that illustrate how compactness and respect for political boundaries can lead to partisan bias when redistricting. John F.

HANDBOOK OF SOCIAL CHOICE AND VOTING Jac C. Heckelman and Nicholas R. Miller, editors.

Arrow s Impossibility Theorem on Social Choice Systems

HOTELLING-DOWNS MODEL OF ELECTORAL COMPETITION AND THE OPTION TO QUIT

RATIONAL CHOICE AND CULTURE

Topics on the Border of Economics and Computation December 18, Lecture 8

Game Theory for Political Scientists. James D. Morrow

Published in Canadian Journal of Economics 27 (1995), Copyright c 1995 by Canadian Economics Association

LOGROLLING. Nicholas R. Miller Department of Political Science University of Maryland Baltimore County Baltimore, Maryland

Judicial Elections and Their Implications in North Carolina. By Samantha Hovaniec

11th Annual Patent Law Institute

Introduction to the declination function for gerrymanders

Refinements of Nash equilibria. Jorge M. Streb. Universidade de Brasilia 7 June 2016

AGENDAS AND SINCERITY: A SECOND RESPONSE TO SCHWARTZ

POLITICAL SCIENCE (POLI)

1 Aggregating Preferences

Notes for Session 7 Basic Voting Theory and Arrow s Theorem

GAME THEORY. Analysis of Conflict ROGER B. MYERSON. HARVARD UNIVERSITY PRESS Cambridge, Massachusetts London, England

POLITICAL EQUILIBRIUM SOCIAL SECURITY WITH MIGRATION

Public choice and the development of modern laboratory experimental methods in economics and political science

WISCONSIN SUPREME COURT ELECTIONS WITH PARTISANSHIP

Agendas and Strategic Voting

Resistance to Women s Political Leadership: Problems and Advocated Solutions

REFORM OF THE HUNGARIAN ELECTORAL SYSTEM

Mechanism Design with Public Goods: Committee Karate, Cooperative Games, and the Control of Social Decisions through Subcommittees

Voters Interests in Campaign Finance Regulation: Formal Models

Implications for the Desirability of a "Stage Two" in European Monetary Unification p. 107

THE BATTLE FOR THE SECESSION: Catalonia versus Spain. Joan Barceló- Soler. I. Introduction: Historical Background and Contemporary Facts

Politics is the subset of human behavior that involves the use of power or influence.

International Cooperation, Parties and. Ideology - Very preliminary and incomplete

Evolutionary Game Path of Law-Based Government in China Ying-Ying WANG 1,a,*, Chen-Wang XIE 2 and Bo WEI 2

CRITIQUE OF CAPLAN S THE MYTH OF THE RATIONAL VOTER

REFORMING THE ELECTORAL FORMULA IN PEI: THE CASE FOR DUAL-MEMBER MIXED PROPORTIONAL Sean Graham

1 Strategic Form Games

PS 124A Midterm, Fall 2013

Battleground 59: A (Potentially) Wasted Opportunity for the Republican Party Republican Analysis by: Ed Goeas and Brian Nienaber

Lecture 16: Voting systems

Government and Politics

EFFICIENCY OF COMPARATIVE NEGLIGENCE : A GAME THEORETIC ANALYSIS

Introduction to Game Theory

Transitions to Democracy

Preferential votes and minority representation in open list proportional representation systems

Voting and preference aggregation

VOTING SYSTEMS AND ARROW S THEOREM

Research Note: Toward an Integrated Model of Concept Formation

Is Democracy Possible?

Strategic Models of Politics

Do not turn over until you are told to do so by the Invigilator.

Background Essay on the Campaign

COURSE SYLLABUS PSC 761: AMERICAN POLITICAL FRONTIERS

The Impact of Minor Parties on Electoral Competition: An Examination of US House and State Legislative Races

Michael Laver and Ernest Sergenti: Party Competition. An Agent-Based Model

Women s. Political Representation & Electoral Systems. Key Recommendations. Federal Context. September 2016

2. Rule of Law. Thin/procedural (Raz) & Thick/substantive interpretation of rule of law

PEI COALITION FOR WOMEN IN GOVERNMENT. Submission to the Special Committee on Democratic Renewal for the Legislative Assembly of Prince Edward Island

Transcription:

Flanagan s Status Quo Lindsay Swinton April 12, 2007 ISCI 330

Flanagan s Status Quo In 1988 abortion legislation was abolished by the supreme court of Canada (Flanagan 120). Current law was deemed to violate a women s security of person under the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms (Wikipedia). Drafting and passing abortion legislation became the responsibility of the current Prime Minister and the House of Commons (Flanagan 121). Attempts by Brian Mulroney to introduce abortion legislation into the House of Commons and senate failed repeatedly (Flanagan 121). ) Despite public opinion favoring moderate legislation, abortion in Canada remains unlegislated (Flanagan 121).Under the circumstances stated why does Canadian abortion law remain in a state of limbo? In Game Theory and Canadian Politics Thomas Flanagan attempts to elucidate this seeming anomaly in Canadian politics. Firstly, the inability to pass new legislation is explained by the tendency for the status quo to prevail when a cyclical opinion structure (Flanagan 121) is present in the legislating body (Flanagan 121). Secondly, Flanagan (121) emphasizes how parliamentary outcomes are influenced by the procedures with which legislation is passed. These two points are illuminated and analyzed using aspects of game theory. Rational choice theory is used to analyze the parliamentary procedure and cyclical opinion structure that caused all possible resolutions and amendments introduced into the House of Commons to fail. Than, the game of chicken and extensive form games are introduced to explicate bill C-43 s majority vote in the House of Commons and subsequent failure in the senate. Although enlightening, Flanagan s analysis lacks in-depth explanations and pertinent aspects of game theory. He comments on the vote s failure to unify around the

median voter, but fails to develop or sufficiently explain this comment. The sequential games used to explore the case of bill C-43 lack fundamental aspects of game theory such as the Nash equilibrium and subgame perfection. Lastly, his assumptions pertaining to ordinal utilities appear to violate necessary elements such as connectivity and transitivity (Gates and Humes 8). This paper will attempt to critique and expand upon Flanagan s case study the staying power of the status quo. Mulroney s attempt to introduce abortion legislation to the House of Commons will be introduced and Flanagan s analysis of the subsequent events will be explained and critiqued using additional aspects of game theory absent from the original paper. Mulroney began the battle for abortion legislation by attempting to test opinion in the House of Commons with an unconventional parliamentary procedure. He would introduce a set of resolutions containing three different choices: a moderate gestational approach, a pro-life approach and a pro-choice approach. The resolutions were to be voted upon and drafted into a bill (Flanagan 124). This voting process would eliminate a fourth option--the status quo-- which would typically be voted upon in parliamentary procedure. (Flanagan 124). Regular parliamentary procedure dictates the bill in its final, amended form compete against the status-quo. The opposition refused to comply with the new procedures and a free vote was held on a motion supporting moderate gestational legislation. (Flanagan 124). The resolution and five amendments were voted upon and defeated. The amendments were as follows: 1. A Pro-choice compromise that would necessitate justification of termination in later stages of pregnancy (Flanagan 126).

2. A pro-life amendment that would define early pregnancy to the first trimester (Flanagan 126). 3. A strong pro-life amendment allowing abortion only if the mother s life is in danger (Flanagan 126) 4. An amendment that would define early pregnancy to the first eighteen weeks (Flanagan 126). 5. A pro-choice amendment that would allow abortions to be performed only by a qualified doctors. (Flanagan 126) With the failure of the resolution and all its amendments the status-quo continued to prevail. However, the vote did successfully test opinion in the house. The Members of Parliament could now be categorized according to their opinions. Flanagan analyzed this data by placing the MP s into seven groups: 1. 40 Resolute Pro-choice who wanted to maintain the status quo 2. 12 Pro-choice compromisers who voted for amendments one and five 3. 17 Pro-choice leaning moderates who voted for amendments one, five and the government resolution 4. 38 moderates who voted for the government resolution 5. 12 Pro-life leaning moderates who supported the government resolution plus amendment two 6. 9 Pro-life compromisers who voted for amendment three and the government resolution 7. 96 Resolute pro-lifers who voted for amendment two and/or three and against the government resolution. (Flanagan 127)

A strange phenomenon had occurred: the ninety-six pro-lifer s voted against the government resolution in the final vote and by default supported the status-quo a seemingly pro-choice option. Flanagan mentions that the expected outcome would be for the majority to coalesce around the position of the median voter as is predicted by elementary rational analysis of uni-dimensional conflicts (Flanagan 127). He fails to explain this comment. What is a uni-dimensional conflict and why does this situation violate its expectations? A uni-dimensional conflict is a dispute involving a single issue, such as abortion, with gradated strengths of opinion (Brams 28). It can be represented graphically with opinion along the x-axis and the number of voters along the y-axis (Brams 28). The median is the line intersecting the x-axis dividing the area under the curve into two areas of equal proportion (Brams 28). According to rational analysis voter opinions are fixed but their vote will depend upon the position of the options along the horizontal axis (Brams 28). Under a bell-shaped distribution the median position falls at the optimal position for voting support because the majority of voters will have an opinion near the median position (Bram 28). Flanagan s argument can be farther explored by displaying the distribution of MP opinion and placing each amendment at its approximate position on the distribution. This is demonstrated below (fig 1). MP opinion does not fall under a stereotypical, symmetric, bell shaped curve. Instead, opinions at the extremities have the greatest frequency. The pro-life side has an especially high frequency of voters at its extreme pole. This causes the median to drift left and fall between the pro-life moderates and prolife compromisers (Flanagan 127). According to rational analysis amendment two should

have passed because it falls closest to the median and therefore should have harbored the greatest support. Why did amendment two fail? And why did the status quo-prevail when it falls to the far right of the gradient and is the farthest choice from the median? Median Fig 1: Voting distribution Parliamentary procedure and a structurally induced equilibrium determined the fate of amendment two (Flanagan 130). In parliamentary procedure Member s of Parliament choose between two options in a series of votes. Each amendment competes against the original resolution and in the final vote the amended resolution is pitted against the status-quo (Flanagan 130). Amendment two was introduced before amendment three (Flanagan 127). It was defeated because the resolute pro-lifer s and pro-life compromisers still hoped to pass amendment three (Flanagan 127). The final vote was between the gestational resolution and the status quo. The status quo s triumph is an example of a structurally induced equilibrium. A structurally induced equilibrium is a

forced outcome obtained by directing options into a binary choice (Flanagan 130) The parliamentary procedure forced the resolute pro-lifer s to choose between the status quo and the gestational resolution in the final vote, when they clearly preferred a different option: amendments two and/or three. It was during the final vote that the ninety-six pro-lifers did something unexpected. They voted against the gestational resolution (blue in Fig 1) in support of the status quo (pink in Fig 1) seemingly supporting the position farthest from their own (Flanagan 128). This action can explained by the resolute pro-lifer s hope that a present status quo would lead to move favorable legislation in the future (Flanagan 128). In a final attempt to introduce abortion legislation Mulroney brought forth bill C- 43. If successful, it would legalize abortion for women when pregnancy threatened psychological, physical and/or mental health (Flanagan 132). Mulroney announced that bill C-43 would be the final attempt by his government to introduce abortion legislation. Additionally, he declared all cabinet ministers would support bill C-43 (Flanagan 133). This is an example of precommitment (Flanagan 133): Mulroney declared his intended action and therefore limited the possible outcomes of the vote. Bill C-43 passed in the House of Commons but failed in the senate. Flanagan modeled the situation in the House of Commons before and after precommitment using sequential games. Flanagan demonstrated the actions of the pro-life bloc and prime minister in the sequential games on the following page (Flanagan 128).

Fig 2: Flanagan s (134) Sequential Games

Flanagan (133) compares the actions of the resolute-pro lifers to players in the game of chicken. This comparison appears improbable and I will argue that the outcomes of the sequential games can better be explained using Nash equilibrium and subgame perfection Flanagan claims the pro-life block s actions, before Mulroney s announcement to precommit, were analogous to the game of chicken. Although precommitment is a strategy used to respond to the game of chicken, the game modeled by Flanagan (134) does not resemble chicken. Chicken is modeled in matrix form below (fig 3) C D C 3,3 (P) 2,4 (N,P) D 4,2 (N,P) 1,1, Where 4>3>2>1 N= nash equilibrium P=pareto optimal outcome Fig 3 Chicken The sequential game created by Flanagan was converted to matrix form and is modeled below. Prime Minister Pro- Life Bloc Support C-43 Oppose C-43 No Bill New Bill 2,3 2,3 (P) (P) 1,1 3,2 (N,P) Where 3>2>1 Fig 4: Matrix form of sequential game

Firstly, Flanagan s game contains only three possible utility values compared to chicken s four values. Secondly, it contains different Nash equilibrium and pareto optimal outcomes. Lastly, Flanagan s game contains repeated outcomes: no bill and support C-43 and, new bill and support C-43 produce the same outcome. The matrix form of Flanagan s game does not appear to be analogous to chicken. Flanagan neglects to analyze his sequential games using typical elements of game theory. Analysis using Nash equilibrium and subgame perfection adds depth to the explanation of the outcomes observed. Before precomittment a new bill is the subgame perfect outcome. This means it is both a feasible outcome within the game and is a best response for both players to all of the other players possible strategies (Gates and Humes 25). After precommitment the passing of C-43 is the subgame perfect outcome. According to Flanagan s model the subgame perfect outcomes model the real life result: only after precommitment did abortion legislation successfully pass through the House of Commons. My final contention involves Flanagan s sequential games and two basic assumptions of game theory: connectedness and transitivity (Green and Shapiro 15). Firstly, connectedness implies that the preferences of an agent can be ranked. (Green and Shapiro). Attempting to assign a common ranked utility to a group and not a single agent becomes problematic. Flanagan (134) assigns common ranked utility values to all three pro-life groups. He is assuming all members of the pro-life group including pro-life leaning moderates who supported the government s original resolution and amendment two and, resolute pro-lifer s who opposed the government resolution but supported amendment two and three would rank their preferences the same. This is

unlikely as the pro-life leaning moderates would be more likely to prefer C-43 which is similar to the first resolution and amendment two more than the resolute pro-lifers. Flanagan, by assigning a common ranked utility to all members of the pro-life group may be challenging the assumption of connectivity. The inherent variation in opinion between poles of the pro-life bloc also hinders the assumption of transitivity. For transitivity to occur in Flanagan s sequential game the pro-life bloc would always prefer a new bill over C-43 passing and always prefer C-43 passing over the status-quo, and also always prefer a new bill over the status-quo (Gates and Humes 8). This implies the presence of a unified opinion within the group. This unified opinion is absent from the pro-life bloc. Therefore another basic assumption of game theory may be neglected in Flanagan s sequential game analysis. In conclusion, Flanagan s analysis only begins to explore the applications of game theory to the staying power of the status quo (Flanagan 119). His analysis was propelled farther by modeling the distribution of MP opinion surrounding the abortion issue. One was than able to see the discrepancy between opinion and the outcome: the majority of MP s supported a pro-life approach but the status quo prevailed. The idea of structure induced equilibrium increases our understanding of this phenomenon in politics. By farther analyzing Flanagan s sequential game model with sub game perfect equilibrium our understanding of the final outcome increases and the outcome is seen to mirror real life events. Finally, certain aspects of Flanagan s sequential game model were critiqued and found deficient. Although Flanagan s case study was enlightening, some aspects may be flawed and an enhanced analysis farther explicates the phenomenon of the staying power of the status quo.

Works Cited Abortion in Canada." Wikipedia. 01 Apr.-May 2007 <http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/abortion_in_canada#history>. Brams, Steven J. Rational Politics. Washinton, DC: Congressional Quarterly Inc., 1985. Flanagan, Thomas. Game Theory and Canadian Politics. Toronto: University of Toronoto Press, 1999. Gates, Scott, and Brian D. Humes. Games, Information and Politics. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 1997. Green, Donald P., and Ian Shapiro. Pathologies of Rational Choice. New Haven and London: Yale University Press, 1994.