Cosmopolitanism and patriotism: questions of identity, membership and belonging

Similar documents
Dialogue of Civilizations: Finding Common Approaches to Promoting Peace and Human Development

Introduction. in this web service Cambridge University Press

What is multiculturalism?

Towards a Global Civil Society. Daniel Little University of Michigan-Dearborn

The Student as Global Citizen: Feasible Utopia or Dangerous Mirage?

Where does Confucian Virtuous Leadership Stand? A Critique of Daniel Bell s Beyond Liberal Democracy

COMMUNITARIAN MORAL CLAIMS FOR DEMOCRACY.

C o m m u n i c a t i o n f o r A l l :

PHILOSOPHICAL IMAGES OF THE HUMAN BEING: CITIZEN OF THE WORLD AS A CULTURAL FIGURE

Part III Immigration Policy: Introduction

PLAN 619 Fall 2014 Cultural Diversity in Planning University of Hawai`i, Department of Urban & Regional Planning

In Nations and Nationalism, Ernest Gellner says that nationalism is a theory of

Constructing a Socially Just System of Social Welfare in a Multicultural Society: The U.S. Experience

Multiculturalism Sarah Song Encyclopedia of Political Theory, ed. Mark Bevir (Sage Publications, 2010)

Ideas for an intelligent and progressive integration discourse

National identity and global culture

U75138 Persuasive Communication

Education and Politics in the Individualized Society

For a Universal Declaration of Democracy. A. Rationale

Cohesion in diversity

We the Stakeholders: The Power of Representation beyond Borders? Clara Brandi

The Student as Global Citizen: Feasible Utopia or Dangerous Mirage?

Comments on Schnapper and Banting & Kymlicka

Last time we discussed a stylized version of the realist view of global society.

Maureen Molloy and Wendy Larner

Carlos Eloy Viteri Gualinga is an exemplary insider-outsider in several. ways. A Kichwa born in a small community in the Ecuadorian Amazon, he is the

A NATIONAL CALL TO CONVENE AND CELEBRATE THE FOUNDING OF GLOBAL GUMII OROMIA (GGO)

Citizenship Education and Inclusion: A Multidimensional Approach

For a Universal Declaration of Democracy

Training future members of the world with an understanding of global citizenship

Lilie Chouliaraki Cosmopolitanism. Book section

Recommendation Rec (2002) 12 of the Committee of Ministers to member states on education for democratic citizenship

Citizenship Education for the 21st Century

Cultural Cosmopolitanism and Civic Education

NATIONALISM. Nationalism

Global Justice. Spring Books:

Expanding on the Politics of Difference

Definition: Institution public system of rules which defines offices and positions with their rights and duties, powers and immunities p.

Utopian Justice: A Review of Global Justice, A Cosmopolitan Account, by Gillian Brock

E-LOGOS. Rawls two principles of justice: their adoption by rational self-interested individuals. University of Economics Prague

Nationalism

Universal Rights and Responsibilities: The Universal Declaration of Human Rights and the Earth Charter. By Steven Rockefeller.

Mehrdad Payandeh, Internationales Gemeinschaftsrecht Summary

Mark Scheme (Results) Summer GCE Government & Politics Other Ideological Traditions 6GP04 4B

GOVT-353: Political Theory and the Global Order. Craig French Department of Government, Georgetown University Fall 2009

HYBRID MULTICULTURALISM? ETHNIC MINORITY STUDENT POLICY IN HONG KONG 1. Kerry J Kennedy The Hong Kong Institute of Education

The cosmopolitan imagination: critical cosmopolitanism and social theory

THE GIFT ECONOMY AND INDIGENOUS-MATRIARCHAL LEGACY: AN ALTERNATIVE FEMINIST PARADIGM FOR RESOLVING THE PALESTINIAN-ISRAELI CONFLICT

Standards Correlated to Teaching through Text Sets: Citizenship and Government 20194

A Civil Religion. Copyright Maurice Bisheff, Ph.D.

Refugee Rights and Global Justice in Religious Ethics

What Role Does Othering Play In Maintaining The Illusion Of Imagined Communities?

Strategic plan

LAW AND POVERTY. The role of final speaker at a two and one half day. The truth is, as could be anticipated, that your

THE MEANING OF IDEOLOGY

9 GRADE CANADA IN THE CONTEMPORARY WORLD

Industrial Society: The State. As told by Dr. Frank Elwell

Pearson Edexcel GCE in Government & Politics (6GP04/4B) Paper 4B: Ideological Traditions

Political Resolution IndustriALL Global Union s 2 nd Congress Rio de Janeiro, Brazil, 5-7 October 2016

COMPETENCES FOR DEMOCRATIC CULTURE Living together as equals in culturally diverse democratic societies

10 WHO ARE WE NOW AND WHO DO WE NEED TO BE?

What role does religion play in the migration process?

Comparative futures: notes on a methodology for the study of sustainability, religion and global ethics

Good Question. An Exploration in Ethics. A series presented by the Kenan Institute for Ethics at Duke University

Torill Strand. Introduction: Cosmopolitanism in the Making. Studies in Philosophy and Education 2009, vol 29(2), pp

APPENDIX A Citizenship Continuum of Study from K gr. 3 Page 47

2. Realism is important to study because it continues to guide much thought regarding international relations.

Ada, National College for Digital Skills supports the Home Office 4P Prevent strategy to combat radicalisation and terrorism.

Centro de Estudos Sociais, Portugal WP4 Summary Report Cross-national comparative/contrastive analysis

MY VISION FOR INDIA By Samiksha Mallick Before I begin to tell my readers my vision for India, I would like to bring under limelight the things I see

Strategic Insights: Getting Comfortable with Conflicting Ideas

New York University Multinational Institute of American Studies Study of the United States Institute on U.S. Culture and Society

Global Changes and Fundamental Development Trends in China in the Second Decade of the 21st Century

2007 Thomson/West. No Claim to Orig. U.S. Govt. Works.

CITIZENS AND STRANGERS GATEWAY 100 Fall 2007

The Moral Myth and the. Abuse of Humanitarian Intervention

National Charter for Education on Living Together in Lebanon

Part III Immigration Policy: Introduction

COMMISSION OF THE EUROPEAN COMMUNITIES COMMUNICATION FROM THE COMMISSION TO THE EUROPEAN COUNCIL A CITIZENS AGENDA

Questioning America Again

Chantal Mouffe On the Political

Politics between Philosophy and Democracy

In his account of justice as fairness, Rawls argues that treating the members of a

Business Ethics Journal Review

EUROBAROMETER 62 PUBLIC OPINION IN THE EUROPEAN UNION

Strengthening the role of communities, business, non-governmental organisations in cross-cultural understanding and building inclusive societies

Education for a Human Right to Peace from the Perspective of a Philosophy for Making Peace(s) 1

Multiculturalism and the Canadian Identity: Where are we Going. Canadian Identity

Essentials of Peace Education. Working Paper of InWEnt and IFT. Essentials of Peace Education

Department of Political Science and Public Administration

Plato s Concept of Justice: Prepared by, Mr. Thomas G.M., Associate Professor, Pompei College Aikala DK

Subverting the Orthodoxy

1) Is the "Clash of Civilizations" too broad of a conceptualization to be of use? Why or why not?

Solutions for Environment, Economy, and Democracy (SEED): A Manifesto for Prosperity

Summary. A deliberative ritual Mediating between the criminal justice system and the lifeworld. 1 Criminal justice under pressure

Planning for Immigration

Do we have a strong case for open borders?

GLOBAL DEMOCRACY THE PROBLEM OF A WRONG PERSPECTIVE

Diasporas and Development. Michael Collyer University of Sussex, Brighton, UK

Whilst few contest the inspirational words of the Millennium Declaration, the same cannot be

Transcription:

151 ELISABETE DO ROSÁRIO MENDES SILVA Polytechnic Institute of Bragança ULICES University of Lisbon Centre for English Studies Cosmopolitanism and patriotism: questions of identity, membership and belonging We now live in a globalized world which influences international relations, world economy and diplomacy. The individual also faces the challenge of imagining and feeling part of the world, besides the obligations he owes to the state he belongs to. This conception is based on the idea that each individual has a significant role in the sense that they represent a relevant contribution for the world problems, for peace maintenance, for the global and equal distribution of goods and resources, for humanitarian assistance and for the protection of the human rights. The world citizen is therefore asked to be part of a compassionate world project, in a tolerant and understanding outlook of our fellow citizens, despite all the skeptical positions regarding this ideal. We are, in fact, growingly faced with a plurality of identities, promoting thus a cosmopolitan way of life. According to Robin Cohen (1999), taking into account the three great forces which define our current world: globalization, multiculturalism and nationalism, the solution lies in cosmopolitanism because, on the one side, there is no other way and it s part of our global contemporary conditions and, on the other, only cosmopolitanism represents the right choice seeing that it considers the individual in a universal perspective. (Cohen, 1999: 25) However, the respect for difference and cultural diversity was seriously threatened by the terrorist attacks of 9/11, which created an atmosphere of suspicion and skepticism regarding the Other. Consequently, kindness to strangers was replaced with mistrust about

152 foreigners. The contrast between North and South, between The West and poor countries in Africa, in America and in Asia has also been a social and political concern shared by both western states, NGOs and other humanitarian associations. The big issue here is the solidarity among States. We can ask then the following questions: Is there a moral duty of helping the nations in need?; Does moral cosmopolitanism represent the hope of a universal redistribution of justice?; Is local identity threatened by the ideals of a world citizenship? It is therefore our main purpose to try to answer these questions, by centring on the relevancy of the concept cosmopolitanism in contrast with other forms of dealing with the Other, such as nationalism and multiculturalism. We will then reflect on the similarities and differences of cosmopolitanism and patriotism, focussing on the problems of world citizenship and accounting for the role of local/national identities, nowadays. Finally, we will try to demonstrate that cosmopolitanism, in its ideals of absence of roots and belonging to a national state represents a myth and a utopia. Nevertheless, cosmopolitanism stands for a political project that should not be overlooked. In reality, the plurality of cultures and the awareness and, eventually, acceptance of the other, of the unknown, eased by the advance of technology and transports, in addition to the huge economic disparities between rich and poor, between globalised countries and globalizing ones endorse the consciousness of a cosmopolitan condition which represents a cosmopolitan empathy concerning the Others. Aimed at this reality, cosmopolitanism has assumed a transnational humanitarian insight. However, the ideals of world citizenship, so proclaimed by the Stoics, that is, the nonexistence of roots and the absence of allegiance to a state, are currently questioned and revised under a patriotic outlook. The need of national or local roots is defended by some authors (Appiah, 2006), and for some others (Nussbaum, 1996) love of country does not come after love of humanity 1. Pheng Cheah calls our attention to the fact that a definition 1 For Nussbaum, cosmopolitanism represents an exile from the comfort of local truths and from the protector feeling of patriotism and from the symbols of national belonging. Cosmopolitanism only offers love of humanity. (Nussbaum, 1996: 15-

153 of cosmopolitanism as an elitist absence of roots is inadequate. Hence, the author argues that the intellectual spirit underlying the notion of a world citizen is not absent of roots. However, one imagines a sphere of universal belonging that goes beyond the ties to a country: (Cheah, 2006:487) ( ) what is imagined is a universal circle of belonging that involves the transcendence of the particularistic and blindly given ties of kinship and country. Cosmopolitanism therefore embodies the universality of philosophical reason itself, namely its power of transcending the particular and contingent. Anthony Appiah, defender of the liberal tradition, advocates the theory of rooted cosmopolitanism, that is, the individual owes obedience to a civil society, respecting the state institutions as a citizen of that state, but always valuing human rights and cultural difference: (Appiah, 1998:106) I have been arguing, in essence, that you can be cosmopolitan celebrating the variety of human cultures; rooted loyal to one local society (or a few) that you count as home; liberal convinced of the value of the individual; and patriotic celebrating the institutions of the state (or states) within which you live. The cosmopolitan patriot can, for Appiah, look for the possibility of the existence of a world where everyone is rooted cosmopolitan, linked to their national roots and cultural specificities, but benefiting from the existence of different places that represent home for other culturally diverse people. (Appiah, 1996: 22) The respect for difference is uttered through the model of conversation: (Appiah, 2006: xxi) The world is getting more crowded; in the next half a century the population of our once foraging species will 17). This theory is refuted by some scholars (Appiah, Cheah, Hillary Putman) who consider that cosmopolitanism and patriotism are not that distinct, or that the two feelings are not incompatible.

154 approach nine billion. Depending on the circumstances, conversations across boundaries can be delightful, or just vexing: what they are mainly are, though, is inevitable. The dialogue does not necessarily generate consensus, especially when we speak about values. Nevertheless, dialogue is important when it comes to helping people to get used to the presence of the other. Appiah, in our opinion, does not clear out a form of concrete relationship between different people. This ideal of cultural communication beyond borders seems equally difficult to achieve, since the task of making the existence of the other concrete reveals itself extremely complex. Even when we try to imagine other lifestyles and other communities we just picture them abstractly (cf. Scarry, 1996). Furthermore, Appiah explains the application of the real practice of world citizenship to which he constantly appeals to in a superficial and inconsistent way. Cosmopolitanism and patriotism, more feelings than ideologies (Appiah, 1996: 23), complement each other in the sense that they represent forms of belonging and they share the same ideals of respect for the other and association with a more restrict sphere within other wider circles. Hence, living in adequate spheres of moral concern, as Appiah advocates, must uphold the cosmopolitan ideal of life: (Appiah, 1996: 29). It is because humans live best on a smaller scale that we should defend not only the state, but the county, the town, the street, the business, the craft, the profession, and the family, as communities, as circles among the many circles that are narrower than the human horizon, that are appropriate spheres of moral concern. We should, as cosmopolitans, defend the right to live in democratic states with rich possibilities of association within and across their borders, states of which they can be patriotic citizens. And as cosmopolitans, we can claim that right for ourselves. However, we agree with Immanuel Wallerstein (1996) when he asserts the idea that the virtues of patriotism and cosmopolitanism are neither abstract nor universal and the consequences of acting as a world citizen can lead to different results, depending on the time and

155 on the space one lives in, defining, thus, the attitudes concerning diversity: (Wallerstein, 1996: 122) Those who are strong strong politically, economically, socially have the option of aggressive hostility toward the weak or magnanimous comprehension of difference. In either case, they remain privileged. Those who are weak, or at least weaker, will only overcome disadvantage if they insist on the principles of group equality. To do this effectively, they may have to stimulate group consciousness nationalism, ethnic assertiveness. One must also take into account nationality and the feeling of belonging to a more confined sphere when the cosmopolitan ideal is intended to be applied. In a first plan, our ties are more confined and associated with a community. To go beyond these ties would mean risking the loss of belonging to a place, to a country and even to the world (Barber, 1996: 34). Gertrude Himmelfarb (1996) also calls our attention to the utopian and illusive character of cosmopolitanism, focussing on the essential qualities of nation, such as family, race, religion, culture, communities in the individual s life: (Himmelfarb, 1996: 76-77) Cosmopolitanism ( ) obscures, indeed, the reality of the world in which a good many human beings actually reside. It is utopian, not only in its unrealistic assumption of a commonality of aims, aspirations, and values, but also in its unwarranted optimism. ( ) To pledge one s fundamental allegiance to cosmopolitanism is to try to transcend not only nationality but all the actualities, particularities, and realities of life that constitute one s natural identity. Cosmopolitanism has a nice, high-minded ring to it, but it is an illusion, and, like all illusions, perilous. We agree with the author on this notion of utopia and illusion underlying cosmopolitanism. In fact, our roots are based on familiar, local and national specific contexts that unavoidably shape our identity. Moreover, the cosmopolitan dream of creating a unified global government represents a seductive idea, but difficult to accomplish because conflicts of values and nationalist ambitions and

156 ideals that distinguish and oppose the many nations of the world will always subsist. Moving on to a more positive insight on the concept cosmopolitanism, Charles Taylor (1996), as well as other authors (Walzer (2004), Nussbaum (1996) and Wallerstein (1996), asserts the idea of a civic education in order to enhance the underlying values of patriotism to attain cosmopolitan solidarity and a common moral ethics: (Taylor, 1996: 120) ( ) we need patriotism as well as cosmopolitanism because modern democratic states are extremely exigent common enterprises in self-rule. They require a great deal of their members, demanding much greater solidarity toward compatriots than toward humanity in general. We cannot make a success of these enterprises without strong common identification. And considering the alternatives to democracy in our world, it is not in the interest of humanity that we fail in these enterprises. However, there are still many political and economic constraints and different theories as far as the social treatment of difference is concerned which represent rejection sources and a barrier for the accomplishment of the project of cosmopolitanism. Multiculturalism and nationalism, as political, philosophical and social ideologies, represent, in our point of view, strategies to deal with all types of difference, such as cultural, ethnic or social. Nevertheless, the ideals of both multiculturalism and nationalism are divergent from the ideals of cosmopolitanism. One the one hand, multicultural procedures base themselves on the assumption of difference and alienation of the other and, on the other, nationalism stands for homogeneity and sameness. Multiculturalism safeguards utmost cultural freedom for every community within the national space. That can lead to perverse consequences, such as the seclusion of communities: (Beck, 2006: 67) ( ) multiculturalism postulates an essentialist identity and rivalry among cultures, though in a very diluted form. The strategy of multiculturalism presupposes collective notions of difference and takes its orientation from more or less

157 homogeneous groups conceived as either similar to or different, but in any case clearly demarcated, from one another and as binding for individual members. Multiculturalism, in opposition to individualism, stands for the prospect of the different ethnic groups living side by side in the same State. Multicultural tolerance means acceptance of the other, even if it becomes a burden and a nuisance: (Beck, 2006: 67) According to multiculturalism, there is no such thing as the individual. Individuals are merely epiphenomena of their cultures. Hence there is a direct line leading from the duality between Europe and its barbarian others, through imperialism, colonialism and Eurocentric universalism, to multiculturalism and global dialogue. In each case individuals are conceived as members of territorialhierarchical and ethnic-political units, which then engage in dialogue with one another across frontiers. Nowadays, the trans-nationalisation of values and of ways of life allows a cultural permeability and the human rights universality is much more valued and protected. Negative words such as diaspora, mongrelism, cultural hybridism start to acquire a more positive and realist association in view of the fact that there is a more conscious appraisal of the individual. However, this cultural plurality only becomes real and fully acknowledged within a national frame. (Breckenridge, 2002: 6) Consequently, nationalism, representing the celebration of a group national belonging, denies difference on the inside, but produces and stabilizes it externally. (Beck, 56) There is thus a political solidarity only to the national citizens, excluding the Others, who have dissimilar rights concerning social security, for instance. This is one reason why other nations can be stigmatized as inferior. The distinction between us and the others is therefore used to promote national unity. In this context, nationalism for Beck must be modified into a cosmopolitan course as a way of mitigating the difference and avoiding social and national prejudice: (Beck, 2006: 62) Only a nationalism modified in a cosmopolitan direction can exploit the political potential for cooperation between states,

158 and thereby regain the ability to solve national problems under conditions of interdependence. A fusion of national and international strategies is necessary to check the potential for ethnic violence created by globalization both internally and externally, but without dismissing the difference as a premodern prejudice. In fact, the nation, as a frame of public culture and political symbolism and of a mass culture oriented to the mobilization of citizens for the love and defence of the nation (Smith, 2001: 35), still represents, on the one hand, a powerful institution in the regulation of the cosmopolitan ideals concerning social justice, given that the richest nations could, effectively, have a say in the distribution of wealth and in the security of human rights on a world scale. However, on the other hand, national identity will still represent a powerful restriction between the members of the nation and foreigners who are steered clear of full citizenship. These constraints reject cosmopolitanism, contradicting the ideal of world citizenship asserted by the cosmopolitans. Last century and presently, the recurring ethnic conflicts for example, in the Rwanda Genocide in 1994, and now, the most recent one, in Republic of Congo, the economic competition, the environmental clashes and the protection of the national security all concur with a rejection of the others and, in addition, promote national identity and culture. Cosmopolitanism, in its Stoic definition, is utopian and illusory (cf. Himmelfarb, 1996) because, as verified, there are many constraints, inevitable in our society, which prevent the success of the cosmopolitan ideals in their full outline. According to Appiah (2006: xx), cosmopolitanism represents an ideal and an adventure which should not be repudiated, but it is still a relevant political project that questions the moral position of the political communities. Despite all the resurgent nationalisms and the non-immigration politics, there is today a more cosmopolitan conscience of the Other. Globalisation and the consequent development of transports and technology shortened the distance between people. What happens in the world, bad news or good news, has become visible through the media. Some of those images cause repulse, pity and human solidarity but that s all. In most cases, these feelings symbolize mere pity and solidarity for the ones in need and real help is not rendered concrete.

159 One can, however, think of two premises of moral cosmopolitanism, global justice and cosmopolitan hope, to try to help people in need. The moral obligation to help others, asserted by Benhabib and Arendt, must, in reality, represent not only a local and national ethic principle but also universal. Despite our political and economic competitive world, we should follow Immanuel Wallerstein s advice (1996: 124). For the author the best way to deal with our social reality is to try to understand that we are not citizens of the world but that we occupy particular niches in an unequal world. We consider, nevertheless, that the defence of our national and local interests is not at all incompatible with the cosmopolitan attitudes of seeing the world. To sum up, and presenting our definition of cosmopolitanism, the real cosmopolitan is the one who feels at home everywhere he goes, respecting and following, yet, the rules of every nation he visits or lives in. Moreover, a cosmopolitan does not feel at home in a nation that does not respect humanist values, assumed as universal in the dominant paradigm of the European culture. BIBLIOGRAPHY: APPIAH, Kwame Anthony (2006). Cosmopolitanism. Ethics in a World of Strangers. New York & London, W.W. Norton & Company, 2006. (1998). Cosmopolitan Patriots in CHEAH, Pheng & ROBBINS, Bruce (eds.). Cosmopolitics. Thinking and Feeling Beyond the Nation. Minneapolis: University of Minneapolis Press, pp. 91-114.

160 (1996). Cosmopolitan Patriots in NUSSBAUM, Martha C. For Love of Country. Debating the Limits of Patriotism. Boston: Beacon Press, pp. 21-29. ARENDT, Hannah. [1951] (1968). The Origins of Totalitarianism. Harcourt, Brace and Janovich: New York. BECK, Ulrich (2006). Cosmopolitan Vision. Transl. by Ciaran Cronin. Cambridge: Polity Press. BENHABIB, Seyla (2004). The Rights of Others. Aliens, Residents and Citizens. Cambridge: CUP. BRECKENRIDGE, Carol A. et al. Durham & London: Duke University Press. (2002). Cosmopolitanism. CHEAH, Pheng (2006). Cosmopolitanism. in Theory, Culture & Society. London, Thousand Oaks and New Delhi: Sage, vol. 23 (1-2): 486-496. COHEN, Robin (1999). Back to the Future: From Metropolis to Cosmopolis in HJARNO, Jan (ed). From Metropolis to Cosmopolis. Esbjerg: South Jutland University Press. pp. 9-26. HIMMELFARB, Gertrude. (1996). The Illusions of Cosmopolitanism in NUSSBAUM, Martha C. For Love of Country. Debating the Limits of Patriotism. Boston: Beacon Press, pp. 72-77.

161 NUSSBAUM, Martha C. (1996). Patriotism and Cosmopolitanism For Love of Country. Debating the Limits of Patriotism. Boston: Beacon Press, pp. 2-20. SCARRY, Elaine (1996) The Difficulty of Imagining Other People in NUSSBAUM, Martha C. For Love of Country. Debating the Limits of Patriotism. Boston: Beacon Press, pp. 98-110. SMITH, Anthony (2001) Nationalism. Theory, Ideology, History, Cambridge & Malden: Polity Press. Taylor, Charles (1996) Why Democracy Needs Patriotism in NUSSBAUM, Martha C. For Love of Country. Debating the Limits of Patriotism. Boston: Beacon Press, pp. 119-121. WALLERSTEIN, Immanuel (1996) Neither Patriotism nor Cosmopolitanism in NUSSBAUM, Martha C. (1996). For Love of Country. Debating the Limits of Patriotism. Boston: Beacon Press, pp. 122-124. WALZER, Michael. (2005) Politics and Passion. New Haven & London: Yale University Press.