The author of this important volume

Similar documents
Introduction. Cambridge University Press Natural Law Liberalism Christopher Wolfe Excerpt More information

Rawls versus the Anarchist: Justice and Legitimacy

Libertarianism. Polycarp Ikuenobe A N I NTRODUCTION

Commentary on Idil Boran, The Problem of Exogeneity in Debates on Global Justice

The Justification of Justice as Fairness: A Two Stage Process

POLITICAL AUTHORITY AND PERFECTIONISM: A RESPONSE TO QUONG

Reconciling Educational Adequacy and Equity Arguments Through a Rawlsian Lens

Choose one question from each section to answer in the time allotted.

AMY GUTMANN: THE CONSTRUCTIVE POTENTIAL OF COMMUNITARIAN VALUES DOES GUTMANN SUCCEED IN SHOWING THE CONSTRUCTIVE POTENTIAL OF COMMUNITARIAN VALUES?

Chantal Mouffe On the Political

Choose one question from each section to answer in the time allotted.

E-LOGOS. Rawls two principles of justice: their adoption by rational self-interested individuals. University of Economics Prague

Last time we discussed a stylized version of the realist view of global society.

24.03: Good Food 3/13/17. Justice and Food Production

RESPONSE TO JAMES GORDLEY'S "GOOD FAITH IN CONTRACT LAW: The Problem of Profit Maximization"

The character of public reason in Rawls s theory of justice

S.L. Hurley, Justice, Luck and Knowledge, (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2003), 341 pages. ISBN: (hbk.).

PH 3022 SOCIAL AND POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY UK LEVEL 5 UK CREDITS: 15 US CREDITS: 3/0/3

Public Schools and Sexual Orientation

Introduction 478 U.S. 186 (1986) U.S. 558 (2003). 3

Justice As Fairness: Political, Not Metaphysical (Excerpts)

Natural Law and Spontaneous Order in the Work of Gary Chartier

Inclusion, Exclusion, Constitutionalism and Constitutions

In Defense of Rawlsian Constructivism

Book Prospectus. The Political in Political Economy: from Thomas Hobbes to John Rawls

Faithful citizens, faithful voting

1. In the feudal period there was little idea of individuals having their own interests or

Rawls, Islam, and political constructivism: Some questions for Tampio

2 INTRODUCTION. Zelman v. Simmons-Harris (2002). 2

MULTICULTURALISM AND DELIBERATIVE DEMOCRACY. Maurizio Passerin d'entrèves. University of Manchester

Incentives and the Natural Duties of Justice

POLITICAL SCIENCE (POLI)

The Values of Liberal Democracy: Themes from Joseph Raz s Political Philosophy

Jan Narveson and James P. Sterba

Comments on Schnapper and Banting & Kymlicka

Balancing Procedures and Outcomes Within Democratic Theory: Core Values and Judicial Review

Two Sides of the Same Coin

We the Stakeholders: The Power of Representation beyond Borders? Clara Brandi

Education for Deliberative Character: The Problem of Persistent Disagreement and Religious Individuals

Multiculturalism and liberal democracy

Rawls s Notion of Overlapping Consensus by Michael Donnan

Political equality, wealth and democracy

Multiculturalism Sarah Song Encyclopedia of Political Theory, ed. Mark Bevir (Sage Publications, 2010)

Politics between Philosophy and Democracy

No man is an island. By Ingemund Hägg 2. John Stuart Mill, liberalism and flawed attacks by anti-liberals 1. The human being

The Veil of Ignorance in Rawlsian Theory

Educational Adequacy, Educational Equality, and Ideal Theory. Jaime Ahlberg. University of Wisconsin Madison

Penalizing Public Disobedience*

Rousseau s general will, civil rights, and property

IS IT TIME TO REWRITE THE CONSTITUTION? FIDELITY TO OUR IMPERFECT CONSTITUTION

Robust Political Economy. Classical Liberalism and the Future of Public Policy

The problem of global distributive justice in Rawls s The Law of Peoples

Two Pictures of the Global-justice Debate: A Reply to Tan*

Entry by Birth Alone?: Rawlsian Egalitarianism and the Basic Right to Invite

The Proper Metric of Justice in Justice as Fairness

Global Justice and Two Kinds of Liberalism

CONTEXTUALISM AND GLOBAL JUSTICE

Phil 115, June 13, 2007 The argument from the original position: set-up and intuitive presentation and the two principles over average utility

ABSTRACT. Electronic copy available at:

MAJORITARIAN DEMOCRACY

Legal Reasoning, the Rule of Law, and Legal Theory: Comments on Gerald Postema, Positivism and the Separation of the Realists from their Skepticism

Plato s Concept of Justice: Prepared by, Mr. Thomas G.M., Associate Professor, Pompei College Aikala DK

Cover Page. The handle holds various files of this Leiden University dissertation.

Do we have a strong case for open borders?

Theory Comprehensive January 2015

Can asylum seekers appeal to their human rights as a form of nonviolent

Controversy Liberalism, Democracy and the Ethics of Votingponl_

Theorizing Diversity POL 509. Course Syllabus Graduate Seminar, Department of Politics. Professor Alan Patten Fall 2010

Response to Robert P. George, Natural Law, the Constitution, and the Theory and Practice of Judicial Review

Liberalism and the Politics of Legalizing Unauthorized Migrants

WHY NOT BASE FREE SPEECH ON AUTONOMY OR DEMOCRACY?

Where does Confucian Virtuous Leadership Stand? A Critique of Daniel Bell s Beyond Liberal Democracy

Western Philosophy of Social Science

PUBLIC POLICY RESEARCH PAPER SERIES

Freedom in a Democratic Society

Themes and Scope of this Book

Second Edition. Political Theory. Ideas and Concepts. Sushila Ramaswamy

J É R Ô M E G R A N D U N I V E R S I T Y O F G E N E V A. T e a c h i n g a s s i s t a n t a n d p h d s t u d e n t

Samaritanism and Political Obligation: A Response to Christopher Wellman s Liberal Theory of Political Obligation *

John Rawls. Cambridge University Press John Rawls: An Introduction Percy B. Lehning Frontmatter More information

Towards a Global Civil Society. Daniel Little University of Michigan-Dearborn

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

ELIMINATING CORRECTIVE JUSTICE. Steven Walt *

A Civil Religion. Copyright Maurice Bisheff, Ph.D.

Exam Questions By Year IR 214. How important was soft power in ending the Cold War?

1) Is the "Clash of Civilizations" too broad of a conceptualization to be of use? Why or why not?

Criminal Justice Without Moral Responsibility: Addressing Problems with Consequentialism Dane Shade Hannum

The Debate of Immigration: Democracy, Autonomy, and Coercion

Preface Is there a place for the nation in democratic theory? Frontiers are the sine qua non of the emergence of the people ; without them, the whole

Political Liberalism and Its Feminist Potential. Elizabeth Edenberg

Immigration. Our individual rights are (in general) much more secure and better protected

2 POLITICAL THEORY / month 2004

Genuine Electoral Democracy and Human Rights. S. Wang (CityU)

Considering a Human Right to Democracy

Rawls, Reasonableness, and International Toleration

Justifying Punishment: A Response to Douglas Husak

Introduction. Cambridge University Press Rawls's Egalitarianism Alexander Kaufman Excerpt More Information

Jus in Bello through the Lens of Individual Moral Responsibility: McMahan on Killing in War

Social Practices, Public Health and the Twin Aims of Justice: Responses to Comments

POL 343 Democratic Theory and Globalization February 11, "The history of democratic theory II" Introduction

Transcription:

Saving a Bad Marriage: Political Liberalism and the Natural Law J. Daryl Charles Natural Law Liberalism by Christopher Wolfe (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2006) The author of this important volume writes with the awareness that political liberals and natural law theorists seem highly unlikely bedfellows. The former, tracing their roots to Hobbes, Locke and Mill, are by nature skeptical of the possibility of both recognizing and agreeing on a range of objective human goods. As a result, the essence of political life for them is to defend the rights of individuals to pursue their own ideas of the good. Proponents of natural law, by contrast, proceed on the assumption that human beings indeed can J. DARYL CHARLES is a Senior Fellow at the Center for Politics and Religion at Union University in Jackson, TN and the Director and a Senior Fellow of the Bryan Institute for Critical Thought and Practice at Bryan College in Dayton, TN. recognize objective human goods and that these goods constitute a moral fund that must regulate civil society. Christopher Wolfe believes that both positions can be wed to the extent that this marriage is based on shared conviction and a complementarity of perspective. While the differences between the two may breed certain tensions, the marriage nevertheless holds great promise. The nature of this wedding, of course, is not without its difficulties, as the political narrative of the last 250 years indicates well. During this period, natural law and political liberalism appeared to grow distant, skeptical of one another, and in the end incompatible. But, Wolfe reminds us, the two were originally married in the classical liberal political philosophy of John Locke. It is high time, then, that the 71

MODERN AGE two partners be reconciled, particularly given the crisis of liberalism in our own day a crisis that, in Wolfe s view, is fundamentally intellectual and moral in nature. Unquestionably, liberal democracy offers people a measure of freedom, fulfillment and well-being that no other form of government would appear capable of producing. At the same time, it is foremost procedural in character and cannot in and of itself renew or replenish the character of its practitioners and beneficiaries. The very goods that democratic liberalism claims to foster for example, liberty, equality, and tolerance become shibboleths at best and vices at worst when they are emptied of their moral content. When basic human goods requisite to civil society for example, truth, piety, justice, neighbor-love, and self-sacrifice are neglected, no form of government will be sufficient to the task. Wolfe is acutely aware that for the last three centuries political liberalism and natural-law theory have been perceived as opponents, even enemies. But this perception, in his view, is rooted in a mistaken understanding of each by the other. To facilitate a reunion of the two traditions, Wolfe contends that both are in need of moderation. Liberalism must be moderated in such a way as to be compatible with important intellectual and moral goods, with faith and reason, and with the moral virtues that regulate the passions and promote individual and social well-being. At the same time, classical natural-law theory needs to be separated from its original historical, political, and social context, purified of elements that are inconsistent with its most important principles, and adapted to modern circumstances. The initial task, as Wolfe sees it, is to identify key inadequacies of contemporary liberalism as advanced by its chief theoreticians. This undertaking constitutes Part One of the volume. Part Two, then, is devoted to exploring how political liberalism and natural law theory intersect and interact. Such requires a thorough examination of basic definitions, operating assumptions, goals and vision, not least of which is identifying precisely what human and moral goods are to be pursued and preserved. Only then can a viable public philosophy be propounded. For Wolfe, the inability of liberalism s major theorists to establish a plausible doctrine of public reason and liberal autonomy should raise serious questions and cause us to explore alternative explanations. The lack of plausibility is exemplified in the work of the late John Rawls, arguably liberalism s most influential exponent, as expressed in A Theory of Justice (1971) 1 and Political Liberalism (1992). 2 Rawls s invention was to claim a certain neutrality with regard to basic comprehensive views of polity. However, on Wolfe s account, Rawls was unable to vindicate this claim. The reason for this is that Rawls s political liberalism excludes traditional religious and moral views that qualify as comprehensive. The first principles of political liberalism are thought by Rawls to be constitutive of our political culture among these, the freedom and equality of citizens and fair terms of social cooperation. Justice as fairness, in Rawlsian thought, embodies a baseline conception of the good. But how does society arrive at what is just, particularly when any number of comprehensive views might clash in the wider culture? Rawls s answer is an appeal to public reason. Political liberalism assumes the fact of a pluralism of comprehensive frameworks, whether they are religious or non-religious, wherein reasonable people cooperate along the lines of a just society. Because Rawls has few rivals in shaping late-twentieth-century political theory, 72

WINTER 2010 the weaknesses in his system are worthy of attention. Supremely problematic, for Wolfe, is the internal inadequacy of Rawls s notion of public reason. It matters very much to Rawls that political liberalism be neutral with respect to the philosophical question of what society should tolerate, what behavior should be discouraged, and why reasonable people should cooperate. But Rawls refuses to acknowledge the illusory character of a liberal neutrality. Wolfe rightly observes that both our definition of tolerance and the particular form of tolerance are decisive in the recognition of political rights and individual autonomy. According to one notion of tolerance, ideas should not be suppressed by force. A second understanding holds that persons have an inherent right to believe what they want about the human good. The problem with the second is that it easily fades into a subjectivism that undermines the common good. But political liberalism chafes under the idea that, according to religious or moral truths, some things are inherently wrong. What matters, then, is not whether something is true or false or right or wrong, but rather whether members of society cooperate with one another. Public reason, according to Rawls, is the supra-moral agency that permits reasonable people to achieve social cooperation, whereas comprehensive views only tend to divide. A further criticism leveled by Wolfe against Rawls s political philosophy is that it is powerless to address at both the theoretical and practical level the totalitarian temptation. How do relatively free societies evolve into totalitarian regimes, and what is to prevent this tendency? Similarly, in Liberal Virtues 3 Stephen Macedo argues that liberalism is constituted by principles of justice that are impartial. This requires an environment of pluralism in which arguments can be publicly stated, debated, and accepted. Logically, this means that those arguments cannot be private, complex, or of a nature that is rejected by otherwise reasonable people. And religious belief, because it is viewed by Macedo as a private phenomenon, is automatically disqualified from the realm of public reason. Wolfe finds weaknesses in Macedo s argument akin to that of Rawls. Macedo s position, which rejects natural-law reasoning, is unable to proffer an argument against, say, slavery or abortion. Historically, both issues have been divisive, and opposition to both at any given point might be viewed as a minority position. And on neither issue is it possible let alone plausible to achieve a reasonable middle ground. Macedo s assumption that religion is private is equally problematic for Wolfe, since religion claims to be both rational and public in its manifestation. In the end, liberal public reason is not a plausible doctrine. Its assumptions are philosophically flawed, it measures are unclear, and its program is susceptible to partisan manipulation. Another form of excluding moral argument from public debate is found in Amy Gutmann and Dennis Thompson s Democracy and Disagreement. 4 One of the requirements for democratic deliberation, according to Gutmann and Thompson, is the principle of reciprocity: that is, the capacity to seek mutually fair terms of social cooperation. This means, theoretically, that each citizen must offer reasons in public argument that are acceptable to others, which in turn depends on their commonality and their verifiability. Such, of course, would exclude claims made by religious fundamentalists. But the argument from reciprocity, too, suffers from the illusion of objective neutrality. Moreover, morality is ultimately not necessarily empirically verifiable, nor will it necessarily be shared by most citizens. Indeed, people can find public justifi- 73

MODERN AGE cation for what they wish rather than what is right. Wolfe, quite properly, suggests broadening Gutmann and Thompson s definition of reciprocity so that it asks people to direct reasonable arguments to their opponents with reason being defined broadly, not in Rawlsian terms and to be willing to listen and respond to their arguments with civility. For Wolfe, the problem with the Gutmann-Thompson thesis, as with Rawls and Macedo, is that public argument can rule out of order direct appeals to many people s deepest moral and religious convictions in political discourse and decision making. Central to most conceptions of contemporary liberalism is the notion of autonomy. The state s purported neutrality is typically thought to maximize the autonomy of individual citizens, and hence, their freedom to choose whatever lifestyle they wish. Such, therefore, invites a critique of Ronald Dworkin, whose work in Taking Rights Seriously 5 and Sovereign Virtue: The Theory and Practice of Equality 6 exemplifies for Wolfe the contemporary purification of paternalistic aspects of classical political thought. This unenlightened paternalism, which for Dworkin must be rejected, manifests itself in a variety of ways but errs fundamentally in assuming that some objective standard of the good life might transcend any circumstances in which people find themselves. In Wolfe s view, Dworkin ultimately errs in assuming that no transcendent ethical standards exist whereby human behavior is to be evaluated. Wolfe is cognizant of the fact that all people draw the ethical line between acceptable and unacceptable; the difference is where that line is drawn. In the end, the goal of paternalism properly construed, according to Wolfe, is to facilitate free choice of the good, not merely to constrain people externally. This, of course, presupposes that a shared notion of the common good exists. In this vein, Wolfe believes that Joseph Raz s appraisal of moral paternalism also needs comment. What distinguishes Raz from most liberals is that he does not assert autonomy as an unqualifi ed good. What Raz in principle opposes is the idea that, as long as other people are not directly harmed by an individual s behavior, government should coercively restrain personal autonomy. Not surprisingly, the test-case for Raz is how society responds to homosexuality. Raz worries that homosexuals do not enjoy full citizenship when they face public and private discrimination, resulting in homophobic prejudice. Here, as Wolfe correctly perceives, two clarifications are necessary: an alternative defi nition of coercion and the rationale for government s preserving the common good. So, for example, a person deprived of the opportunity to murder has not lost autonomy ; nor can coercion be thought the equivalent of being manipulated. Rather, intention and the common good must inform a society s understanding of coercive restraint. Thus, in restricting homosexual acts via public policy society gives tangible expression to its commitment to uphold the well-being of all citizens. To the extent that Raz is preoccupied with forms of bigotry, Wolfe believes that his understanding of liberalism may be an invitation to a form of liberal tyranny. For on Raz s account, parents and public schools and civic organizations all must tolerate homosexuality; to do otherwise would be intolerable. In the end, Raz s attempt to delegitimize discrimination on grounds of sexual orientation, without recourse to assumptions about the moral rightness or wrongness of related acts, is for Wolfe a failure. Having assessed the contours of contemporary liberalism, Wolfe seeks to broaden the definition of liberalism as a tradition of political thought extending over 74

WINTER 2010 centuries. Liberalism, he maintains, is no single, seamless political philosophy. Yet, it is characterized by several defining features among these, the notion of human dignity and equality, political rule by consent, the protection of rights, limited government, and the rule of law. These core values, alas, happen to correspond with the natural-law and Christian moral tradition. Following a brief history of the naturallaw tradition that extends from Aristotelian thought through Stoicism to Augustinian and Thomistic thought, Wolfe identifies several core elements objective value, human nature, the natural order of ends, and human flourishing that inhere in natural-law thinking. These combine with the common ground shared with classical liberalism human dignity, consent, the centrality of rights, limited government, and rule of law to maintain and fortify civil society. Where the natural-law tradition serves as a corrective to contemporary liberalism is its moral realism (over against the latter s optimism), its reversing of the priority of freedom over truth, its openness to (rather than rejection of) revealed religion, and its concern to protect the family as a social unit. But how does natural law liberalism cash out? A useful test-case, in Wolfe s view, is its approach to religious liberty, since it is thought to protect a broad form of religious liberty while maintaining a firm belief in the existence and intelligibility of religious truth. Undergirding Wolfe s overall thesis is the presupposition that reason has an important role to play in claims to divine revelation. Hence, religion cannot merely be relegated to the private sphere, for to inquire about the meaning of life, about human nature, and about human goods is very much a public matter. After all, social policy proceeds on certain assumptions about each of these questions. What is distinctive about natural-law reasoning is that it seeks to preserve the common good, whereby both the individual and the community are safeguarded. Ultimately, in Wolfe s view, natural law liberalism is more respectful of the social nature of human beings as well as the importance of the moral ecology affecting their development. While attendant to the strengths of liberalism for example, equality and human rights it helps alleviates contemporary liberalism s problematic tendencies, which tend to truncate the intellectual and moral underpinnings of the very tradition from which it springs. Doubtless some readers will initially come to this volume somewhat skeptical of the wedding being proposed by the author. A fair reading of Wolfe s argument, however, should convince the reader not only of the plausibility of his thesis but of the necessity of the marriage. For if we assume as our basis, with Wolfe, the classical liberal political philosophy of Locke rather than contemporary versions thereof which have jettisoned the intellectual and moral underpinnings of the broader tradition that birthed them, we indeed discover common ground with the natural-law tradition that is necessary to safeguard civil society. And in the post-consensus cultural climate pervading the West, this wedding needs to occur sooner rather than later. 1 A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1971). 2 Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1993). 3 Liberal Virtues (Oxford: Clarendon, 1990); cf. also Diversity and Distrust (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2000). 4 Democracy and Disagreement (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1996). 5 Taking Rights Seriously (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1977). 6 Sovereign Virtue: The Theory and Practice of Equality (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2000). 75