Comments on Justin Weinberg s Is Government Supererogation Possible? Public Reason Political Philosophy Symposium Friday October 17, 2008

Similar documents
Rawls versus the Anarchist: Justice and Legitimacy

Two Pictures of the Global-justice Debate: A Reply to Tan*

Global Justice and Two Kinds of Liberalism

Criminal Justice Without Moral Responsibility: Addressing Problems with Consequentialism Dane Shade Hannum

INTERGENERATIONAL JUSTICE AND COERCION AS A GROUND OF JUSTICE

Political Norms and Moral Values

Introduction 478 U.S. 186 (1986) U.S. 558 (2003). 3

Pos 500 Seminar in Political Theory: Political Theory and Equality Peter Breiner

PubPol Values, Ethics, and Public Policy, Fall 2009

POLI 219: Global Equality, For and Against Fall 2013

Ethics Handout 18 Rawls, Classical Utilitarianism and Nagel, Equality

Any non-welfarist method of policy assessment violates the Pareto principle: A comment

Civic Republicanism and Social Justice

The Veil of Ignorance in Rawlsian Theory

PHI 1700: Global Ethics

POLITICAL AUTHORITY AND PERFECTIONISM: A RESPONSE TO QUONG

Definition: Property rights in oneself comparable to property rights in inanimate things

A Response to Tan. Christian Schemmel. University of Frankfurt; Forthcoming in The Journal of Philosophy

Institutional Cosmopolitanism and the Duties that Human. Rights Impose on Individuals

Utilitarianism. Utilitarianism. Dr. Clea F. Rees. Centre for Lifelong Learning Cardiff University.

Justice and collective responsibility. Zoltan Miklosi. regardless of the institutional or other relations that may obtain among them.

Equality, Justice and Legitimacy in Selection 1. (This is the pre-proof draft of the article, which was published in the

Four theories of justice

-Capitalism, Exploitation and Injustice-

Incentives and the Natural Duties of Justice

Part III Immigration Policy: Introduction

CHAPTER 4, On Liberty. Does Mill Qualify the Liberty Principle to Death? Dick Arneson For PHILOSOPHY 166 FALL, 2006

Political Authority and Distributive Justice

Utilitarianism. Utilitarianism. Dr. Clea F. Rees. Centre for Lifelong Learning Cardiff University.

Deliberation and Democratic Legitimacy I

Commentary on Idil Boran, The Problem of Exogeneity in Debates on Global Justice

S.L. Hurley, Justice, Luck and Knowledge, (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2003), 341 pages. ISBN: (hbk.).

Do we have a strong case for open borders?

Part III Immigration Policy: Introduction

Postscript: Subjective Utilitarianism

24.03: Good Food 3/13/17. Justice and Food Production

Assignment to make up for missed class on August 29, 2011 due to Irene

The problem of global distributive justice in Rawls s The Law of Peoples

Proceduralism and Epistemic Value of Democracy

DEMOCRACY AND EQUALITY

Comment on Baker's Autonomy and Free Speech

The Injustice of Affirmative Action: A. Dworkian Perspective

RESPONSE TO JAMES GORDLEY'S "GOOD FAITH IN CONTRACT LAW: The Problem of Profit Maximization"

Entry by Birth Alone?: Rawlsian Egalitarianism and the Basic Right to Invite

Immigration and Libertarianism: Open Borders versus Directionalism 1

HUMAN RIGHTS AS POLITICAL DEMAND

A political theory of territory

Ethical Basis of Welfare Economics. Ethics typically deals with questions of how should we act?

Politics between Philosophy and Democracy

CONTEXTUALISM AND GLOBAL JUSTICE

Libertarianism Against the Welfare State: A Refresher. Bryan Caplan Dep t of Economics and Mercatus Center George Mason University

Theories of Justice to Health Care

Pogge -vs- Sen on Global Poverty and Human Rights 1

The limits of background justice. Thomas Porter. Rawls says that the primary subject of justice is what he calls the basic structure of

POL 10a: Introduction to Political Theory Spring 2017 Room: Golding 101 T, Th 2:00 3:20 PM

Review Article: International Distributive Justice. Dr Simon Caney Department of Politics University of Newcastle Newcastle upon Tyne NE1 7RU U.K.

Review of Mathias Risse, On Global Justice Princeton University Press, 2012, Reviewed by Christian Barry, Australian National University

Rawls, Reasonableness, and International Toleration

Global Justice. Mondays Office Hours: Seigle 282 2:00 5:00 pm Mondays and Wednesdays

ELIMINATING CORRECTIVE JUSTICE. Steven Walt *

Phil 116, April 5, 7, and 9 Nozick, Anarchy, State, and Utopia

Theories of Social Justice

4AANB006 Political Philosophy I Syllabus Academic year

Do we have a moral obligation to the homeless?

Between Equality and Freedom of Choice: Educational Policy for the Least Advantaged

Cambridge University Press The Cambridge Rawls Lexicon Edited by Jon Mandle and David A. Reidy Excerpt More information

What is the Relationship Between The Idea of the Minimum and Distributive Justice?

1100 Ethics July 2016

The Conflict between Notions of Fairness and the Pareto Principle

LIBERAL EQUALITY, FAIR COOPERATION AND GENETIC ENHANCEMENT

Where does Confucian Virtuous Leadership Stand? A Critique of Daniel Bell s Beyond Liberal Democracy

Normative Frameworks 1 / 35

Is Rawls s Difference Principle Preferable to Luck Egalitarianism?

Last time we discussed a stylized version of the realist view of global society.

Chapter Two: Normative Theories of Ethics

Multiculturalism and liberal democracy

Comments on Schnapper and Banting & Kymlicka

Equality of Opportunity: A Normative Anatomy 1. T. M. Scanlon

Is Patriotism Immoral?

Handout 6: Utilitarianism

Is there a genuine tension between cosmopolitan egalitarianism and special responsibilities?

Libertarianism. Polycarp Ikuenobe A N I NTRODUCTION

John Rawls's Difference Principle and The Strains of Commitment: A Diagrammatic Exposition

The Debate of Immigration: Democracy, Autonomy, and Coercion

Equality and Division: Values in Principle 1

(Draft paper please let me know if you want to circulate or quote)

Immigration and freedom of movement

Book Reviews. Julian Culp, Global Justice and Development, Palgrave Macmillan, Basingstoke, UK, 2014, Pp. xi+215, ISBN:

Democracy and Common Valuations

Choice-Based Libertarianism. Like possessive libertarianism, choice-based libertarianism affirms a basic

Playing Fair and Following the Rules

Law & Ethics of Human Rights

Political Obligation 3

Distributive vs. Corrective Justice

Co-national Obligations & Cosmopolitan Obligations towards Foreigners

A pluralistic approach to global poverty

INSTITUTIONAL ISSUES INVOLVING ETHICS AND JUSTICE Vol.I - Economic Justice - Hon-Lam Li

Philosophy and Public Affairs, Vol. 30, No. 3. (Summer, 2001), pp

Utilitarianism. John Stuart Mill

SPECIAL ISSUE ON TRANSITIONAL JUSTICE

Transcription:

Helena de Bres Wellesley College Department of Philosophy hdebres@wellesley.edu Comments on Justin Weinberg s Is Government Supererogation Possible? Public Reason Political Philosophy Symposium Friday October 17, 2008 Government Supererogation: Weinberg s Dilemma Many of us think that governments sometimes perform acts that, although not required by justice, are nonetheless morally good. The U.S. government funds pyrotechnic displays on the Fourth of July, for instance, that, while not plausibly required by justice in any of its distributive, criminal or compensatory aspects, make the patriot s heart soar and delight many small children. In his paper, Justin Weinberg places pressure on those of us who think that governmental action is, or can be, supererogatory in this way. The argument (in outline, and sticking with my example) goes like this: 1. Supererogatory actions are neither required by justice nor morally wrong. 2. Government action is coercive. (Government-supplied Fourth of July fireworks, for instance, are funded by your taxes). 3. The only legitimate justification for government coercion is that it is required by 4. Government-supplied Fourth of July fireworks are either required by justice or they are not. 5. Dilemma: 5.a. Government-supplied Fourth of July fireworks are not plausibly required by Instead they seem supererogatory (i.e. in the optional extra credit compartment of the government s moral report card). 5.b. But if government-supplied fireworks are not required by justice, they cannot be supererogatory. Because government coercion to supply the fireworks will in this case be illegitimate (3), government provision of them must be morally wrong, and hence non-supererogatory (1). 6. Government-supplied Fourth of July fireworks are not supererogatory (1,5) 7. This conclusion generalizes: Government supererogation is impossible. 1 The goal of Weinberg s paper is to spell out the argument summarized here more precisely, and to consider whether or not there is an acceptable way to escape its 1 Weinberg s own, much more precise and general, presentation of the argument can be found at his p.5, and, in a revised version, p.9.

conclusion. He concludes that there isn t, and that our impression that governments can perform supererogatory actions is therefore mistaken. This is a well argued and exceptionally clear paper on an original and interesting problem. I very much enjoyed reading it. That said, I am not persuaded by Weinberg s conclusion. Justice and Coercion Weinberg is interested not in the more traditional general question of whether supererogation is ever possible (he assumes that it is), but rather whether it is possible for governments in particular to perform supererogatory acts. The reason that Weinberg assumes that governments have a special problem here derives from his twin assumptions that governmental action is (if not necessarily, at least actually) coercive, and that coercion can only ever be justified on grounds of justice (premises 2 and 3 above). It follows from the conjunction of these two assumptions that governments are never off the justice hook, so to speak. Everything they do must have a legitimate justice-based rationale, or else the coercion involved in the action at issue will be illegitimate. As a result, the optional extra credit portion of a government s moral report card has the unfortunate feature that, as soon as anything gets placed in it, that thing is automatically transferred either to the requirements fulfilled or infractions portion instead. One obvious way to solve this problem is to reject the second of Weinberg s twin assumptions (I take it that the first is unexceptionable). Why, that is, might not government coercion be legitimately justified on grounds other than justice? Take the following justifications as potential candidates: 1. Humanitarianism. Consider the following combination of views: - We have duties to relieve the suffering of the global poor (at the very least, that of those who are poor through no fault of their own). - These duties are not duties of justice they are neither a matter of respecting the negative pre-political rights of the poor, nor a matter of global distributive fairness. - It is morally appropriate for the governments of rich countries to (coercively) tax their citizens to provide resources for humanitarian purposes overseas. Although these claims can be denied (libertarians reject the third, cosmopolitan egalitarians such as Charles Beitz (1979) and Thomas Pogge (1989) the second), I take it that considerable numbers of us actually accept all three. If this is so, we are committed to a form of legitimate government coercion that is not based on 2. Cultural / aesthetic / intellectual / environmental goods. Most of us feel that our lives are made richer by access to such goods as beauty, knowledge, or participation in local traditions. There are often collective action problems involved in supplying such goods. Due to their impressive powers of coordination and, yes, coercion, governments are in some cases able to supply these goods more

effectively than private actors. If we value these goods, we may well think that government action to supply them is justified, even though not required by 3. Solidarity. There are arguably certain goods that, although they may not be uniquely or most efficiently supplied by the government, gain value from the very fact that they are so supplied. Take Fourth of July fireworks, for instance. There may be private fireworks displays that are a great deal more spectacular and better put together than the public versions. But the fact that the public fireworks are public - that they are an expression of the body politic, coming together to celebrate itself and its achievements provides an extra special good (call it solidarity, or a sense of national unity) that is lacking in the private version. 2 Because this special kind of good can only be provided by government coercion, if we value it we might again think that the accompanying coercion is justified, even though not by I find myself sympathetic to each of these suggestions. Of course, coercion is never a morally light matter, and not just any old justification of it will do. Perhaps beyond a certain degree of expense, and in the presence of widespread disinterest in or hostility to the action at issue, governmental actions aimed at the above goals will be illegitimate. But, in the absence of such worries, and if the gains to be had are significant, why not consider coercive actions with the above sorts of justifications legitimate? If we do take this line, a government might sometimes permissibly act in ways not required by justice, thereby leaving room for supererogation. Weinberg gives two reasons in support of the assumption I am here rejecting, i.e. the claim that: 3. The only legitimate justification for government coercion is that it is required by The first appeals to philosophical tradition. We are told, for instance, that [p]olitical philosophers, such as Rawls, have considered the point of theories of justice to delimit the proper scope of government coercion. 3 The second reason appeals to a conceptual claim about the nature of (the domain) of Citing Mill and Kant, Weinberg notes that Justice has often been used to distinguish that part of morality which may coercively be enforced. 4 2 I suggest this as someone who is both queasy about patriotism and indifferent to fireworks, but the underlying idea seems to me to be right. 3 See also the claim that Traditionally, government coercion is justified only on the basis that it is necessary for justice (7), and the reference to the widely held view that the formal content of political justice is the grounds for legitimate government coercion (19). 4 See footnotes 6 and 15. I take it the relevant quote from Mill is this one: When we think that a person is bound in justice to do a thing, it is an ordinary form of language to say, that he ought to be compelled to do it. We should be gratified to see the obligation enforced by anybody who had the power (1863)

I find neither of these reasons persuasive. As for the first, while it may be true, as Weinberg notes, that Rawls sees his theory as answering the question in light of what kind of conception of justice can citizens legitimately exercise coercive power over one another? 5, it is a distinct claim that only reasons of justice can provide the relevant justification. I m not persuaded that Rawls is committed to the latter, in my view much more controversial, claim. As for the second reason, the Millian/Kantian claim that: 8. Duties of justice are all and only those that are permissibly enforceable 6 is not very plausible. Not only is it a standard tenet of ordinary moral thought that not all putative duties of justice are appropriately coercively enforced, including many of those that arise in the course of personal relations. But it is at least not obvious that non-justice duties do not themselves constitute appropriate grounds for coercion. To refer to the earlier example once again, Brian Barry has claimed, for instance, that our humanitarian duty to relieve the distress of the global poor is an obligation that it would be wrong not to carry out and that could quite properly be enforced upon rich countries if the world political system made this feasible (1993). Adam Smith similarly argued for the legitimacy of using state power to impose duties of beneficence within domestic societies (Fleischacker 2005, 26-7). 7 Weinberg is right that if we reject 3. and 8. we would need a new way to conceive of the subject matter of And more importantly, we would need an account of what, if not justice, sets limits to the exercise of government coercion. But, given the unsuitability of the current candidates, I don t find this implication too worrying. Consequentialism and Supererogation Although there is much else in Weinberg s paper that is interesting and worthy of comment, I will halt with the above, which gives my reasons for rejecting his conclusion that government supererogation is impossible. As an addendum, however, I can t resist correcting what I take to be a misrepresentation of consequentialist theories of justice near the end of Weinberg s paper. He writes: Note that if our theory of justice is consequentialist, government supererogation faces a different dilemma. If the apparently supererogatory acts maximize the good, then they are not supererogatory; rather, they are required. Yet earlier we noted the implausibility of 5 Rawls, Justice as Fairness (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2001), p.41. 6 I interpret this claim in Arneson s sense that it is generally morally permissible, and may be morally required, to use physical force and violence and the threat of these evils to coerce people into compliance with the duty. 7 Mill himself dismissed the permissibility of enforcement criterion shortly after proposing it, on the rather different ground that it is a part of the notion of Duty in every one of its forms (i.e. not only in the form of duties of justice) that a person may rightfully be compelled to fulfill it. Duty is a thing which may be exacted from a person, as one exacts a debt (1863). This is a rather hard line to take, and, on the face of it, implausible. Mill is able to endorse it only by opting for a very generous notion of what it is to enforce a duty (he includes within that notion punishment of a man by the opinion of his fellow-creatures; if not by opinion, by the reproaches of his own conscience ).

thinking that, say, celebrations are required by If, on the other hand, the acts don t maximize the good, they are wrong. But of course that doesn t fit with the general attitude of approval towards these acts. (20) The problem pointed to here only arises if we have a simple one-level version of act consequentialism in mind. If we adopt a more sophisticated two-level theory, it disappears. This is because there is ample room for an indirect consequentialist to build into her set of secondary principles a distinction between stringently required acts and good-but-merely-optional ones. There are good consequentialist reasons, for instance, for our moral code to reflect the idea that governments should focus their efforts primarily on (e.g.) poverty programs rather than fireworks, even if the best outcome would be poverty programs and fireworks. Given that consequentialists can also be expected to have more sympathy than non-consequentialists with my earlier arguments about non-justice based justifications for government coercion, Weinberg might have here identified a hitherto unrecognized area where consequentialists have the upper hand. References Brian Barry, Humanity and Justice in Global Perspective, in J. Pennock and J. Chapman, eds., NOMOS XXIV, Ethics, Economics and the Law (New York: Harvester Wheatsheaf, 1982) Charles Beitz, Political Theory and International Relations ((Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1979) Samuel Fleischacker, A Short History of Distributive Justice (Harvard University Press, 2004) J.S. Mill, Utilitarianism (1863) Thomas Pogge, Realizing Rawls (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1989)