RAWLS DIFFERENCE PRINCIPLE: ABSOLUTE vs. RELATIVE INEQUALITY

Similar documents
AN EGALITARIAN THEORY OF JUSTICE 1

John Rawls THEORY OF JUSTICE

Ethics Handout 18 Rawls, Classical Utilitarianism and Nagel, Equality

Phil 115, June 13, 2007 The argument from the original position: set-up and intuitive presentation and the two principles over average utility

VALUING DISTRIBUTIVE EQUALITY CLAIRE ANITA BREMNER. A thesis submitted to the Department of Philosophy. in conformity with the requirements for

Philosophy 285 Fall, 2007 Dick Arneson Overview of John Rawls, A Theory of Justice. Views of Rawls s achievement:

John Rawls's Difference Principle and The Strains of Commitment: A Diagrammatic Exposition

At a time when political philosophy seemed nearly stagnant, John Rawls

Definition: Institution public system of rules which defines offices and positions with their rights and duties, powers and immunities p.

Phil 115, May 24, 2007 The threat of utilitarianism

Great comments! (A lot of them could be germs of term papers )

Distributive Justice Rawls

1 Justice as fairness, utilitarianism, and mixed conceptions

Distributive Justice Rawls

Reconciling Educational Adequacy and Equity Arguments Through a Rawlsian Lens

The limits of background justice. Thomas Porter. Rawls says that the primary subject of justice is what he calls the basic structure of

Why Rawls's Domestic Theory of Justice is Implausible

Economic Perspective. Macroeconomics I ECON 309 S. Cunningham

The limits of background justice. Thomas Porter. Social Philosophy & Policy volume 30, issues 1 2. Cambridge University Press

VI. Rawls and Equality

ANALOGICAL ARGUMENTS FOR EGALITARIANISM. Ratio 27 (2014): Christopher Freiman College of William and Mary Department of Philosophy

Matthew Adler, a law professor at the Duke University, has written an amazing book in defense

Rawls and Natural Aristocracy

Empirical Research on Economic Inequality Why study inequality?

UTILITARIANISM AND POPULATION ETHICS

Justifying Punishment: A Response to Douglas Husak

RECONCILING LIBERTY AND EQUALITY: JUSTICE AS FAIRNESS. John Rawls s A Theory of Justice presents a theory called justice as fairness.

Aggregation and the Separateness of Persons

Why Does Inequality Matter? T. M. Scanlon. Chapter 8: Unequal Outcomes. It is well known that there has been an enormous increase in inequality in the

Rawls on International Justice

Normative Frameworks 1 / 35

PPE 160 Fall Overview

John Rawls, Socialist?

S.L. Hurley, Justice, Luck and Knowledge, (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2003), 341 pages. ISBN: (hbk.).

Rawls versus the Anarchist: Justice and Legitimacy

-Capitalism, Exploitation and Injustice-

MAXIMIZING THE MINIMAL STATE: TOWARD JUSTICE THROUGH RAWLSIAN-NOZICKIAN COMPATIBILITY. Timothy Betts. Submitted in partial fulfillment of the

John Rawls. Cambridge University Press John Rawls: An Introduction Percy B. Lehning Frontmatter More information

Is Rawls s Difference Principle Preferable to Luck Egalitarianism?

Criminal Justice Without Moral Responsibility: Addressing Problems with Consequentialism Dane Shade Hannum

Economic philosophy of Amartya Sen Social choice as public reasoning and the capability approach. Reiko Gotoh

LIBERAL EQUALITY, FAIR COOPERATION AND GENETIC ENHANCEMENT

Deliberation and Democratic Legitimacy I

The Veil of Ignorance in Rawlsian Theory

Rawls and Feminism. Hannah Hanshaw. Philosophy. Faculty Advisor: Dr. Jacob Held

Social Contract Theory

24.03: Good Food 3/13/17. Justice and Food Production

Last time we discussed a stylized version of the realist view of global society.

JUSTICE, NON-VIOLENCE, AND THE PRACTICE OF POLITICAL JUDGMENT: A STUDY OF RICOEUR S CONCEPTION OF JUSTICE YANG-SOO LEE

Chapter Two: Normative Theories of Ethics

In Defense of Liberal Equality

Utilitarianism, Game Theory and the Social Contract

Rawls s problem of securing political liberties within the international institutions

When Does Equality Matter? T. M. Scanlon. Lecture 1: Introduction. Our country, and the world, are marked by extraordinarily high levels of

1100 Ethics July 2016

Between Equality and Freedom of Choice: Educational Policy for the Least Advantaged

The Conflict between Notions of Fairness and the Pareto Principle

Cambridge University Press The Cambridge Rawls Lexicon Edited by Jon Mandle and David A. Reidy Excerpt More information

Poverty--absolute and relative Inequalities of income and wealth

Civic Republicanism and Social Justice

Educational Adequacy, Educational Equality, and Ideal Theory. Jaime Ahlberg. University of Wisconsin Madison

CONTEXTUALISM AND GLOBAL JUSTICE

WHEN IS THE PREPONDERANCE OF THE EVIDENCE STANDARD OPTIMAL?

The Social Choice Theory: Can it be considered a Complete Political Theory?

ATINER's Conference Paper Series LAW

A Rawlsian Perspective on Justice for the Disabled

Democracy As Equality

DEMOCRACY AND EQUALITY

TAKING SELF-REALIZATION SERIOUSLY

INSTITUTIONAL ISSUES INVOLVING ETHICS AND JUSTICE Vol.I - Economic Justice - Hon-Lam Li

Princeton University Press

WHAT should a theory of justice look like? Any successful answer to this

The Difference Principle in Rawls: Pragmatic or Infertile?

Phil 115, June 20, 2007 Justice as fairness as a political conception: the fact of reasonable pluralism and recasting the ideas of Theory

Any non-welfarist method of policy assessment violates the Pareto principle: A comment

Do not turn over until you are told to do so by the Invigilator.

When users of congested roads may view tolls as unjust

1 Aggregating Preferences

and government interventions, and explain how they represent contrasting political choices

Chapter 6 Online Appendix. general these issues do not cause significant problems for our analysis in this chapter. One

Postscript: Subjective Utilitarianism

Four theories of justice

Part III Immigration Policy: Introduction

Justice as fairness The social contract

Justice, fairness and Equality. foundation and profound influence on the determination and administration of morality. As such,

The Justification of Justice as Fairness: A Two Stage Process

Meena Krishnamurthy a a Assistant Professor, Department of Philosophy, Associate

Justice As Fairness: Political, Not Metaphysical (Excerpts)

Politics between Philosophy and Democracy

Beccaria s Dream On Criminal Law and Nodal Governance. Klaas Rozemond Associate professor of Criminal Law VU University Amsterdam

NTNU, Trondheim Fall 2003

Introduction to Equality and Justice: The Demands of Equality, Peter Vallentyne, ed., Routledge, The Demands of Equality: An Introduction

Economic Growth and the Interests of Future (and Past and Present) Generations: A Comment on Tyler Cowen

Balancing Equality and Liberty in Rawls s Theory of Justice

POS 103, Introduction to Political Theory Peter Breiner

FAIRNESS VERSUS WELFARE. Louis Kaplow & Steven Shavell. Thesis: Policy Analysis Should Be Based Exclusively on Welfare Economics

CHAPTER II. THE PRINCIPLES OF JUSTICE

CHAPTER VI. DUTY AND OBLIGATION

Do we have a moral obligation to the homeless?

John Rawls: anti-foundationalism, deliberative democracy, and cosmopolitanism

Transcription:

RAWLS DIFFERENCE PRINCIPLE: ABSOLUTE vs. RELATIVE INEQUALITY Geoff Briggs PHIL 350/400 // Dr. Ryan Wasserman Spring 2014 June 9 th, 2014 {Word Count: 2711} [1 of 12]

{This page intentionally left blank (except for this notice)} [2 of 12]

RAWLS DIFFERENCE PRINCIPLE: ABSOLUTE vs. RELATIVE INEQUALITY 1. INTRODUCTION In the book A Theory of Justice, John Rawls examines the notion of a just society. More specifically, he develops a conception of justice Justice as Fairness derived from his novel interpretation of the social contract. Central to his account are two lexically-ordered principles of justice by which primary social institutions, or the basic structure of society, are ideally to be organized and regulated. Broadly speaking, the second of Rawls two principles pertains to the distribution of income and wealth, and its formulation is to be understood as an expression of Rawls Difference Principle roughly, the principle that inequality in expectation is permissible only if lowering it would make the [worst-off] class even more worse off. 1 2 I want to suggest that Rawls Difference Principle (DP) entails the following worrisome outcome: Because DP maximizes the absolute level of expectation (and disregards the relative level), it authorizes potentially immense levels of inequality, such that this inequality itself can become a source of social discord and injustice. This paper will ( 2) present Rawls formulation of DP, ( 3) motivate the worrisome outcome entailed by DP, and ( 4) offer a prima facie plausible solution in the form of an addendum to DP. 2. RAWLS DIFFERENCE PRINCIPLE An important motivation for developing the Difference Principle was to overcome what Rawls saw as a major shortcoming of classical Utilitarianism. Rawls noted that [a] striking 1 Rawls (1971), pg. 61. 2 Ibid, pg. 78. [3 of 12]

feature of the Utilitarian view of justice is that it does not matter, except indirectly, how [the] sum of satisfactions is distributed among individuals. 3 In other words, Utilitarianism is merely concerned with maximizing aggregate welfare for a society, and says nothing about the distribution of this welfare amongst individuals. Rawls says that those in the original position the hypothetical rational agents charged with selecting principles of justice, while ignorant of any differentiating characteristics of themselves or others would not opt for Utilitarianism, on the grounds that they would rule out justifying institutions on the grounds that the hardships of some are offset by a greater good in the aggregate. 4 Instead, says Rawls, those in the original position (OP) would opt for something like the Difference Principle, which can be understood as follows: DP: The higher expectations of those better situated are just IFF they work as part of a scheme which improves the expectations of the least advantaged members of society. 5 To see the problem Rawls had with Utilitarianism, and how DP overcomes it, consider the following illustrations (assume these are the only two possible distributions for this society): 100 55 45 5 [Fig. 1] [Fig. 2] The grey bars represent the best-off class, and the black bars represent the worst-off class, 3 Ibid, pg. 26. 4 Ibid, pg. 15. 5 Ibid, pg. 75; see also pg. 83 for the Difference Principle as embedded in the 2 nd Principle of Justice. [4 of 12]

while the width of the bar represents population size, and the height represents level of expectation roughly, the life prospects of realizing rational plans and well-being. 6 In figure 1, the aggregate expectation is 105 units, while in figure 2 the aggregate expectation for society is 100 units. 7 Classical Utilitarianism would select the society in figure 1, because it has a maximized aggregate expectation. But the problem Rawls highlights is that the distribution in figure 1 is such that the best-off are hugely advantaged relative to the worst-off. Meanwhile, though figure 2 has a lower aggregate level of expectation, it has a much more equal distribution amongst the population. Rawls DP would authorize selecting the distribution represented in figure 2, because the additional advantage conferred to the best-off in figure 1 does not improve the expectations of the worst-off; in fact, here, it does just the opposite. And this is precisely the role DP plays in Rawls theory it provides us with a principle by which to select a just arrangement for society by facilitating considerations not only of aggregate expectations, but also the distribution thereof, and helps to avoid situations like that in figure 1. With this brief sketch of DP in hand, we are now situated to understand the worrisome outcome entailed by DP. 3. RELATIVE vs. ABSOLUTE EXPECTATION 3.1. The Worry While DP succeeds in overcoming the distribution problem afflicting classical Utilitarianism, it suffers from its own problem. The problem is that by focusing on the absolute rather than the relative level of expectations of the worst-off, DP authorizes potentially immense levels of inequality, just so long as this inequality results in a higher absolute level of expectation 6 Ibid, see discussion of Expectations on pg. 64, 93. 7 Ibid, pg. 64. The units in figures 1 and 2 are arbitrary; they are for comparison purposes only. [5 of 12]

for the worst-off. 8 And if this inequality between the best-off and worst-off is great enough, it can itself become a source of injustice. To see how this might be so, consider the following illustrations. 75 99 55 45 48 51 [Fig. 3] [Fig. 4] [Fig. 5] In figure 3, there is a relatively equal distribution, but DP sanctions indeed requires the move from this distribution to the one represented in figure 4. 9 Similarly, DP sanctions the move from figure 4 s distribution to that represented in figure 5. For although the relative inequality between the best and worst-off classes increases from fig. 3 to fig. 4, and again from fig. 4 to fig. 5, so too does the absolute level of the worst-off s expectations increase. And it is with this absolute level of expectations that DP is exclusively concerned. This is where the worry about DP arises that at some point the relative level of inequality authorized by DP will be so great as to itself become a source of injustice. 10 8 A related worry is that DP implies that any benefit, no matter how small, to the worst-off will outweigh any loss to [the] better-off ; see Arrow, Kenneth (see references). 9 To understand why DP requires this, consider the negative formulation of DP: Inequality in expectation is unjust unless the worst-off would be even more worse-off without that inequality. So, to move backwards from the situation represented in fig. 4 to fig. 3 would violate DP, because it would leave the worst-off with a lower absolute level of expectations about their life prospects than before. 10 One sense of the phrase at some point might be that there is some absolute value threshold of relative inequality below which DP is just and above which DP is unjust. I would ideally like to avoid taking such a strong (and potentially arbitrary) position. Rather than an absolute point, I would merely suggest that as the relative inequality between best-off and worst-off increases, so too does DP become increasingly unjust. So, perhaps it is better understood as a sort of gradient, rather than a sort of binary (i.e., just/unjust). [6 of 12]

To further illustrate the worry, consider the following example that Lawrence Crocker discusses in his essay Equality, Solidarity, and Rawls MaxiMin : We have a close community in which there are no significant social divisions. Income, wealth, and other advantages are equal to within a few percentages. There is only one way to modify the society to produce a different distribution. On the new distribution, 5 percent of the people would have ten times their previous incomes, and everyone else would have 1 percent more than his or her previous income. It would be nice for the 5 percent to have their incomes increased so dramatically. The 1 percent benefit for the remaining 95 percent of the population seems an advantage so modest as to barely deserve consideration, but it is a slight plus. On the other hand, the enormous inequality which would be introduced by this transition would amount to the division of society into two distinct castes. There would be two castes even if the inequality of wealth did not engender an inequality of political power. 11 So, more perspicuously stated, the worry is that DP s emphasis on the absolute level of expectations entails the possibility of discord, frustration, or relegation to a lower caste for the worst-off as a result of an immensely unequal relative level of expectations. If that s true, and the presence of this discord, frustration, lower status and the like represents a hindrance (or the absence of which would remove a hindrance) to the least-favored class realizing their rational life goals, then the DP s formulation is a possible source of injustice. And if that is true, then by focusing exclusively on absolute levels of expectations the Difference Principle fails to take seriously the moral significance of the relative level of expectations of the least-favored. 3.2. Rawls Response to the Worry Even Rawls seems to anticipate something like the above worry, saying A person s lesser position may be so great as to wound his self-respect, and that society may permit such large disparities in [expectations] that under existing social conditions these differences cannot help but cause a loss of self-esteem. 12 But he dismisses this concern, saying that Although in theory the difference principle permits indefinitely large inequalities in return for small gains 11 Crocker (1977), pg. 265-6. 12 Rawls (1971), pg. 534. [7 of 12]

to the less favored [or worst-off], the spread of income and wealth should not be excessive in practice. 13 While Rawls suggests that in practice the worry under discussion will likely never come to fruition, it is nevertheless unclear as to how or in what way his account can avoid this worrisome outcome which is, as Rawls himself notes, entailed by the Difference Principle. One of Rawls suggestions is that the numerous groups one might belong to would make it difficult to even determine one s relative disadvantage he says the plurality of associations in a wellordered society tends to reduce the visibility, or at least the painful visibility, of variations in men s prospects. 14 This is all very well, it seems, just so long as one has a sufficient number of associations, but not so satisfying an answer for those lacking such a plurality of associations. A second response from Rawls is that although the worry about DP is apt, it is, nevertheless, not any more troublesome than the entailments of other conceptions of justice. He says there seems to be no reason why the hazards of particular envy should be worse in a society regulated by justice as fairness than by any other conception. 15 This response is also less than satisfying, because while Rawls assertion here may be true, it nevertheless seems to undermine one of his primary motivations for developing his account that appears in A Theory of Justice, which was to provide an alternative account to those of Locke, Rousseau, and Kant, which suffer from similar problems. So, if all of these accounts fair similarly well in this respect, by what reasoning would one opt for Rawls account, rather than the others? A third response from Rawls is that the citizenry in his ideal society would hold mutual respect and esteem in such high regard that those more advantaged [would] not make an 13 Ibid, pg. 536; my emphasis 14 Ibid, pg. 536. 15 Ibid, pg. 537. [8 of 12]

ostentatious display of their higher estate calculated to demean the condition of those who have less. 16 I think this response is probably the best, but it is also less than satisfying. For while this may be generally true, it is easy to imagine an individual whose realization of life plans requires that he make an ostentatious show of his advantage. Furthermore, those who are worseoff may be disturbed by a non-ostentatious show like seeing their neighbors driving expensive sports cars, sailing in yachts, or drinking rare imported wines, while they pedal their 10-speed bicycles, wear hand-me-downs, and drink soy milk. 4. SUGGESTING AN ADDENDUM TO DP While all of the foregoing responses seem sensible, the worry about DP still remains, for there is no principle or rule by which the immense relative inequalities between best-off and worst-off are to be forestalled. And it is my suggestion that a principle, or rule, or some additional condition or addendum to DP is required to provide a robust theoretical impediment to DP-sanctioned distributions such that the best-off are hugely advantaged relative to the worst-off. Otherwise, we must do as Rawls does and rely on the weak supposition that these worrisome theoretical entailments of DP will fail to manifest in practice. My humble suggestion is that because the problem seems to arise when moving from one DP-sanctioned distribution to another that has a higher absolute level of expectation for worstoff, but a lower relative expectation, the solution is to put a cap on the amount of relative inequality that is allowed when moving from an initial distribution to a second. One very simple way to do this is would be to stipulate that the relative level of expectation of those worst-off in a 16 Ibid, pg. 537. [9 of 12]

second distribution is not to exceed the level that existed in the initial distribution. To illustrate this point, consider the following simplified examples: 100 60 50 30 D1 D2 So, the initial distribution, D1, has a relative level of expectation of 5:3. On my suggested addendum, to move from D1 to D2 requires that the relative expectation of 5:3 not be exceeded. So for example, to move the best-off from 50 to 100 units is justified only if the expectations of the worst-off increase to 60 units (or greater) in D2. More precisely formulated, the addendum would look like this: 17 Addendum: B* B W* W B/W Where: B* = the absolute level of expectations for best-off in the 2 nd distribution. B = the absolute level of expectations for best-off in the initial distribution. W* = the absolute level of expectations for worst-off in the 2 nd distribution. W = the absolute level of expectations for worst-off in the initial distribution. B/W = the relative expectations of the best-off over the worst-off. In this way, the addendum (i) allows for inequality, (ii) this inequality is still subject to DP (i.e., 17 Credit is due to Crocker (see References) for inspiring me to formulate my addendum to DP in mathematical terms. [10 of 12]

benefits the worst-off), but it also (iii) precludes the sort of increases in relative expectation that were illustrated in fig. 3-5. It is important to keep in mind that this addendum is merely a humble suggestion; I realize that there will doubtless be concerns stemming from the addendum, but it is an initial, prima facie plausible suggestion for trying to forestall the sort of immense relative inequalities that even Rawls himself acknowledges are entailed by the Difference Principle. 5. CONCLUSION John Rawls book A Theory of Justice represents an immense contribution to the field of political philosophy, in no small part because of his two principles of justice expressed therein. And while his second principle of justice relies on the intuitively appealing understanding of just inequality encapsulated in the Difference Principle, there is nevertheless a worrisome entailment of this principle that even extraordinary levels of inequality are considered just, so long as this inequality redounds to the benefit of the worst-off class of society. I have suggested that the potentially immense level of inequality can itself become a source of injustice by hindering the realization of individual s rational life plans and well-being. And that if that is so, then the difference principle requires the inclusion of some formal provision to safeguard against such inequalities. I then suggested that the prima facie plausible addendum to the Difference Principle I offer could provide such a safeguard, and would thereby ensure that Rawls two principles do not ultimately justify what would amount to immense, socially divisive inequalities. [11 of 12]

REFERENCES 1. Rawls, John (1971/rev. 1999), A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press), pp. 3-107, 532-538 2. Crocker, Lawrence (1977), Equality, Solidarity, and Rawls MaxiMin, Philosophy & Public Affairs, Vol. 6, No. 3, pp. 262-266 3. Arrow, Kenneth (1973), Some Ordinalist-Utilitarian Notes on Rawls Theory of Justice by John Rawls, The Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 70, No. 9, pp. 245-263. 4. Also, special thanks to Dr. Ryan Wasserman for his productive discussion of this topic with me. [12 of 12]