Bernd Lahno Can the Social Contract Be Signed by an Invisible Hand? A New Debate on an Old Question *

Similar documents
The Veil of Ignorance in Rawlsian Theory

John Rawls. Cambridge University Press John Rawls: An Introduction Percy B. Lehning Frontmatter More information

Two Pictures of the Global-justice Debate: A Reply to Tan*

Lahore University of Management Sciences. Phil 228/Pol 207 Contemporary Debates in Political Philosophy Summer 2017

Is Rawls s Difference Principle Preferable to Luck Egalitarianism?

Morals by Convention The rationality of moral behaviour

Jan Narveson and James P. Sterba

Lahore University of Management Sciences. Phil 323/Pol 305 Contemporary Debates in Political Philosophy Fall

Part III Immigration Policy: Introduction

PHIL 28 Ethics & Society II

Political Obligation 3

Last time we discussed a stylized version of the realist view of global society.

The Original Position

Part III Immigration Policy: Introduction

Social and Political Philosophy Philosophy 4470/6430, Government 4655/6656 (Thursdays, 2:30-4:25, Goldwin Smith 348) Topic for Spring 2011: Equality

Definition: Property rights in oneself comparable to property rights in inanimate things

From the veil of ignorance to the overlapping consensus: John Rawls as a theorist of communication

Great Philosophers: John Rawls ( ) Brian Carey 13/11/18

POL 10a: Introduction to Political Theory Spring 2017 Room: Golding 101 T, Th 2:00 3:20 PM

POLITICAL AUTHORITY AND PERFECTIONISM: A RESPONSE TO QUONG

The PPE Enterprise: A Substantive Research Programme

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Natural Law and Spontaneous Order in the Work of Gary Chartier

Poverty Knowledge, Coercion, and Social Rights: A Discourse Ethical Contribution to Social Epistemology

Libertarianism. Polycarp Ikuenobe A N I NTRODUCTION

Hobbes Today: Insights for the 21st Century, ed.s.a.lloyd(cambridge University Press: New York, 2013), 353 pp., 65.00, ISBN

IMPARTIAL JUSTICE: CONDITIONS AND IMPLICATIONS

A conception of human rights is meant to play a certain role in global political

Princeton University Press

SUBSCRIBE NOW AND RECEIVE CRISIS AND LEVIATHAN* FREE!

A Defense of Public Justification

Social and Political Ethics, 7.5 ECTS Autumn 2016

PH 3022 SOCIAL AND POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY UK LEVEL 5 UK CREDITS: 15 US CREDITS: 3/0/3

Utilitarianism, Game Theory and the Social Contract

Introduction to Equality and Justice: The Demands of Equality, Peter Vallentyne, ed., Routledge, The Demands of Equality: An Introduction

British Political Culture and the Idea of Public Opinion,

Libertarianism and the Justice of a Basic Income. Peter Vallentyne, University of Missouri at Columbia

Justice As Fairness: Political, Not Metaphysical (Excerpts)

VII. Aristotle, Virtue, and Desert

POLITICAL DISPOSITIONS AND DISPOSITIONAL POLITICS*

James M. Buchanan The Limits of Market Efficiency

A Liberal Defence of Compulsory Voting : Some Reasons for Scepticism.

The public vs. private value of health, and their relationship. (Review of Daniel Hausman s Valuing Health: Well-Being, Freedom, and Suffering)

THE POSSIBILITY OF A FAIR PLAY ACCOUNT OF LEGITIMACY. Justin Tosi

Theories of Social Justice

Pos 419Z Seminar in Political Theory: Equality Left and Right Spring Peter Breiner

The Restoration of Welfare Economics

Rawls versus the Anarchist: Justice and Legitimacy

PLSC 118B, THE MORAL FOUNDATIONS OF POLITICS

Do we have a strong case for open borders?

Social Contractarianism

DEMOCRACY, JUDICIAL REVIEW AND DISAGREEMENTS ABOUT JUSTICE

Introduction 478 U.S. 186 (1986) U.S. 558 (2003). 3

Policy & precarity what are people able to do and be? Helen Taylor Cardiff Metropolitan

What is philosophy and public policy?

PARTIAL COMPLIANCE: SUNDAY SCHOOL MORALITY MEETS GAME THEORY.

No man is an island. By Ingemund Hägg 2. John Stuart Mill, liberalism and flawed attacks by anti-liberals 1. The human being

Aggregation and the Separateness of Persons

Do we have a moral obligation to the homeless?

New Directions for the Capability Approach: Deliberative Democracy and Republicanism

Where does Confucian Virtuous Leadership Stand? A Critique of Daniel Bell s Beyond Liberal Democracy

On Human Rights by James Griffin, Oxford University Press, 2008, 339 pp.

LOGROLLING. Nicholas R. Miller Department of Political Science University of Maryland Baltimore County Baltimore, Maryland

The third debate: Neorealism versus Neoliberalism and their views on cooperation

INTERPRETING THE RIGHT TO LIFE

The Provision of Public Goods, and the Matter of the Revelation of True Preferences: Two Views

Political Obligation 2

Constitutional Political Economy 1

Self-Organization and Cooperation in Social Systems

On the Irrelevance of Formal General Equilibrium Analysis

Rawls, Islam, and political constructivism: Some questions for Tampio

Social Contract Theory

1 From a historical point of view, the breaking point is related to L. Robbins s critics on the value judgments

How to approach legitimacy

New German Critique and Duke University Press are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to New German Critique.

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at

A Rawlsian Perspective on Justice for the Disabled

Review of Michael E. Bratman s Shared Agency: A Planning Theory of Acting Together (Oxford University Press 2014) 1

Scanlon: Freedom of Expression / Categories of Expression

Western Philosophy of Social Science

In Nations and Nationalism, Ernest Gellner says that nationalism is a theory of

The purpose of this review is not so much to critique Robert Miller s new book, but rather

University of Alberta

Fisheries and Aquaculture Standards Revision Process Procedures Contents

Economic Analysis, Moral. Philosophy, and Public Policy. Third Edition. Edited by. DANIEL HAUSMAN Universitär of Wisconsin-Madison

Economics and Reality. Harald Uhlig 2012

Prof. Dr. Bernhard Neumärker Summer Term 2016 Albert-Ludwigs-Universität Freiburg. Constitutional Economics. Exam. July 28, 2016

Political Norms and Moral Values

PHL 370 Issues in Philosophy of Law: Rights Instructor: Mark Schranz Lectures: TBD Office/Hours: TBD

Theories of Justice. Is economic inequality unjust? Ever? Always? Why?

Autonomy and Rights: The Moral Foundations of Liberalism by Horacio Spector. A Review by

Penalizing Public Disobedience*

Compromise, Peace and Public Justification

Ethics and Public Policy. Government / Public Policy 42 Spring 2016 Dartmouth College

POSC 6100 Political Philosophy

Rawls and Feminism. Hannah Hanshaw. Philosophy. Faculty Advisor: Dr. Jacob Held

The Language of Law and More Probable Than Not : Some Brief Thoughts

Procedural Rules of the Climate Negotiations Introduction

The One-dimensional View

INSTITUTIONAL ISSUES INVOLVING ETHICS AND JUSTICE Vol.I - Economic Justice - Hon-Lam Li

Transcription:

RMM Vol. 4, 2013, 39 43 Special Topic: Can the Social Contract Be Signed by an Invisible Hand? http://www.rmm-journal.de/ Bernd Lahno Can the Social Contract Be Signed by an Invisible Hand? A New Debate on an Old Question * The title of this special topic in RMM is borrowed from a paper of Hillel Steiner (1978) in which he argues against Robert Nozick s (1974) invisible hand conception of the emergence of the state. Steiner believes that central institutions of social order such as money and government need some form of conscious endorsement by individuals to emerge and to persist over time. The idea to take this old but still central theme of the debate on the origin of social order as one starting point in a new attempt to evaluate the conception of a social contract was borne when Tony de Jasay (2010) criticized Bob Sugdens plea for a Humean version of contractarianism (2009, this journal). To Robert Sugden it seems perfectly consistent to be a Humean and a contractarian at the same time. To be sure: as an economist in the tracks of David Hume Sugden rejects the idea of explaining or justifying the fundamental social institutions by reference to some original contract. From a Humean point of view these institutions are simply the outcome and manifestation of social conventions. However, the relevant conventions are of a particular kind. They are promoting the common interest and can ultimately be characterized as a specific form of mutually advantageous social exchange: I abide by the social rules in exchange for your corresponding compliance. The concept of a contract, argues Sugden, is best suited to capture this politics-as-exchange (Buchanan 1987) conception of basic social institutions since a contract is typically based on reciprocity as well as consent. Anthony de Jasay responds that no alleged common interest neither actual nor hypothetical can ever suffice to justify what he calls a rule of submission. Subordinating the pursuit of individual interest to collective command is never possible in full agreement. But, no such subordination is actually required in the emergence and maintenance of the relevant conventions. Neither a global feeling of reciprocity nor any normative consent is needed as a motivational force to make conventions work. For Jasay the whole point of the Humean theory of social institutions based on convention is that enlightened self-interest combined with some awareness of actually existing behavioral regularities suffice to gen- * The work on this project was supported by a fellowship at the Käte Hamburger Kolleg / Centre for Global Cooperation Research, University of Duisburg-Essen, Germany.

40 Bernd Lahno erate mutual adaption to conventional rules. Commitment beyond self interest is unnecessary to explain (or justify) social order. This raises the question of the exact role of mutual advantage and the common good in a Humean account of social order. The opponents seem to agree that the following basic observations are in principle correct: (1) There is a behavioral regularity in accordance with a (system of) social rule(s). (2) It is by and large individually rational to act rule-compliant, provided that sufficiently many others do. (3) It is mutually advantageous that people act in accordance with the rules. The primary disagreement is about the relationship between (2) and (3) and their relevance in a reasonable explanation of the emergence and maintenance of the social regularity as asserted in (1). For Jasay (2) is the only premise needed to understand why individuals comply with the rules und thus to understand how the behavioral regularities and the respective social rules may emerge. Individual interest is the core of any explanation of the emergence and maintenance of social order; no reference to a common good or mutual advantage of all is necessary. It is completely sufficient that in the evolution and maintenance of the convention all adapt locally and freely. Their consent does not relate to the rule or convention as a whole. They just do what is favoring their interests in the given situation. Hillel Steiner came to a somewhat different conclusion more than 35 years ago. In his Can the social Contract Be Signed by an Invisible Hand? he argued that institutions like money require conscious observance of rules and their shared recognition as being mutually advantageous (see also his contribution in this special topic). Thus, they cannot be properly understood as the result of invisible hand processes. Without shared intentions and normative beliefs concerning the rules as a whole they cannot work. Simply treating the conventions as social facts that do not have some overall purpose or cannot be modeled in a teleological manner as if they had does not suffice. The idea that a mutual understanding of (3) plays a major role in the emergence of the social regularity and, thus, is crucial for explaining (1) defines for Hartmut Kliemt 1 the core of contractarianism. As Kliemt may express it: a global perspective on the system of social rules is a necessary and characteristic ingredient in any contractarian explanation (and/or justification) of social order. Arguably, this is exactly, what Sugden wants to endorse in pleading for a Humean form of contractarianism. In that case he and Steiner would be on the one side of the issue and Jasay (and presumably Kliemt) on the other. On the face of it the whole dispute may seem to be about an empirical issue. What are the proper conditions to make conventions work? It also raises a history of ideas issue about the correct exegesis of Hume s theory of justice. Yet, there is, of course, a much more contested normative issue in the background. 1 In a commentary which will be included in this special topic.

Can the Social Contract Be Signed by an Invisible Hand? 41 It is true, Anthony de Jasay argues in the first place that conventions in the Humean sense form a solid ground for social order and nothing but a sufficiently sophisticated account of self-interested rational behavior is needed to understand such social co-operation. But what he really seems to be opposing is not so much some false empirical belief about the functioning of social order or the motives of social compliance. Nor is Jasay attacking a specific claim about the origin of society. The main target of his critique is rather the normative conviction that some form of mutual agreement going beyond the agreements in bilateral contracts constitutes a real and not just a fictitious obligation to conform to the social rules. This, so his fear, would legitimize subordinating individual life to all sorts of collective command. The empirical claim that social order requires a mutual understanding of the common good is, of course, crucially related to the normative conviction that such consent may in fact justify an obligation to abide by the rules of society. It will be one issue in this special topic to get a better understanding of how this is-ought relationship is actually constituted. Within the 35 years since the publication of Hillel Steiner s paper different advances have been made in economics and philosophy that may well shed some new light on some of the fundamental issues in the debate about a contractarian conception of social order. These make us confident that a new attempt to explore the contractarian idea is well worthwhile. In economics a new interest in the role of norms in social co-operation and exchange arose with the rise of skepticism about the traditional economic model of human behavior, followed by enhanced research in bounded rationality, and a shift towards behavioral economics and the behavioral sciences as a whole. Thus new insights into the behavioral foundations of mutual understanding and social cooperation in general were generated. In philosophy, following the re-introduction of contractarian thought by John Rawls (1972), Robert Nozick (1974) and others (see also Gordon 1976) new perspectives on the foundations of social contract theory and its normative force were facilitated by new attempts to define the justifying potential of a common understanding or contract (Scanlon 1982; 1998), the introduction of economic analysis of problems of cooperation and coordination into normative thought in ethics and social philosophy (Gauthier 1986; Taylor 1987; Hardin 1988; Skyrms 1996; Binmore 2005), and a growing interest in collective intentionality (see Schweikard and Schmid 2013 for an overview). In the light of these advancements and motivated by the debate between Robert Sugden and Anthony de Jasay RMM offers a platform with this special topic to

42 Bernd Lahno recap on the strength s and the weaknesses of the contractarian idea and to once more explore its potential. Those who first motivated this project, Hillel Steiner, Anthony de Jasay, and Robert Sugden, as well as a number of other well reputed scholars confirmed to contribute to our special topic. The special topic will actually start with a previously unpublished paper by Hillel Steiner, originally written in 1986, in which he extends and elaborates on his argument about money from the 1978 paper, and with an original article by Anthony de Jasay, in which he further clarifies his worries. A response by Robert Sugden will follow. Further contributions will discuss the matter by reference to the roots of the debate in seventeenth and eighteenth century philosophy or to recent advancements in economics, the behavioral sciences or in social philosophy. Some of the contributions confirmed are already in a very elaborated stage and ready to be published soon. They are officially announced on RMM s webpage with the launch of the special topic. But as always the project is open ended and further contributions will continuously be added. After some time the special topic will probably reach a stage, in which it will become possible and appropriate to survey the discussion thus far and to try to draw some first and cautious conclusions. But now, at the very start of the project, no comprehensive preview of the discussion should (and can reasonably) be given. We experienced stunning interest and, in fact, enthusiasm by the colleagues which we could win for the project. The stimulating and thoughtful proposals of contribution that we received give us all the confidence one can have that this project will evolve into a most fruitful and exciting endeavor. We are looking forward to this adventure. References Binmore, K. (2005), Natural Justice, Oxford New York: Oxford University Buchanan, J. M. (1987), The Constitution of Economic Policy, The American Economic Review 77(3), 243 250. Gauthier, D. (1986), Morals by Agreement, Oxford: Oxford University Gordon, S. (1976), The New Contractarianism, Journal of Political Economy 84(3), 573 590. Hardin, R. (1988), Morality within the Limits of Reason, Chicago: University of Chicago Jasay, A. de (2010), Ordered Anarchy and Contractarianism, Philosophy 85, 399 403. Nozick, R. (1974), Anarchy, State, and Utopia, New York: Basic Books. Rawls, J. (1971), A Theory of Justice, Cambridge/MA: Harvard University Steiner, H. (1978), Can a Social Contract Be Signed by an Invisible Hand?, in: Birnbaum, P., J. Lively and G. Perry (eds.), Democracy Consensus and Social Contract, London Beverley Hills: Sage Publications, 295 316.

Can the Social Contract Be Signed by an Invisible Hand? 43 Scanlon, T. F. (1982), Contractualism and Utilitarianism, in: Sen, A. and B. Williams, Utilitarianism and beyond, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 103 128. (1998), What We Owe to Each Other, Cambridge/MA: Harvard University Schweikard, D. P. and H. B. Schmid (forthcoming), Collective Intentionality, in: Zalta, E. N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2013 Edition), URL: http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2013/entries/collective-intentionality/. Skyrms, B. (1996), Evolution of the Social Contract, Cambridge: Cambridge University Sugden, R. (2009), Can a Humean Be a Contractarian?, RMM 0, 11 23, URL: http:// www.rmm-journal.de/downloads/002_sugden.pdf. Taylor, M. (1987), The Possibility of Cooperation, Cambridge: Cambridge University