Regulatory Policy Program

Similar documents
Measuring Sustainable Development: Theory and Application

Equitable intergenerational preferences and sustainability

Robbins as Innovator: the Contribution of An Essay on the Nature and Significance of Economic Science

The Restoration of Welfare Economics

Any non-welfarist method of policy assessment violates the Pareto principle: A comment

Human Development and the current economic and social challenges

HARVARD JOHN M. OLIN CENTER FOR LAW, ECONOMICS, AND BUSINESS

Nordic Journal of Political Economy

Jürgen Kohl March 2011

CREATING A LEARNING SOCIETY. Joseph E. Stiglitz The London School of Economics and Political Science The Amartya Sen Lecture June 2012

Economic Growth and the Interests of Future (and Past and Present) Generations: A Comment on Tyler Cowen

Postscript: Subjective Utilitarianism

Law & Economics Lecture 1: Basic Notions & Concepts

Some reflections on the role of moral reasoning in economics

Ethical Basis of Welfare Economics. Ethics typically deals with questions of how should we act?

Chapter 2 Positive vs Normative Analysis

THE PHILOSOPHY AND ECONOMICS OF THE ENVIRONMENT. Reading list for Trinity Term Topic One (A): Philosophical Foundations

CHAPTER 19 MARKET SYSTEMS AND NORMATIVE CLAIMS Microeconomics in Context (Goodwin, et al.), 2 nd Edition

Towards an operational sustainability criterion

1.2 Efficiency and Social Justice

2. Economics: A Very Short Introduction (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 2007, pp

"Efficient and Durable Decision Rules with Incomplete Information", by Bengt Holmström and Roger B. Myerson

Working Papers in Economics

Natural Wealth. Partha Dasgupta*

Economic Analysis of Law and the Value of Efficiency

14.770: Introduction to Political Economy Lecture 12: Political Compromise

1 Aggregating Preferences

Agencies Should Ignore Distant-Future Generations

1100 Ethics July 2016

George Mason University School of Law

THE RICH HAVE MORE MONEY

COWLES FOUNDATION FOR RESEARCH IN ECONOMICS YALE UNIVERSITY

PubPol Values, Ethics, and Public Policy, Fall 2009

Individualism. Marquette University. John B. Davis Marquette University,

Economic philosophy of Amartya Sen Social choice as public reasoning and the capability approach. Reiko Gotoh

involving 58,000 foreig n students in the U.S. and 11,000 American students $1.0 billion. Third, the role of foreigners in the American economics

Solving the "Tragedy of the Commons": An Alternative to Privatization*

The Conflict between Notions of Fairness and the Pareto Principle

The political economy of public sector reforms: Redistributive promises, and transfers to special interests

The Arrow Impossibility Theorem: Where Do We Go From Here?

Equity and efficiency defined and considered

A Public Philosophical Critique of Modern Economics

UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA, SAN DIEGO DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS

VOTING ON INCOME REDISTRIBUTION: HOW A LITTLE BIT OF ALTRUISM CREATES TRANSITIVITY DONALD WITTMAN ECONOMICS DEPARTMENT UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA

Online publication date: 21 July 2010 PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE

Part III Immigration Policy: Introduction

Rational Choice. Pba Dab. Imbalance (read Pab is greater than Pba and Dba is greater than Dab) V V

Arrow s Impossibility Theorem on Social Choice Systems

Economic Sociology I Fall Kenneth Boulding, The Role of Mathematics in Economics, JPE, 56 (3) 1948: 199

Planning versus Free Choice in Scientific Research

POLI 111: INTRODUCTION TO THE STUDY OF POLITICAL SCIENCE

History of Social Choice and Welfare Economics

ECONOMICS AND INEQUALITY: BLINDNESS AND INSIGHT. Sanjay Reddy. I am extremely grateful to Bina Agarwal, IAFFE S President, and to IAFFE for its

The public vs. private value of health, and their relationship. (Review of Daniel Hausman s Valuing Health: Well-Being, Freedom, and Suffering)

Robust Political Economy. Classical Liberalism and the Future of Public Policy

Immigration and Conflict in Democracies

Theories of Regulation (410115) 1

Course: Economic Policy with an Emphasis on Tax Policy

NBER WORKING PAPER SERIES NATIONAL SOVEREIGNTY IN AN INTERDEPENDENT WORLD. Kyle Bagwell Robert W. Staiger

Empirical research on economic inequality Lecture notes on theories of justice (preliminary version) Maximilian Kasy

The Social Choice Theory: Can it be considered a Complete Political Theory?

Learning and Belief Based Trade 1

ONLINE APPENDIX: Why Do Voters Dismantle Checks and Balances? Extensions and Robustness

Improving the Relationship between Welfare Economics and Ethics

VIOLENCE PREVENTION: Bringing Health and Human Rights Together

Definition: Institution public system of rules which defines offices and positions with their rights and duties, powers and immunities p.

Australian Agricultural & Resource Economics Soc. Conference Paper: Cairns, Feb Decision-Making in a Social Welfare Context.

Experimental Computational Philosophy: shedding new lights on (old) philosophical debates

Equality and Priority

Social Choice Theory and Deliberative Democracy: A Response to Aldred

Sampling Equilibrium, with an Application to Strategic Voting Martin J. Osborne 1 and Ariel Rubinstein 2 September 12th, 2002.

and Collective Goods Princeton: Princeton University Press, Pp xvii, 161 $6.00

Labour market integration and its effect on child labour

THREATS TO SUE AND COST DIVISIBILITY UNDER ASYMMETRIC INFORMATION. Alon Klement. Discussion Paper No /2000

A NOTE ON THE THEORY OF SOCIAL CHOICE

Introduction 478 U.S. 186 (1986) U.S. 558 (2003). 3

Kenneth Arrow on Public Goods, Public Policy, and Environmental Economics. Partha Dasgupta. September 18, 2017

Working Paper No. 14/05. Relocating the responsibility cut: Should more responsibility imply less redistribution?

How Mythical Markets Mislead Analysis: An institutionalist critique of market universalism. Geoffrey M. Hodgson

Aidis, Ruta, Laws and Customs: Entrepreneurship, Institutions and Gender During Economic Transition

THE ECONOMICS OF SUBSIDIES. J. Atsu Amegashie University of Guelph Guelph, Canada. website:

What is the Relationship Between The Idea of the Minimum and Distributive Justice?

Whose values count: is a theory of social choice for sustainability science possible?

John Rawls's Difference Principle and The Strains of Commitment: A Diagrammatic Exposition

Pure Time Preference in Intertemporal Welfare Economics. J. Paul Kelleher University of Wisconsin-Madison. Forthcoming in Economics and Philosophy

Macroeconomic Implications of Shifts in the Relative Demand for Skills

George Mason University SCHOOL of LAW

Study Unit 04 Activity 04. Summarise the arguments stating that population growth is not a real problem.

Lecture I: Political Economy and Public Finance: Overview. Tim Besley, LSE. Why should economists care about political economy issues?

Late pre-classical economics (ca ) Mercantilism (16th 18th centuries) Physiocracy (ca ca. 1789)

(67686) Mathematical Foundations of AI June 18, Lecture 6

Revista Economica 65:6 (2015) ECONOMIC DEVELOPMENT AS AN INTERRELATION BETWEEN WEALTH, COMPETITIVENESS, AND INTELLECTUAL CAPITAL EMPIRICAL EVIDENCES

RATIONALITY AND POLICY ANALYSIS

The Effects of Housing Prices, Wages, and Commuting Time on Joint Residential and Job Location Choices

Ethics Handout 18 Rawls, Classical Utilitarianism and Nagel, Equality

Trends in the Income Gap Between. Developed Countries and Developing Countries,

Why Does Inequality Matter? T. M. Scanlon. Chapter 8: Unequal Outcomes. It is well known that there has been an enormous increase in inequality in the

Social Choice & Mechanism Design

Tradeoffs in implementation of SDGs: how to integrate perspectives of different stakeholders?

Comments on Justin Weinberg s Is Government Supererogation Possible? Public Reason Political Philosophy Symposium Friday October 17, 2008

Transcription:

Interpreting Sustainability in Economic Terms: Dynamic Efficiency Plus Intergenerational Equity Robert Stavins Alexander Wagner Gernot Wagner May 2002 RPP-2002-02 Regulatory Policy Program Center for Business and Government John F. Kennedy School of Government 79 John F. Kennedy Street, Weil Hall Cambridge, MA 02138

Citation This paper may be cited as: Stavins, Robert N., Alexander Wagner, and Gernot Wagner. 2002. Interpreting Sustainability in Economic Terms: Dynamic Efficiency Plus Intergenerational Equity. Regulatory Policy Program Working Paper RPP-2002-02. Cambridge, MA: Center for Business and Government, John F. Kennedy School of Government, Harvard University. Comments may be directed to the authors at John F. Kennedy School of Government, Harvard University, 79 JFK Street, Cambridge, MA 02138; Email robert_stavins@harvard.edu and awagner@fas.harvard.edu and gwagner@post.harvard.edu. Regulatory Policy Program The Regulatory Policy Program at the Center for Business and Government provides an environment in which to develop and test leading ideas on regulation and regulatory institutions. RPP s research aims to improve the global society and economy by understanding the impacts of regulation and creating better decisions about the design and implementation of regulatory strategies around the world. RPP s efforts are organized around the following three core areas: regulation, markets, and deregulation; regulatory instruments; and regulatory institutions and policymaking. The views expressed in this paper are those of the authors and do not imply endorsement by the Regulatory Policy Program, the Center for Business and Government, the John F. Kennedy School of Government, or Harvard University. For Further Information Further information on the Regulatory Policy Program can be obtained from the program s director, Jennifer Nash, Center for Business and Government, John F. Kennedy School of Government, 79 JFK Street, Cambridge, MA 02138, telephone (617) 384-7325, telefax (617) 496-0063, Email jennifer_nash@ksg.harvard.edu.

Interpreting Sustainability in Economic Terms: Dynamic Efficiency Plus Intergenerational Equity Robert N. Stavins, Alexander F. Wagner, and Gernot Wagner RPP-2002-02 Abstract Economists have expended considerable effort to develop economically meaningful definitions of the somewhat elusive concept of sustainability. We relate such a definition of sustainability to well known concepts from neoclassical economics, in particular, potential Pareto improvements (in the Kaldor-Hicks sense) and interpersonal compensation. In the inter-temporal realm, we find that dynamic efficiency is a necessary but not sufficient condition for a notion of sustainability that has normative standing as a goal for public policy. We define sustainability as dynamic efficiency plus intergenerational equity. Further, we argue that it is not unreasonable for economists to focus on the efficiency element, leaving equity considerations to the political process. The analogy to the relationship between potential Pareto improvements and (intragenerational) transfers can facilitate discussions about sustainability, both within the economics community and as part of an interdisciplinary discourse, and makes the basic concepts easier to operationalize. Robert Stavins is the Albert Pratt Professor of Business and Government, John F. Kennedy School of Government, Harvard University, and a University Fellow of Resources for the Future; Alexander Wagner is a Ph.D. student in Political Economy and Government at Harvard University; and Gernot Wagner is a B.A. student at Harvard College. We thank Geir Asheim, Partha Dasgupta, John Hartwick, John Pezzey and Martin Weitzman for helpful comments on an earlier draft. The authors are responsible for any remaining errors.

Interpreting Sustainability in Economic Terms: Dynamic Efficiency Plus Intergenerational Equity Robert N. Stavins, Alexander F. Wagner, and Gernot Wagner 1. Introduction There has been much debate among economists, and between economists and nearly everyone else regarding the meaning of the frequently employed concept of sustainability. In this note, we suggest that a broadly-accepted and normatively useful notion of sustainability can be better understood by breaking it into two components, both of which are well defined in economics: dynamic efficiency and intergenerational equity. Within this realm, there are sound reasons for economists to focus on policy criteria associated with the dynamic efficiency element of sustainability. In 1987, the Brundtland Commission placed sustainability on international political and scientific agendas with its report, Our Common Future (World Commission on Environment and Development 1987). The Commission proposed the widely embraced definition that development is sustainable when it meets the needs of the present without compromising the ability of future generations to meet theirs (WCED 1987). This is the definition we use as our starting point. We find that contrary to some claims sustainability is not only about intergenerational equity; rather, widelyheld views of sustainability encompass elements of both efficiency and distributional equity. Furthermore, much as economists have long focused on potential rather than actual Pareto improvements, they need not be apologetic for focusing on dynamic efficiency, leaving (admittedly important) equity considerations to the political process.

2. Dynamic Efficiency The definition of sustainability offered by the World Commission on Environment and Development (WCED) is broadly accepted and seems to have intuitive appeal: meeting the needs of the present without compromising the ability of future generations to meet their needs. In the absence of efficiency, constant consumption at no more than a subsistence level could satisfy this requirement, yet it would surely not be accepted as a reasonable social goal or target for public policy. Any appealing normative criterion for public policy in this domain ought to include some notion of nonwastefulness. That is, a meaningful definition of sustainability which has normative standing as a social goal ought to include dynamic efficiency, expressed formally as the maximization of (1) W (t) U( c(τ) ) e r( τ t) dτ, t over all feasible alternative consumption paths c(τ), where U( c(τ) ) denotes the most general, idealized utility function comprising both direct consumption as well as the enjoyment of non-market goods and services, and is the social rate of time preference. 1 If it is desirable to avoid unnecessarily degrading resources, and if sustainability has normative standing as a policy goal, then dynamic efficiency is a necessary condition for a normatively meaningful interpretation of this concept. The important point here is that W (t) must capture total welfare. Anything else can be misleading. Omitting contributions to welfare of any kind of capital will lead to an 1 This formulation as well as the notation used in equation (2) are consistent with Arrow et al. (2002), which calls the solution of this problem the present value of felicities. Weitzman (2002) refers to it as a measure of welfare-equivalent sustainability.

underestimate of the total value of W (t), and omitting any form of capital depreciation will lead to an overestimate. The theoretical implications of technological and population change have been examined in this context, and the theory regarding ideal measures of W (t) has been explored extensively. 2 3. Intergenerational Equity Although we have argued that dynamic efficiency is necessary for a normatively useful definition of sustainability, we do not believe that dynamic efficiency is a sufficient condition for sustainability. 3 It is also essential for consistency with widely embraced definitions of this concept that the maximized total welfare function not decrease over time. Formally, an optimized consumption path fulfills the condition of intergenerational equity if (2) dw (t) dt 0, where W (t) represents the maximized total welfare function from equation (1). 2 Pezzey and Toman (2001) provide a survey of these issues. Heal (1998, 2001), Solow (1991), and Weitzman (2002) also give reasons why narrow definitions of economic capital should be expanded to include, for example, human and natural capital. 3 In fact, sustainability has frequently been defined as being exclusively about intergenerational equity. Most recently, Arrow et al. (2002) make a clear distinction between optimality as the discounted present value of future well being as presented in equation (1) and sustainability, defined as the maintenance or improvement of well being over time, formally presented in equation (2). One exception in the current literature is Asheim, Buchholz and Tungodden (2001), who impose so-called efficiency and equity axioms and show that if social preferences fulfill these two axioms, any optimal path will lead to an efficient and non-decreasing path, thus implicitly including dynamic efficiency in the definition of sustainability. For an earlier discussion of sustainability and optimality, see Pezzey (1992).

This brings us to an economic definition of sustainability: an economy is sustainable if and only if it is dynamically efficient and the resulting stream of maximized total welfare functions is non-declining over time. 4. Sustainability We acknowledge that the above definition provides a demanding pair of decision criteria that cannot be considered to be very useful as a guide for public policy. The same is true, however, of the benchmark of a Pareto-improving policy one which makes some members of society better off, but makes no one worse off (1896). Actual Pareto improvements are exceptionally rare, of course, perhaps even non-existent. Hence, the strict Pareto criterion is virtually never taken as a guide for public policy, despite its considerable normative appeal. Economists resort instead to seeking potential Pareto improvements in the Kaldor-Hicks sense the world is viewed as being made better off if the magnitude of gains and the magnitude of losses are such that the gainers can fully compensate the losers for their loses and still be better off themselves. 4 Note that under the Kaldor-Hicks criterion, the change is considered to be an improvement whether or not the compensation actually takes place. Actual compensation of losers by winners is essentially left to the political process. What is key is that the Kaldor-Hicks criterion is a necessary condition for satisfying the strict Pareto criterion. If a policy proposal fails the Kaldor-Hicks test, it cannot pass the Pareto test. If a proposed change is not a potential Pareto improvement, it cannot be a Pareto improvement. This is the fundamental theoretical foundation the 4 The notion that a welfare improving change ought to be associated with a potential Pareto improvement was introduced by Kaldor (1939) and Hicks (1940).

normative justification for employing benefit-cost analysis, that is, for searching for policies that maximize the positive difference between benefits and costs. Similarly, we can think of an economy as having the potential to become sustainable if it fulfills the criterion of dynamic efficiency. It can then, in principle, be made sustainable by appropriate intergenerational transfers to achieve a non-declining total welfare path. One such economy that can be made sustainable has been formalized by Hartwick (1977), in which there exists the possibility of turning exhaustible resources into capital stock, a particular type of intergenerational transfer. If the Hartwick rule of investing all rents from exhaustible resources in reproducible capital is followed, then the economy can be made sustainable. 5 Much as economists have long focused on potential rather than actual Pareto improvements, leaving the allocation of net gains among individuals (and, hence, the resolution of debates regarding distributional equity) to the political process, similar reasoning leads to an analogous approach to the sustainability debate. In theory, it may be argued that sustainability is ultimately the most desirable policy goal, but in practice it is more reasonable to aim for potential sustainability in the form of dynamic efficiency (of an all-encompassing societal welfare function). 6 We recognize that this opens an avenue for criticism of economics as being excessively focused on efficiency rather than equity, but the efficiency criterion and 5 The conditions under which the Hartwick rule holds, however, are restrictive. Asheim and Buchholz (2000) further explore the assumptions under which the Hartwick rule holds. 6 Except for the elusive case of the Hartwick economy, utility transfers between generations are difficult to operationalize. Their abstractness provide a further reason why we can make more useful policy statements by being satisfied with potential transfers.

related analytical methods are ultimately where the greatest strengths of economics lie. 7 5. Conclusion Sustainability is a broad concept, but it does not need to be vague, as Solow (1991) has argued. Interpretations that are acceptable both to natural scientists and economists should be possible. We find that sustainability can be conceptualized simply and clearly by employing a conventional economics framework, based on discounted utilitarianism. In short, a sustainable growth path is one which is both dynamically efficient and which is non-decreasing over time. Much as a potential Pareto improvement in the Kaldor-Hicks sense can yield Pareto optimality when combined with appropriate compensation of losers by winners, so too can dynamic efficiency lead to the more ambitious goal of sustainability when it is combined with appropriate intergenerational transfers. And much as economics often resorts to seeking potential Pareto improvements, leaving the final allocation to the political process, so too may it focus on dynamic efficiency, leading to the possibility, at least, of actual sustainability. 7 One of the most prominent critiques of this focus of economics on efficiency has been offered by Sen (1970). He points out that a society may be efficient even when some people are rolling in luxury and others are near starvation, as long as the starvers cannot be made better off without cutting into the pleasures of the rich. In short, a society can be Pareto optimal and still be perfectly disgusting. Our definition of sustainability does involve notion of distributional equity by including both dynamic efficiency and intergenerational equity. We argue only that the comparative advantage of economics lies in its focus on the first element, whereas the comparative advantage of politics lies in focusing on distributional considerations.

REFERENCES Arrow, Kenneth; Daily, Gretchen; Dasgupta, Partha; Ehrlich, Paul; Goulder, Lawrence; Heal, Geoffrey; Levin, Simon; Mäler, Karl-Göran; Schneider, Stephen; Starrett, David and Walker, Brian. Are We Consuming Too Much? Discussion Paper, Beijer International Institute of Ecological Economics, Stockholm (February 2002). Asheim, Geir; Buchholz, Wolfgang. The Hartwick rule: Myths and facts. Discussion Paper, University of Regensburg (January 2000). Asheim, Geir; Buchholz, Wolfgang and Tungodden, Bertil. Justifying Sustainability. Journal of Environmental Economics and Management 41(3), 252 268 (2001). Hartwick, John M. Investment of Rents from Exhaustible Resources and Intergenerational Equity, American Economic Review 67(5), 972 974 (1977). Heal, Geoffrey. Valuing the Future: Economic Theory and Sustainability. Columbia University Press (1998). Heal, Geoffrey. Optimality or Sustainability. Plenary address to the annual conference of the European Association of Environmental and Resource Economists, Southampton (June 2001). Hicks, John R. The Valuation of the Social Income. Economica (New Series) 7(26), 105 124 (May 1940). Kaldor, Nicholas. Welfare Propositions of Economics and Interpersonal Comparisons of Utility. The Economic Journal 49(195), 549 552 (September 1939). Pareto, Vilfredo. Cours d Economie Politique, volume 2. Lausanne, (1896). Pezzey, John C.V. Sustainable Development Concepts: An Economic Analysis. Washington, D.C.: World Bank. World Bank Environment Paper No. 2 (1992). Pezzey, John C.V. and Toman, Michael A. Progress and Problems in the Economics of Sustainability. Forthcoming in Tietenberg, Thomas H. and Folmer, Henk (Eds.). International Yearbook of Environmental and Resource Economics 2002/2003. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar. Draft copy (August 2001). Sen, Amartya K. Collective Choice and Social Welfare. San Francisco: Holden-Day (1970).

Solow, Robert M. Sustainability: An economist s perspective. The Eighteenth J. Seward Johnson Lecture to the Marine Policy Center, Woods Hole Oceanographic Institution, in Dorfman, Robert and Dorfman, Nancy S. (Eds.). Economics of the Environment: Selected Readings. New York: Norton. 179-187 (1991). Weitzman, Martin L. Income, Capital, and the Maximum Principle. Draft copy, Harvard University (January 2002). World Commission on Environment and Development. Our Common Future. Oxford: Oxford University Press (1987).