Fair Division in Theory and Practice

Similar documents
Elections and Electoral Systems

Elections and referendums

DHSLCalc.xls What is it? How does it work? Describe in detail what I need to do

Voting: Issues, Problems, and Systems. Voting I 1/31

Voting: Issues, Problems, and Systems

Voting: Issues, Problems, and Systems. Voting I 1/36

Math of Election APPORTIONMENT

Fair Division in Theory and Practice

ANALYSIS AND COMPARISON OF GREEK PARLIAMENTARY ELECTORAL SYSTEMS OF THE PERIOD

Section Apportionment Methods. Copyright 2013, 2010, 2007, Pearson, Education, Inc.

n(n 1) 2 C = total population total number of seats amount of increase original amount

Voting: Issues, Problems, and Systems, Continued

Presidential Election Democrat Grover Cleveland versus Benjamin Harrison. ************************************ Difference of 100,456

Elections and Electoral Systems

Fair Division in Theory and Practice

Economics 470 Some Notes on Simple Alternatives to Majority Rule

Voting: Issues, Problems, and Systems, Continued. Voting II 1/27

Explaining the Impossible: Kenneth Arrow s Nobel Prize Winning Theorem on Elections

Many Social Choice Rules

Practice TEST: Chapter 14

Chapter 9: Social Choice: The Impossible Dream Lesson Plan

An introduction to Electoral. André Blais Université de Montréal

Fairness Criteria. Review: Election Methods

Chapter 4 The Mathematics of Apportionment

Name Date I. Consider the preference schedule in an election with 5 candidates.

Exercises For DATA AND DECISIONS. Part I Voting

Democratic Electoral Systems Around the World,

Structure. Electoral Systems. Recap:Normative debates. Discussion Questions. Resources. Electoral & party aid

Today s plan: Section : Plurality with Elimination Method and a second Fairness Criterion: The Monotocity Criterion.

12.2 Defects in Voting Methods

Measuring Fairness. Paul Koester () MA 111, Voting Theory September 7, / 25

Arrow s Impossibility Theorem

Math for Liberal Arts MAT 110: Chapter 12 Notes

Voting rules: (Dixit and Skeath, ch 14) Recall parkland provision decision:

The Impossibilities of Voting

REPRESENTATIVE DEMOCRACY - HOW TO ACHIEVE IT

Voting and Apportionment(Due by Nov. 25)

Chapter 4 The Mathematics of Apportionment

Satisfaction Approval Voting

1.6 Arrow s Impossibility Theorem

Elections with Only 2 Alternatives

In Defense of Majoritarianism

Main idea: Voting systems matter.

9.3 Other Voting Systems for Three or More Candidates

Computational Social Choice: Spring 2007

Compare the vote Level 3

In the next few lectures, we consider the problem of dividing indivisible things (say, seats in a legislature) among players (say, states) in

Voting Criteria: Majority Criterion Condorcet Criterion Monotonicity Criterion Independence of Irrelevant Alternatives Criterion

Voting and Apportionment(Due with Final Exam)

Part Three (continued): Electoral Systems & Linkage Institutions

Compare the vote Level 1

Mathematical Thinking. Chapter 9 Voting Systems

Measuring the Compliance, Proportionality, and Broadness of a Seat Allocation Method

Introduction to the Theory of Voting

Desirable properties of social choice procedures. We now outline a number of properties that are desirable for these social choice procedures:

CARLETON ECONOMIC PAPERS

Chapter 1 Practice Test Questions

Social welfare functions

Note: Article I, section 2, of the Constitution was modified by section 2 of the 14th amendment.

Josh Engwer (TTU) Voting Methods 15 July / 49

answers to some of the sample exercises : Public Choice

Voting Methods

State Study of Election Methods: A Continuation

The mathematics of voting, power, and sharing Part 1

Voting. Hannu Nurmi. Game Theory and Models of Voting. Public Choice Research Centre and Department of Political Science University of Turku

THE ALTERNATIVE VOTE AND COOMBS RULE VERSUS FIRST-PAST-THE-POST: A SOCIAL CHOICE ANALYSIS OF SIMULATED DATA BASED ON ENGLISH ELECTIONS,

A small country consists of four states. There are 100 seats in the legislature. The populations are: A: 44,800 B: 52,200 C: 49,200 D: 53,800

MATH 1340 Mathematics & Politics

Mathematics and Social Choice Theory. Topic 4 Voting methods with more than 2 alternatives. 4.1 Social choice procedures

ELECTING CANDIDATES WITH FAIR REPRESENTATION VOTING: RANKED CHOICE VOTING AND OTHER METHODS

The Mathematics of Apportionment

REFORMING THE ELECTORAL SYSTEM IN ALBERTA: THE CASE FOR DUAL- MEMBER MIXED PROPORTIONAL Sean Graham

House Copy OLS Copy Public Copy For Official House Use BILL NO. Date of Intro. Ref.

PRESENTATION SUMMARY

Computational Social Choice: Spring 2017

Chapter 10. The Manipulability of Voting Systems. For All Practical Purposes: Effective Teaching. Chapter Briefing

Designing for Equality

Analysis and Design of Electoral Systems 735

MATH4999 Capstone Projects in Mathematics and Economics Topic 3 Voting methods and social choice theory

REFORMING THE ELECTORAL FORMULA IN PEI: THE CASE FOR DUAL-MEMBER MIXED PROPORTIONAL Sean Graham

that changes needed to be made when electing their Presidential nominee. Iowa, at the time had a

Electoral System Change in Europe since 1945: Czech Republic

2010 Municipal Elections in Lebanon

Voting Methods for Municipal Elections: Propaganda, Field Experiments and what USA voters want from an Election Algorithm

Simple methods for single winner elections

DUAL-MEMBER MIXED PROPORTIONAL: A NEW ELECTORAL SYSTEM FOR CANADA. (Updated April 4, 2016) Sean Graham

ALEX4.2 A program for the simulation and the evaluation of electoral systems

Dr. Johana Shahini Charles University, Prague

Homework 7 Answers PS 30 November 2013

Designing for Equality Best-fit, medium-fit and non-favourable combinations of electoral systems and gender quotas

Write all responses on separate paper. Use complete sentences, charts and diagrams, as appropriate.

Chapter 9: Social Choice: The Impossible Dream Lesson Plan

Notes for Session 7 Basic Voting Theory and Arrow s Theorem

Voting Systems. High School Circle I. June 4, 2017

The Mathematics of Apportionment

Algorithms, Games, and Networks February 7, Lecture 8

Intro to Contemporary Math

Plurality voting system

Rock the Vote or Vote The Rock

The Mathematics of Voting. The Mathematics of Voting

Transcription:

Fair Division in Theory and Practice Ron Cytron (Computer Science) Maggie Penn (Political Science) Lecture 4: The List Systems of Proportional Representation 1

Saari s milk, wine, beer example Thirteen people with the following preferences must decide on one choice of beverage for the group: Number of voters Preference ranking 4 M W B 2 W B M 1 B M W 2 M B W 4 B W M 2

Number of voters Preference ranking 4 M W B 2 W B M 1 B M W 2 M B W 4 B W M What is the outcome under plurality rule? Under a vote for two rule? Under Borda Count? 3

Number of voters Preference ranking 4 M W B 2 W B M 1 B M W 2 M B W 4 B W M What is the outcome under plurality rule? MBW by 6:5:2 Under a vote for two rule? WBM by 10:9:7 Under Borda Count? BMW by 14:13:12 4

The Borda count, plurality rule and the vote for two rule (a variant of the block vote) are all real-world voting rules. Is the selection of a winner more a function of the voting procedure used than of the preferences of the voters? What does it mean to represent the preferences of the voters? How can we evaluate these systems, given that they all appear reasonable? 5

The pairwise vote (the Condorcet method): a bad decision procedure? Voter Preference ranking 1 A B C 2 B C A 3 C A B What is the majority s choice between A and B? Between B and C? Between C and A? 6

Voter Preference ranking 1 A B C 2 B C A 3 C A B A simple majority vote between pairs of alternatives yields a binary relation that describes the preferences of the majority : A B B C C A This is called Condorcet s Paradox, and implies that the will of the majority will not necessarily yield a best outcome. Here, majority preferences are described by a binary relation that is not transitive. 7

Condorcet s paradox can be generalized (number of people, number of alternatives) To illustrate, suppose that there are n voters and we would like a decision procedure to satisfy a property called minimal democracy: If for some alternative x there is a different y such that n 1 people strictly prefer y to x, then x can t be the social choice. 8

With n people and at least n alternatives to choose from, no procedure can be guaranteed to satisfy minimal democracy. Person 1 : x 1 x 2 x 3... x n 1 x n Person 2 : x 2 x 3 x 4... x n x 1 Person 3 : x 3 x 4 x 5... x 1 x 2... Person n : x n x 1 x 2... x n 2 x n 1 This generates a majority preference cycle x 1 x 2... x n x 1 in which n 1 people share the same preferences over every pairwise vote (for any alternative chosen, n 1 people agree to prefer something else) 9

Is the Condorcet method of taking pairwise votes to determine a social outcome a good procedure? The 1998 Minnesota gubernatorial election Dem. Hubert Humphrey (Atty General) 28% Rep. Norm Coleman (St. Paul mayor) 35% Ref. Jesse The Body Ventura 37% 10

28% Humphrey Coleman Ventura 35% Coleman Humphrey Ventura 37% Ventura Coleman Humphrey Coleman is a Condorcet winner, a candidate that defeats every other candidate in a pairwise vote. Ventura is a Condorcet loser, a candidate that loses to every other candidate in a pairwise vote 11

Condorcet consistency: the ability to select a Condorcet winner if one exists The Minnesota election used plurality rule: each alternative got one point for each ballot it was at the top of. Condorcet s method ranks the alternatives: C H V, while plurality rule ranks the alternatives V C H. Plurality rule is not Condorcet consistent; not only did it not select a Condorcet winner, but it selected a Condorcet loser. 12

What do these examples tell us? They appear to imply that anything is possible, given the appropriate choice of electoral system. Electoral system choice is meaningful because of the fact that no procedure is perfect (and because reasonable systems can produce very different outcomes) Electoral system designers must define the criteria that they want their system to satisfy 13

1. District magnitude Classifying electoral systems The number of seats to be filled by the particular election, or number of winners 2. Ballot structure Ordinal or categorical; whether voters rank candidates or check boxes 3. Electoral formula The mathematical formula that translates ballots into seats; a coarse categorization would be plurality, proportional, and majority. 14

Other ways to classify electoral systems would focus on their outputs Whether the systems produce proportional results Ways of distorting the proportionality of a system include malapportionment, electoral formula, and electoral thresholds. Whether the systems induce strategic behavior (plurality systems are notorious in this the Nader effect) Whether there are many invalid ballots (i.e. whether the system is simple enough for people to understand and use) 15

The List Systems of Proportional Representation Some number of seats are to be distributed to parties that run in an election and voters vote for a party Goal is to allocate seats proportionally to the parties based on their shares of the total votes, so that for each party: % of total votes cast for party = % of total seats given to party 16

How they work For each constituency, each party draws up a list of candidates; length of list depends on DM Most countries draw up sub-national constituencies for each election; some countries hold nationwide election (Israel, Iraq s first election post-hussein) Depending on % of vote each party receives and formula used, seats are distributed to the parties DM > 1 (always), categorical ballot (though there is a lot of variation) 17

Two types of formulas for granting seats to parties Largest remainder systems Seat allocation occurs in two rounds Formula uses subtraction (Hamilton s method) Highest average systems Seat allocation occurs over many rounds Formula uses division (Divisor methods) 18

Largest remainder systems All utilize an electoral quota (# of votes that translate into a seat) Seat allocation occurs in two rounds In first round, parties meeting the quota are awarded seats The (quota) * (# seats awarded) is subtracted from each party s total vote In second round parties left with the greatest number of votes are awarded any leftover seats 19

About Quotas First, the total valid vote is calculated. The formulas are then: Hare quota (Hamilton s Method): votes seats Droop quota: votes seats+1 +1 Imperiali quota: votes seats+2 Drop remainder for Droop quota, not for others. Note: Hare > Droop > Imperiali, and bigger quotas benefit smaller parties 20

Hare Example: 100 votes, 5 seats Quota =? Party Round 1 Seats won Round 2 Seats won Total A 36 B 31 C 15 D 12 E 6 Imperiali Example: 100 votes, 5 seats Quota =? Party Round 1 Seats won Round 2 Seats won Total A 36 B 31 C 15 D 12 E 6 21

Hare Example: 100 votes, 5 seats Quota = 20 Party Round 1 Seats won Round 2 Seats won Total A 36 B 31 C 15 D 12 E 6 Imperiali Example: 100 votes, 5 seats Quota =? Party Round 1 Seats won Round 2 Seats won Total A 36 B 31 C 15 D 12 E 6 22

Hare Example: 100 votes, 5 seats Quota = 20 Party Round 1 Seats won Round 2 Seats won Total A 36 1 B 31 1 C 15 0 D 12 0 E 6 0 Imperiali Example: 100 votes, 5 seats Quota =? Party Round 1 Seats won Round 2 Seats won Total A 36 B 31 C 15 D 12 E 6 23

Hare Example: 100 votes, 5 seats Quota = 20 Party Round 1 Seats won Round 2 Seats won Total A 36 1 16 B 31 1 11 C 15 0 15 D 12 0 12 E 6 0 6 Imperiali Example: 100 votes, 5 seats Quota =? Party Round 1 Seats won Round 2 Seats won Total A 36 B 31 C 15 D 12 E 6 24

Hare Example: 100 votes, 5 seats Quota = 20 Party Round 1 Seats won Round 2 Seats won Total A 36 1 16 1 2 B 31 1 11 0 1 C 15 0 15 1 1 D 12 0 12 1 1 E 6 0 6 0 0 Imperiali Example: 100 votes, 5 seats Quota =? Party Round 1 Seats won Round 2 Seats won Total A 36 B 31 C 15 D 12 E 6 25

Hare Example: 100 votes, 5 seats Quota = 20 Party Round 1 Seats won Round 2 Seats won Total A 36 1 16 1 2 B 31 1 11 0 1 C 15 0 15 1 1 D 12 0 12 1 1 E 6 0 6 0 0 Imperiali Example: 100 votes, 5 seats Quota = 14.2 Party Round 1 Seats won Round 2 Seats won Total A 36 2 8 0 2 B 31 2 3 0 2 C 15 1 1 0 1 D 12 0 12 0 0 E 6 0 6 0 0 26

Highest Average systems Parties vote totals are divided by a series of divisors to form a table of averages If there are k seats to be allocated, the seats are assigned to the parties with the k highest numbers in the table There are two commonly used sequences of numbers (Sainte Laguë is rare) D Hondt (Jefferson s Method): 1, 2, 3, 4, 5, 6, 7,... Modified Sainte Laguë: 1.4, 3, 5, 7, 9,... Sainte Laguë (Webster s Method): 1, 3, 5, 7, 9,... 27

D Hondt Example: 100 votes, 5 seats Party Votes/1 Votes/2 Votes/3 Total A 36 18 12 B 31 15.5 10.3 C 15 7.5 5 D 12 6 4 E 6 3 2 Sainte Laguë Example: 100 votes, 5 seats Party Votes/1 Votes/3 Votes/5 Total A 36 12 7.2 B 31 10.3 6.2 C 15 5 3 D 12 4 2.4 E 6 2 1.2 28

D Hondt Example: 100 votes, 5 seats Party Votes/1 Votes/2 Votes/3 Total A 36 18 12 B 31 15.5 10.3 C 15 7.5 5 D 12 6 4 E 6 3 2 Sainte Laguë Example: 100 votes, 5 seats Party Votes/1 Votes/3 Votes/5 Total A 36 12 7.2 B 31 10.3 6.2 C 15 5 3 D 12 4 2.4 E 6 2 1.2 29

D Hondt Example: 100 votes, 5 seats Party Votes/1 Votes/2 Votes/3 Total A 36 18 12 2 B 31 15.5 10.3 2 C 15 7.5 5 1 D 12 6 4 0 E 6 3 2 0 Sainte Laguë Example: 100 votes, 5 seats Party Votes/1 Votes/3 Votes/5 Total A 36 12 7.2 B 31 10.3 6.2 C 15 5 3 D 12 4 2.4 E 6 2 1.2 30

D Hondt Example: 100 votes, 5 seats Party Votes/1 Votes/2 Votes/3 Total A 36 18 12 2 B 31 15.5 10.3 2 C 15 7.5 5 1 D 12 6 4 0 E 6 3 2 0 Sainte Laguë Example: 100 votes, 5 seats Party Votes/1 Votes/3 Votes/5 Total A 36 12 7.2 B 31 10.3 6.2 C 15 5 3 D 12 4 2.4 E 6 2 1.2 31

D Hondt Example: 100 votes, 5 seats Party Votes/1 Votes/2 Votes/3 Total A 36 18 12 2 B 31 15.5 10.3 2 C 15 7.5 5 1 D 12 6 4 0 E 6 3 2 0 Sainte Laguë Example: 100 votes, 5 seats Party Votes/1 Votes/3 Votes/5 Total A 36 12 7.2 2 B 31 10.3 6.2 1 C 15 5 3 1 D 12 4 2.4 1 E 6 2 1.2 0 32

What are these different systems accomplishing? Different PR formulas minimize different standards of proportionality D Hondt (Jefferson) minimizes over-representation of the most represented party What does this mean? Party Votes Votes/2 Votes/3 Votes/4 seats A 60000 30000 20000 15000 4 B 28000 14000 1 C 12000 0 Total 100000 5 33

Party Votes Votes/2 Votes/3 Votes/4 seats A 60000 30000 20000 15000 4 B 28000 14000 1 C 12000 0 Total 100000 5 A has 60% of the vote, why not 3 seats? A s overrepresentation is 80% seats to 60% votes; 80 60 1.33 If B got another seat it would be overrepresented by 40 28 1.43 If C got another seat it would be overrepresented by 20 12 1.67 D Hondt chooses an allocation that minimizes this term 34

Indices of proportionality An index assigns a number to the outcome of an electoral system (vote/seat shares) that says something about how (dis)proportional the system is If DM=1 or DM= all formulas will yield the same outcome; small to intermediate DMs matter Different notions of proportionality will yield different indices; many formulas will conceptually characterize an index, and will minimize it D Hondt minimizes an index that is seat share-to-vote share ratio of the most over-represented party 35

Which index to choose? All indices use data consisting of i = 1,...,n total parties The vote shares v i of those parties (votes for party / total votes cast) And the seat shares s i of the parties (seats party wins / total seats allocated) Given v = (v 1,...,v n ) and s = (s 1,...,s n ) how would you construct an index of proportionality? 36

Loosemore-Hanby Index More indices Given a collection of vote shares v i and seat shares s i for parties i = 1,...,n i v i s i 2 This is always minimized by largest remainder with Hare quota (a.k.a. Hamilton s method) It s subject to all of the paradoxes that Hamilton s method is subject to (Alabama, population, new states, etc.) 37

Criticisms of Loosemore-Hansby i v i s i 2 Can you see any downsides to using an index like this (in addition to the fact that it suffers from paradoxes)? 38

Criticisms of Loosemore-Hansby i v i s i 2 It can t discriminate between a lot of parties having small vote-seat share differences and a few parties having big vote-seat differences How would you deal with that problem? 39

Gallagher (Least-Squares) Index i (v i s i ) 2 2 This index penalizes large disproportionalities more than small ones It still suffers from paradoxes (as does every index that is based on absolute, rather than relative, vote-seat differences) 40

Sainte-Laguë Index Sainte-Laguë independently derived his formula (which is equivalent to Webster s method) by seeking to minimize the following index of proportionality Let S i be the number of seats i gets and V i the number of votes Let TS=total number of seats and TV=total number of votes i ( Si V i TS V i TV ) 2 What do S i V i and TS TV represent? 41

Two-tier districting It s commonly acknowledged that there is a trade-off between proportionality and constituency service Because there is a direct link between proportionality and DM Two-tier systems compensate by electing part of the legislature at large (or from a very large region), and part from smaller districts (the lower tier ) Used by most largest remainder systems and modified Sainte Laguë systems 42

How two-tier districting works For highest average systems, a proportion of the total number of seats are set aside for the second (e.g. national) tier After seats are allocated at the regional level, these remaining seats are used to top up parties who did not receive their fair (proportional) share of the district seats For largest remainder systems the % of second tier seats is not fixed, and equal the remainder seats that were left over after the first round of seat allocation in the regional districts 43

In-class question Suppose that there are two districts holding elections, using largest remainder with Droop quota ( votes +1 with remainder dropped). In seats+1 each district there are 100 votes total, 9 seats. District 1 District 2 Party 1 54 32 Party 2 40 42 Party 3 6 26 (1) In each district, allocate seats in 1 round according to Droop quota but don t allocate using the remainders (2) Now pool the vote totals across districts and allocate 18 seats using Droop and remainders (Droop =11) (3) How many upper tier (compensatory) seats does each party deserve? How does this compare to allocations without compensation? 44

Things to think about for your lab this week In 2012 Democrats received 1.4 million more votes for the House of Representatives than Republicans, but Republicans won the House by 234 to 201 What factors might have contributed to this disproportionality? How can we disentangle these various possible causes? 45