Phil 115, May 24, 2007 The threat of utilitarianism

Similar documents
Ethics Handout 18 Rawls, Classical Utilitarianism and Nagel, Equality

Phil 115, June 13, 2007 The argument from the original position: set-up and intuitive presentation and the two principles over average utility

RECONCILING LIBERTY AND EQUALITY: JUSTICE AS FAIRNESS. John Rawls s A Theory of Justice presents a theory called justice as fairness.

Do we have a strong case for open borders?

Normative Frameworks 1 / 35

Assignment to make up for missed class on August 29, 2011 due to Irene

Chapter 02 Business Ethics and the Social Responsibility of Business

John Rawls THEORY OF JUSTICE

Phil 115, June 20, 2007 Justice as fairness as a political conception: the fact of reasonable pluralism and recasting the ideas of Theory

Why Does Inequality Matter? T. M. Scanlon. Chapter 8: Unequal Outcomes. It is well known that there has been an enormous increase in inequality in the

24.03: Good Food 3/13/17. Justice and Food Production

Great comments! (A lot of them could be germs of term papers )

3. Because there are no universal, clear-cut standards to apply to ethical analysis, it is impossible to make meaningful ethical judgments.

VI. Rawls and Equality

IMPARTIAL JUSTICE: CONDITIONS AND IMPLICATIONS

At a time when political philosophy seemed nearly stagnant, John Rawls

Introduction to Equality and Justice: The Demands of Equality, Peter Vallentyne, ed., Routledge, The Demands of Equality: An Introduction

Distributive Justice Rawls

The Value of Equality and Egalitarianism. Lecture 3 Why not luck egalitarianism?

AN EGALITARIAN THEORY OF JUSTICE 1

UTILITARIANISM AND POPULATION ETHICS

Phil 115, May 25, 2007 Justice as fairness as reconstruction of the social contract

Philosophy 285 Fall, 2007 Dick Arneson Overview of John Rawls, A Theory of Justice. Views of Rawls s achievement:

Phil 116, April 5, 7, and 9 Nozick, Anarchy, State, and Utopia

II. Bentham, Mill, and Utilitarianism

Utilitarianism. Utilitarianism. Dr. Clea F. Rees. Centre for Lifelong Learning Cardiff University.

Chapter Two: Normative Theories of Ethics

Dr. Mohammad O. Hamdan

Phil 290, February 8, 2011 Christiano, The Constitution of Equality, Ch. 2 3

Paternalism. But, what about protecting people FROM THEMSELVES? This is called paternalism :

Utilitarianism. Utilitarianism. Dr. Clea F. Rees. Centre for Lifelong Learning Cardiff University.

Distributive Justice Rawls

Robert Nozick Equality, Envy, Exploitation, etc. (Chap 8 of Anarchy, State and Utopia 1974)

Chapter 4. Justice and the Law. Justice vs. Law. David Hume. Justice does not dictate a perfect world, but one in which people live up

FAIRNESS VERSUS WELFARE. Louis Kaplow & Steven Shavell. Thesis: Policy Analysis Should Be Based Exclusively on Welfare Economics

VALUING DISTRIBUTIVE EQUALITY CLAIRE ANITA BREMNER. A thesis submitted to the Department of Philosophy. in conformity with the requirements for

RAWLS DIFFERENCE PRINCIPLE: ABSOLUTE vs. RELATIVE INEQUALITY

Business Law 16th Edition TEST BANK Mallor Barnes Langvardt Prenkert McCrory

Session 20 Gerald Dworkin s Paternalism

Lecture 17 Consequentialism. John Stuart Mill Utilitarianism Mozi Impartial Caring

Introduction to Rawls on Justice and Rawls on utilitarianism. For THEORIES OF JUSTICE USD Fall, 2008 Richard Arneson

Topic 1: Moral Reasoning and ethical theory

In Defense of Liberal Equality

Justice, fairness and Equality. foundation and profound influence on the determination and administration of morality. As such,

Apple Inc. vs FBI A Jurisprudential Approach to the case of San Bernardino

Chapter 02 Business Ethics

Consequentialist Ethics

Phil 290, February 22, 2011 Christiano, The Constitution of Equality, Ch. 7

Is Rawls s Difference Principle Preferable to Luck Egalitarianism?

CHAPTER 1 PROLOGUE: VALUES AND PERSPECTIVES

The Entitlement Theory 1 Robert Nozick

Meena Krishnamurthy a a Assistant Professor, Department of Philosophy, Associate

Lecture 7 Act and Rule Utilitarianism. Based on slides 2011 Pearson Education, Inc. Publishing as Pearson Addison-Wesley

enforce people s contribution to the general good, as everyone naturally wants to do productive work, if they can find something they enjoy.

Handout 6: Utilitarianism

What s the Right Thing To Do?

Is A Paternalistic Government Beneficial for Society and its Individuals? By Alexa Li Ho Shan Third Year, Runner Up Prize

Contract law as fairness: a Rawlsian perspective on the position of SMEs in European contract law Klijnsma, J.G.

Introduction. Cambridge University Press Rawls's Egalitarianism Alexander Kaufman Excerpt More Information

Great Philosophers: John Rawls ( ) Brian Carey 13/11/18

Utilitarianism. John Stuart Mill

Criminal Justice Without Moral Responsibility: Addressing Problems with Consequentialism Dane Shade Hannum

Matthew Adler, a law professor at the Duke University, has written an amazing book in defense

Choice-Based Libertarianism. Like possessive libertarianism, choice-based libertarianism affirms a basic

VII. Aristotle, Virtue, and Desert

The public vs. private value of health, and their relationship. (Review of Daniel Hausman s Valuing Health: Well-Being, Freedom, and Suffering)

Politics between Philosophy and Democracy

John Rawls's Difference Principle and The Strains of Commitment: A Diagrammatic Exposition

Meeting Need NICOLE HASSOUN. Carnegie Mellon University ABSTRACT

John Stuart Mill ( ) Branch: Political philosophy ; Approach: Utilitarianism Over his own body and mind, the individual is sovereign

Aggregation and the Separateness of Persons

Social Contract Theory

THE ORIGINAL POSITION PHILOSOPHY

1 Justice as fairness, utilitarianism, and mixed conceptions

Consider Ethics: Theory, Readings, and Contemporary Issues Third Edition Bruce N. Waller. Copyright 2011 Pearson Education, Inc. All rights reserved.

S.L. Hurley, Justice, Luck and Knowledge, (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2003), 341 pages. ISBN: (hbk.).

ECON 4270 Distributive Justice Lecture 4: Rawls and liberal equality

Do we have a moral obligation to the homeless?

COMPARE AND CONTRAST CONSERVATISM AND SOCIALISM REFER TO BURKE AND MARX IN YOUR ANSWER

Between Equality and Freedom of Choice: Educational Policy for the Least Advantaged

The political problem of economic inequality and the perils of redistribution.

Economic Perspective. Macroeconomics I ECON 309 S. Cunningham

Utilitarianism and business ethics

CHAPTER 1 PROLOGUE: VALUES AND PERSPECTIVES

Rawls versus the Anarchist: Justice and Legitimacy

Can Negative Utilitarianism be Salvaged?

Ethical Basis of Welfare Economics. Ethics typically deals with questions of how should we act?

Chinese University of Hong Kong Second Lecture 2017 Jonathan Jacobs John Jay College of Criminal Justice/CUNY

What is Fairness? Allan Drazen Sandridge Lecture Virginia Association of Economists March 16, 2017

Democracy and Common Valuations

Political Obligation 3

Strategy. "Paternalism, Drugs, and the Nature of Sports" Paternalism. Soft Paternalism. Brown

A THEORY OF JUSTICE. Revised Edition JOHN RAWLS

A Rawlsian Perspective on Justice for the Disabled

Rawls, Williams, and Utilitarianism

Ross s view says that the basic moral principles are about prima facie duties. Ima Rossian

Justice as Fairness and the American Welfare Reform Debate

The Difference Principle in Rawls: Pragmatic or Infertile?

Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy

Equality of Resources. In discussing libertarianism, I distinguished two kinds of criticisms of

Transcription:

Phil 115, May 24, 2007 The threat of utilitarianism Review: Alchemy v. System According to the alchemy interpretation, Rawls s project is to convince everyone, on the basis of assumptions that he expects everyone to accept, that his conception of justice is correct. According to the system interpretation, by contrast, Rawls s project is to systematize our thinking about justice, and his conception of justice is part of that systematization. Why systematize? What moves Rawls to write A Theory of Justice, in brief, is his realization that political philosophy is in a state of profound crisis. The dominant political philosophy, Rawls notes, has been utilitarianism. Utilitarianism says that social institutions are just when they lead to the greatest sum of happiness. Utilitarianism has been dominant because is the only acceptably systematic conception of justice. But it is a conception with unacceptable substantive implications. Part of Rawls s aim in systematizing our thinking about justice, then, is to give us an alternative to utilitarianism: to give us an acceptably systematic theory of justice that is substantively acceptable. In other words, to give us a theory of justice that organizes, extends, and revises our particular judgments in certain ways, but does not overthrow them. Sidgwick on ordinary moral opinion: III:v:1 3: Begin with the commonsense idea that laws are just only if they avoid running counter to natural and normal expectations (p. 271). But this implies that established laws can never be unjust. Even manifestly unjust laws, such as laws protecting the property rights of slaveholders, are deemed just, so long as they have been around long enough. We then turn to the idea of Natural Rights as an independent standard by which to evaluate established laws. [B]ut it is difficult to find in Common Sense any definite agreement in the enumeration of these Natural Rights, still less any clear principles from which they can be systematically deduced (274). II:v:4: For example, it is often suggested that the role of law is to let people lead the lives they choose, by preventing others from interfering with them and enforcing their voluntary contracts. But: We believe it is permissible to restrict this freedom in the case of children and the mentally ill. Why? Because it is in their interest. But then the real principle seems to be, Laws should aim to make people as well off as possible. We think that it is sometimes just to restrict freedom of action when it annoys others even though it does not interfere with their own freedom of action. Sometimes freedom can be traded off against goods of other kinds.

How can this view account for the enforcement of contracts? The state s enforcement of a contract that I entered into at an earlier time may interfere with my will at a later time. Isn t this an interference with my freedom? II:v:5: At any rate, justice is thought to involve a just distribution not only of freedom, but also of other goods. What is the relevant principle for distributing other goods? It seems to be, that men ought to be rewarded in proportion to their deserts (279). II:v:6: But are we to apportion the reward to the effort made, or to the results attained (283)? The results attained may be in part the product of favorable circumstances and fortunate accidents. Or results may be due to natural talents, which were allowed to flower only by favorable conditions and good education. In what sense does one deserve reward for what results from dumb luck, entirely beyond one s control? Shall we say, then, that the reward should be proportionate to the amount of voluntary effort for a good end? (284). Determinists will claim that even this is beyond the control of individuals. Whether or not we are not determinists, it does not seem possible to separate in practice that part of a man s achievement which is due strictly to his free choice from that part which is due to the original gift of nature and to favouring circumstances (285). Even if we aim to requite voluntary services in proportion to their worth how are we to determine the worth of services provided? When people speak of the fair price of services, they often mean whatever price those services usually receive. So we are back to normal expectations. Should we say, then, that fair price equals market value under free competition? (i) What if I undersell something out of ignorance? On the one hand, it may not be unfair for the buyer to buy it at the price I ask. On the other hand, I did not receive what it was worth. So commonsense leads to a paradox in this case. (ii) Some services are valuable, but have no market price on account of the indirectness and uncertainty of their practical utility (287). (iii) People think it unjust to profiteer during emergencies. But then can it be fair for any class of persons to gain competitively by the unfavorable economic situation of another class with which they deal? (288) Where are we to draw the line? (iv) One s bargaining situation worsens as more people are willing to provide services of the same kind. But how can this lessen one s desert? (v) One s bargaining position worsens as one is more willing. Yet people aren t less deserving simply because they are more eager to please. (vi) One is apt to receive more if one caters to the tastes of the rich. In sum, our commonsense views about justice seem to be a total mess. III:xi,1: Commonsense makes judgments about which acts are just, and these judgments appear to be based on some general principles, which seem, at first, not to be utilitarian. The method of intuitionism, as Sidgwick calls it, holds that such principles can be thrown into scientific form.

III:xi:2: How do we distinguish scientific axioms from mere opinions? I: The terms of the proposition must be clear and precise. II: The self-evidence of the proposition must be ascertained by careful reflection. III: The propositions accepted as self-evident must be mutually consistent. Otherwise, one must be false. IV: The proposition must be generally affirmed. If there is no sign that the person I disagree with has made an error, then I cannot be certain of the proposition I initially affirmed. The principles of commonsense do not meet these conditions. The principles are usually vague. If we try to make them definite, we encounter all kinds of exceptions and disagreements, which commonsense does not help us to resolve. Utilitarianism: IV:i:1: By contrast to our commonsense thinking about justice, utilitarianism is systematic. Utilitarianism consists in a single, simple principle: that the conduct which, under any given circumstances, is objectively right, is that which will produce the greatest amount of happiness on the whole; that is, taking into account all whose happiness is affected by the conduct (411). When applied to the special case that interests us, namely the justice of social institutions, utilitarianism says that institutions are just when they produce the greatest sum of happiness. By greatest happiness, Sidgwick means the greatest possible surplus of pleasure over pain. The relationship between utilitarianism and intuitionism: IV:i:2: Sidgwick s strategy to convince intuitionists that they ought to be utilitarians has both a negative and a positive part. The negative part is to show that commonsense is a mess. The positive part is to show that utilitarianism naturally systematizes our thinking about justice. When we need to explain exceptions, draw definite boundaries, resolve conflict and disagreement, Sidgwick suggests, we turn instinctively to utilitarianism. Common sense may be unconsciously Utilitarian (424). However, Rawls worries that the utilitarian systematization of common sense will contradict some of our most dearly held beliefs about justice. For example, utilitarianism implies that it can be just to curtail the liberty of a minority for the benefit of the majority.

Sidgwick leaves us with the following picture: Particular judgments Particular consequences of common sense of utilitarianism (e.g., slavery and which radically and implausibly conflict with (e.g., slavery and are unjust) are sometimes just) the effort to systematize which leads us to which entails utilitarianism as a theory of justice Rawls does not think that the choice of utilitarianism is a foregone conclusion, even in the absence of a viable systematic alternative. He thinks that it might be reasonable to stick with intuitionism, as unsystematic as it is. But Rawls thinks that we are not saddled with this choice between utilitarianism and intuitionism. There is a third alternative. There is a way of systematizing our thinking about justice that does not do such violence to our particular judgments. which moderately and plausibly revises and extends Particular judgments of common sense (e.g., slavery and are clearly unjust, but what sort of economic inqualities are unjust is uncertain) Particular consequences of Rawls s principles (e.g., slavery and are still clearly unjust and so are economic inequalities that do not maximize the worst-off position) the effort to systematize which leads us to which entails Rawls s two principles as a theory of justice Rawls s diagnosis of the problem with utilitarianism: A line of thought that leads to utilitarianism: Think about what it is rational for me, as an individual to do. A natural thought is that it is rational for me to maximize the satisfaction of my desires over the course of my life.

This explains why, within my life, I may balance losses at one time against gains at another time. Thus, it is rational for me to endure the pain and inconvenience of the visit to the dentist today, to avoid the greater pain and inconvenience of losing my teeth in the future. If this principle is rational for a single person, then why shouldn t it be right for a society of several people? Why treat satisfactions in the lives of different people as any different from satisfactions at different times in the life of a single individual? My choice Me today Me for the rest of society Total Go to the dentist Serious pain of dental Mild pleasure from eating Net benefit treatment today. crunchy food for all the rest Don t go Avoid this serious pain today. of my days. Miss this mild pleasure for all the rest of my days. Net loss Society s choice Minority The rest of society Total Ban minority religion A few have their deepest Many avoid mild Net benefit desires frustrated discomfort. Permit all religions A few have their deepest desires satisfied Many feel mild discomfort. Net loss What underlies utilitarianism, then, is no less than a certain conception of persons and society. This view of social cooperation is the consequence of extending to society the principle of choice for one man, and then, to make this extension work, conflating all persons into one through the imaginative acts of the impartial sympathetic spectator. Utilitarianism does not take seriously the distinction between persons (24). How do we take seriously this distinction between persons? We imagine a situation in which separate, independent persons, each with his own goals and aspirations, are to decide on principles of justice that will govern the distribution of the benefits and burdens of their cooperation. It is plausible to suppose that principles that were acceptable to each and every one of these individuals would be principles that took seriously the distinction between persons. This is what the original position is supposed to model. Utilitarianism as a teleological theory In teleological theories, the good is defined independently from the right, and then the right is defined as that which maximizes the good (21-22). Utilitarianism is what Rawls calls a teleological theory. Rawls s justice as fairness is not teleological. (So it is, by definition, deontological.) Justice as fairness is not teleological on the second count. It does not call for us to maximize the satisfaction of rational desire. Justice as fairness is also not teleological on the first count. It defines the good in terms of the right. The principles of justice put limits on which satisfactions have value; they impose restrictions on what are reasonable conceptions of one s good (27). Thus, if I desire to subject others to lesser liberty, which violates the first principle of justice, then the satisfaction of my desire carries no weight at all.

By contrast, for utilitarianism, the satisfaction of my desire that others have lesser liberty counts like any other satisfaction in utilitarian calculations (although, of course, it must be weighed against desires that others may have for greater liberty).