Revealing Expressiveness: The Demand Revealing Process with Expressive Voters

Similar documents
"Efficient and Durable Decision Rules with Incomplete Information", by Bengt Holmström and Roger B. Myerson

Market Failure: Compared to What?

I assume familiarity with multivariate calculus and intermediate microeconomics.

Name: Economics 854 Final Prof. Bryan Caplan Spring, Instructions:

Electing the President. Chapter 12 Mathematical Modeling

Gordon Tullock and the Demand-Revealing Process

I assume that you have taken Public Choice I (Econ 852), and are familiar with basic calculus and econometrics.

Do Voters Have a Duty to Promote the Common Good? A Comment on Brennan s The Ethics of Voting

Voting and Electoral Competition

Prof. Bryan Caplan Econ 812

KNOW THY DATA AND HOW TO ANALYSE THEM! STATISTICAL AD- VICE AND RECOMMENDATIONS

Chapter 14. The Causes and Effects of Rational Abstention

STATE-CONTROLLED ELECTIONS: WHY THE CHARADE

Supporting Information Political Quid Pro Quo Agreements: An Experimental Study

What is The Probability Your Vote will Make a Difference?

International Cooperation, Parties and. Ideology - Very preliminary and incomplete

Prof. Bryan Caplan Econ 854

On the Rationale of Group Decision-Making

THE PRO S AND CON S OF THE ELECTORAL COLLEGE SYSTEM

VOTING ON INCOME REDISTRIBUTION: HOW A LITTLE BIT OF ALTRUISM CREATES TRANSITIVITY DONALD WITTMAN ECONOMICS DEPARTMENT UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA

policy-making. footnote We adopt a simple parametric specification which allows us to go between the two polar cases studied in this literature.

Prof. Bryan Caplan Econ 854

LOGROLLING. Nicholas R. Miller Department of Political Science University of Maryland Baltimore County Baltimore, Maryland

The Budget Battle in the Republican-Obama Battleground

NBER WORKING PAPER SERIES. Working Paper No. i63. NATIONAL BUREAU OF ECONOMIC RESEARCH 1050 Massachusetts Avenue Cambridge MA

Reducing Rent Seeking by Providing Prizes to the Minority. Amihai Glazer Department of Economics University of California, Irvine

Sincere Versus Sophisticated Voting When Legislators Vote Sequentially

Mechanism design: how to implement social goals

Part III Immigration Policy: Introduction

John Rawls THEORY OF JUSTICE

Phil 108, April 24, 2014 Climate Change

Reply to Caplan: On the Methodology of Testing for Voter Irrationality

The Economic Effects of Judicial Selection Dr. John A. Dove Faulkner Lecture Outline

Voters Interests in Campaign Finance Regulation: Formal Models

Political Economics II Spring Lectures 4-5 Part II Partisan Politics and Political Agency. Torsten Persson, IIES

Understanding democracy (LOI)

Sincere versus sophisticated voting when legislators vote sequentially

Voter Participation with Collusive Parties. David K. Levine and Andrea Mattozzi

Utilitarianism, Game Theory and the Social Contract

Economic Growth and the Interests of Future (and Past and Present) Generations: A Comment on Tyler Cowen

Phil 290, February 8, 2011 Christiano, The Constitution of Equality, Ch. 2 3

Mapping Policy Preferences with Uncertainty: Measuring and Correcting Error in Comparative Manifesto Project Estimates *

Constitutional Political Economy 1

SOCI 423: THEORIES OF SOCIAL DEVELOPMENT

Ethical Considerations on Quadratic Voting

Random tie-breaking in STV

Prof. Panu Poutvaara University of Munich and Ifo Institute for Economic Research

Party Ideology and Policies

Does Pluralism Provide Equitable Representation? Critiques of the By-Product Model

David Rosenblatt** Macroeconomic Policy, Credibility and Politics is meant to serve

Introduction to Political Economy Problem Set 3

participation Jonathan Baron Democracy is a human invention, a design that serves certain functions. My hypothesis is that

Partisan Advantage and Competitiveness in Illinois Redistricting

1 Electoral Competition under Certainty

CRITIQUE OF CAPLAN S THE MYTH OF THE RATIONAL VOTER

Chapter 6 Online Appendix. general these issues do not cause significant problems for our analysis in this chapter. One

The Provision of Public Goods, and the Matter of the Revelation of True Preferences: Two Views

Electing the President. Chapter 17 Mathematical Modeling

3. Public Choice in a Direct Democracy

A Cost Benefit Analysis of Voting

Are Second-Best Tariffs Good Enough?

U.S. Foreign Policy: The Puzzle of War

EFFICIENCY OF COMPARATIVE NEGLIGENCE : A GAME THEORETIC ANALYSIS

Information Aggregation in Voting with Endogenous Timing

1. Introduction. Michael Finus

4 However, devolution would have better served the people of Wales if a better voting system had been used. At present:

ATTACKING POVERTY: WHAT IS THE VALUE ADDED OF A HUMAN RIGHTS APPROACH?

Optimal Voting Turnouts

Public Finance and Public Policy: Responsibilities and Limitations of Government,

INTERNATIONAL ECONOMICS, FINANCE AND TRADE Vol. II - Strategic Interaction, Trade Policy, and National Welfare - Bharati Basu

Modeling Conflict. Thomas Chadefaux Chair of Sociology, in particular of Modeling and Simulation

VOTING PARADOXES: A Socratic Dialogue

Empirical research on economic inequality Lecture notes on theories of justice (preliminary version) Maximilian Kasy

Prof. Bryan Caplan Econ 854

Social Choice Theory. Denis Bouyssou CNRS LAMSADE

Example 8.2 The Economics of Terrorism: Externalities and Strategic Interaction

The Political Economy of Social Desirability Bias:

Problems with Group Decision Making

Benchmarks for text analysis: A response to Budge and Pennings

The public vs. private value of health, and their relationship. (Review of Daniel Hausman s Valuing Health: Well-Being, Freedom, and Suffering)

Robust Political Economy. Classical Liberalism and the Future of Public Policy

Response to the Report Evaluation of Edison/Mitofsky Election System

In Defense of Liberal Equality

Michael Laver and Ernest Sergenti: Party Competition. An Agent-Based Model

Remarks on the Political Economy of Inequality

Modernizing Canada s Electoral System: Instant Runoff Voting as the Best Alternative. By Maxime Dubé, as an individual

Controversy Liberalism, Democracy and the Ethics of Votingponl_

Why Does Inequality Matter? T. M. Scanlon. Chapter 8: Unequal Outcomes. It is well known that there has been an enormous increase in inequality in the

CARLETON ECONOMIC PAPERS

A New Proposal on Special Majority Voting 1 Christian List

Median voter theorem - continuous choice

Analysis of AV Voting System Rick Bradford, 24/4/11

European Community Studies Association Newsletter (Spring 1999) INSTITUTIONAL ANALYSES OF EUROPEAN UNION GEORGE TSEBELIS

RATIONAL CHOICE AND CULTURE

PRIVATIZATION AND INSTITUTIONAL CHOICE

Decision Making Procedures for Committees of Careerist Experts. The call for "more transparency" is voiced nowadays by politicians and pundits

Mathematics and Democracy: Designing Better Voting and Fair-Division Procedures*

The political economy of public sector reforms: Redistributive promises, and transfers to special interests

HANDBOOK OF SOCIAL CHOICE AND VOTING Jac C. Heckelman and Nicholas R. Miller, editors.

Third Party Voting: Vote One s Heart or One s Mind?

Transcription:

Revealing Expressiveness: The Demand Revealing Process with Expressive Voters Eric Crampton ecrampto@gmu.edu University of Canterbury Draft June 2003. Do not cite without permission. The author thanks David Bernstein, Bryan Caplan, Ed Clarke, Tyler Cowen, Fred Foldvary, Nicolas Tideman, Gordon Tullock, and participants at the 2003 Public Choice Meetings for useful comments and discussion. The standard disclaimer applies.

I. Introduction The demand revealing process (DRP) enjoys a rich tradition in the public choice literature as a superior mechanism for inducing truthful preference revelation and thereby achieving optimal provision of public goods. Tideman and Tullock s (1976) application of the Clarke (1971) procedure as a social choice mechanism sparked a period of vociferous debate over the DRP, including a supplemental edition of Public Choice (1977). Interest in the mechanism has waxed and waned in the period since. While theoretical objections have been raised against the use of the DRP, proponents of the DRP have worked to solidify its foundations. Margolis (1982) hints at a more fundamental problem facing the real world application of the DRP. Specifically, the individual voter faces low expected Clarke taxes should he misrepresent his demand schedule. While Tullock (1982) critiques Margolis s thought experiment, the Margolis objection remains trenchant. We argue here that Margolis s objection is stronger than he anticipated. Not only may individuals have an instrumental interest in misrepresenting their preferences, but more importantly, the low probability that any voter will be required to pay Clarke taxes makes the mechanism highly vulnerable to the elicitation of expressive preferences. After revisiting the DRP mechanism and the expressive voting framework, we argue that the DRP is undesirable as a social choice mechanism because of expressive voting considerations. 1

II. The Demand Revealing Process As noted earlier, the demand revealing process enjoys a rich history in public choice and should be well familiar to the reader. Consequently, only a brief overview of the mechanism is here presented. While several variants on the process exist, the fundamentals of the mechanism are similar across the different applications (see Green and Laffont, 1977; Margolis, 1983). The mechanisms seek to induce truthful preference revelation as either a Nash or dominant strategy. The simplest case, the pivot mechanism demonstrated in Tideman and Tullock (1976), illustrates the principles involved. In this case, voters are offered a binary choice either to implement a public expenditure project of fixed size, or to reject the project s implementation. For example, voters in the Washington DC metropolitan area might be asked whether or not the metro transit system should be extended through Tyson s Corner to Dulles International Airport at a cost of a fixed number of billions of dollars. Obviously, voters will differ on their valuation of such a project. In the DRP, all voters are asked to submit their bids indicating by how much they prefer that the project obtain or be scuttled. All bids for and against the project are totaled. If the dollar value of bids favoring the project outweighs the dollar value of bids in opposition, the rail line is built. Any voter whose bid was necessary for the outcome to obtain, however, is charged a Clarke tax equal to the amount of the voter s bid that proved necessary in changing the outcome. Suppose that I bid $1000 in favor of the project and that the total value of bids supporting the project outweighed the total value of bids against the project by $900. Had I bid any amount lower than $100, the project would not have been undertaken; 2

when my bid was added, the project received net support and was implemented. In this case, I would be charged a tax of $100 the amount of my bid necessary to changing the outcome. We can see that truthful preference revelation should be optimal in this framework. If I truly value the project at $1000, underrevealing my valuation cannot improve my situation and may lead to cases in which the project is not undertaken but in which I would have been willing to pay the amount required to ensure that the project would obtain. Similarly, overvaluation cannot improve my situation but may lead to situations in which I pay more for the public good than the value I place upon it. The pivot mechanism here presented can be extended for choice in continuous space as well; the interested reader is referred back to Tideman and Tullock s original contribution. The disposition of the taxes collected through the operation of the system has engendered some amount of controversy. In the Tideman and Tullock framework, all collected taxes must be wasted in order to avoid incentive effects that might perturb truthful preference revelation. For example, if all taxes collected are to be used to benefit the local homeless shelter and I value (deplore) the activities undertaken by the homeless shelter, I may overreveal (underreveal) my preferences. Of course, even that waste may not be without incentive consequences; it is certainly plausible that some people oppose waste as such (and that some smaller number prefer waste as such) and will attenuate (accentuate) their votes as a consequence. Tideman and Tullock (1976, 1156) note that the Clarke taxes collected will be quite small, so resource waste will prove minimal. They write: 3

Thus, if the citizens of the United States were voting on the annual federal budget, the grand total of all the Clarke taxes charged would be in the neighborhood of $2,000, or about one-thousandth of a penny per person. Bailey (1997) presents a mechanism whereby even this small level of waste can be avoided. While the low level of taxes collected reduces the inefficiencies directly inherent in the use of the DRP, it opens the system to a potentially more damaging critique: when no voter is decisive, all voters are expressive. III. Expressive Voting A recurrent problem in the public choice literature centers on the rationality of voting. Strictly speaking, the expected benefits of voting can never outweigh the costs of doing so. Even if an individual voter truly values the election of Candidate A over Candidate B by a million dollars, the odds that that voter will prove decisive in any reasonably sized electorate approach nil. 1 Consequently, any real costs involved in voting make the voting act irrational from the perspective of an income-maximizing voter. Brennan and Lomasky (1993) solve the problem of the rationality of voting but, in doing so, bring forth a much more challenging problem. Because the odds that any individual voter will prove decisive are lower than the odds of winning the lottery, instrumental interests can explain neither the act of voting nor the content of the vote. If we rely on non-instrumental mechanisms to get voters to the polls, we can hardly expect 1 See Mulligan and Hu nter (2003) fo r detailed analysis of the frequency of pivotal votes. They trenchantly note Fu ture empirical research could also investigate the prevalence of votes in uncontested elections these were omitted from our calculations but are conspicuous in our data and probably relevant to the theory of voting. (51). Expressive voting theory readily explains the anomaly. 4

them to put on their instrumental thinking cap once they get into the voting booth. Instead, voters engage expressive preferences both in the decision to vote and in the decision of for whom to vote. Expressive voting theory holds that voters maximize utility over both instrumental and non-instrumental factors. Instrumental preferences here refer to positively signed arguments in the utility function that provide an increase in utility if policy X is enacted as legislation. Expressive preferences, by contrast, are those arguments in the utility function that cause an increase in utility simply by the act of voting for policy X, regardless of whether X actually obtains as a result of the election. For example, a worker in the oil industry would see his instrumental interests advanced if arctic drilling restrictions were lifted; if that same worker were also an environmentalist, however, voting against the lifting of drilling restrictions may generate expressive benefits for him. Since any instrumental benefits from voting accrue only with an infinitesimal probability (equal to the probability that the individual voter will be decisive), non-instrumental expressive benefits will surely trump instrumental benefits in the voting calculus. Voters in any reasonably-sized electorate effectively make their electoral choices behind a veil of insignificance. 2 Expressive voting severs any tie that might exist between democraticallyapproved policies and efficient outcomes. Indeed, many voters can quite rationally vote for policies that lie directly in opposition to their narrowly instrumental interests if they derive expressive benefits from supporting those policies. As Caplan (2000, 2001) 2 Bren nan an d Lomasky (1993, 124, 224) make first u se of th e term, though Bren nan an d Hamlin (2000) attribute the term to Hartmut Kliemt. 5

argues, voters in this context can readily be viewed as rationally irrational. The lack of any decisive connection between the voter s choice and policy outcomes allows any voter to costlessly entertain whatever biased model of the world they prefer. Caplan specifies that voters have preferences over beliefs about the world. While biased beliefs prove quite costly in an individual s day-to-day life, 3 biased beliefs in the political realm can be entirely costless. It costs the individual voter nothing to believe that tariffs make Americans better off; the individual voter is never decisive in implementing policy. Voters can then rationally hold beliefs that are inconsistent with reality; they are rationally irrational. IV. Expressive Voting in the Demand Revealing Process Caplan (2003) demonstrates that expressive voting can be the cause of significant political failure in democratic majority voting. Electoral competition pushes candidates to compete in expressive policy space, with the standard median voter result obtaining within that expressive policy space. Biases in expressive voter preferences will lead median voter outcomes to diverge significantly from efficient results. Expressive voters hold preferences over beliefs in policy space that they individually find optimal, but collectively cause serious consequences. While Caplan restricts his analysis to standard majority rule settings, we argue that his critique applies a fortiori within the demand revealing process. Within the majority rule framework, each person can cast but one vote. Within the DRP, each voter 3 Imagine, for instance, the costs of holding the belief that a large dose of ars enic is the appropriate cure for a headache. Public opinion on questions of economic policy are frequently as wrong, but individuals do not personally bear th e co sts of such beliefs as th ey are not d ecisive in s eeing th ose beliefs tu rned into policy. See Caplan (2002). 6

can cast a number of votes that is potentially unbounded. Margolis (1982) hints at this problem, but is prevented from full pursuit of it because Brennan and Lomasky (1993) had not yet been written. Margolis asks whether voters might not be willing to spend the penny. He sets up a thought experiment in which voters are asked to reveal their preferences over the level of public expenditure on some public good. The typical voter bidding his marginal valuation will face a Clarke Tax equivalent to 1/100,000 of a penny and will shift the outcome by about $20 towards his desired level of aggregate spending. Margolis argues that a voter in that context should be willing to spend the penny overreveal his preference in order to push the outcome much closer to his desired level of spending, but still (expectationally) incur a Clarke tax of only a penny. In his example, a voter bidding a thousand times more than valuation incurs a huge percentage increase in his Clarke tax; but that tax still amounts to only a penny while the aggregate outcome moves $20,000 closer to his desired level of spending rather than only $20 closer. Margolis s argument hinges on the low probability that any individual voter will prove decisive or, if decisive, will not have changed the outcome by enough to be liable to a very large tax. This framework is intrinsic to the DRP, as noted in Tideman and Tullock (1976, quoted above). The problem becomes all the greater when we consider expressive voters. Introducing expressive voters into the DRP thoroughly undermines whatever efficiency properties had been claimed for the procedure. Margolis asks if voters might not be willing to spend the penny. Voters are willing to incur rather substantial costs to get to the ballot box, costs far in excess of the aforementioned penny. Given the low probability of decisiveness at the DRP ballot box, expressive preferences will be as 7

important in determining the voter s decision as in majoritarian elections. However, the aggregation of preferences will lead to worse outcomes when policies are measured within intrinsic benefit space. Caplan (2002) shows not only persistent biases in voter beliefs about economics, but that these biases coalesce systematically around expressively-salient foci (antibusiness and anti-foreign, for example). Budge et al (2002) find that party platforms exhibit unidirectionality on many policy dimensions. 4 If expressive preferences were normally distributed with an expected value corresponding to the voter s instrumental interests, there would be little cause for concern; expressive preferences would cancel each other out in that case. Persistent bias in expressive preferences, on the other hand, will lead to biased outcomes under either form of preference aggregation. The DRP will magnify biases in outcomes caused by expressive voting. While the model here presented is narrative rather than formal, it is illustrative. Specify that voters derive expressive benefits that are increasing in the size of their demonstrated commitment to the issue. In majoritarian elections, each voter can only vote once; the voting mechanism ignores the intensity of the expressive preference. Under a demand revealing system, by contrast, voters can use the size of their bids as a means of expressing the intensity of their expressive preferences. Consequently, the voters with 4 Budge et al code political party manifestos by the percentage of s tatements falling into each of 56 issue categories, most of which are unipolar in nature. For example, they code only an environmental issue category; not pro and con environmental categories. They write This is because the texts themselves are one-positional. The actual coding categories are theoretically guided but inductively derived basically formed by grouping related sentences in the text and so they reflect the textual practice of only endors ing the obvious position on each issue being against environmental destruction, for example, but all for a hard line on law and order. (Laver and Garry 1998, 12) The coding scheme thus directly reflects party assumption s th at there is only o ne tenable policy on each issue. (Bu dge 2002, 79-81) 8

the strongest expressive preferences will have the greatest impact in deciding the outcome of the election. Consider the following example. Voters are asked to determine whether an environmental program should be undertaken. All voters share identical instrumental preferences. Specifically, the program imposes net costs of $10 on all voters measured in instrumental space. Each voter, operating instrumentally, should bid $10 against the project. Forty percent of the voters receive expressive benefits from registering their support for the program. These voters receive $1 in expressive benefits for bidding $100 in favor of the project. Since the electorate is large, no voter is likely to prove decisive. Note that if any voter were decisive, he would vote against the project as the $10 in net intrinsic costs outweighs the $1 in expressive benefits. However, given the veil of insignificance separating voters from the direct consequences of their actions at the ballot box, each of these expressive voters bids the $100 in favor of the project s implementation. Note that none of these voters will then prove decisive: the project is approved by a wide margin. For any reasonably-sized electorate, the project will be supported by far more than the $100 difference that would require the payment of Clarke taxes. No Clarke taxes are collected, and an inferior result obtains. Expressive benefits of $(0.4*N) are generated at the cost of ($10*N) in instrumental costs. 5 Each and every voter in this case, if he were given the choice unilaterally to maintain or scrap the program, would end the program. And, in a majority rule setting, the project would fail. 5 No wh ere should the argument be construed as implying that expressive preferences are not real preferences, nor that the utility derived therefrom should be discounted. Inefficiency stems from the prisoner s dilemma nature of the voting environment, not from any ephemeral nature of expressive utility. 9

More realistically, voters enjoy heterogeneous expressive preferences. While expressive preferences are biased in particular directions, individual voters feel more or less strongly about each issue. Under the demand revealing process, voters with the strongest expressive preferences are given the greatest weight. Political failure will be magnified. Indeed, it is not inconceivable that bids could range into the millions of dollars if the probability of decisiveness proves low. While this could be bounded by insisting that voters post a bond against the possibility that their votes prove decisive, 6 individual voters presumably could insure against such eventuality given the low probability of decisiveness. The insurance company would then post the bond on behalf of the individual. Absent insurance, we should still expect that expressive preferences will carry greater weight, unless expressive voters face greater financial constraints against bond posting than do instrumental voters. Since expected Clarke taxes remain quite low, the bonding requirement only restricts the magnitude of the bid to an amount dictated by one s personal wealth and risk aversion. V. Conclusion The demand revealing process provides an interesting and relatively new mechanism for aggregating preferences and arriving at optimal policy outcomes, when that process is restricted in application to matters utterly bereft of expressive content. For example, it might enjoy productive use for decision making within a corporate board of directors. 7 As a method of making social choices, however, the procedure is quite 6 Nicolaus Tideman, personal correspondence. 7 Note, however, Attiyeh et al (2000), who find the mechanism fails to work under the simplest experimental conditions. 10

undesirable if voters are expressive. Margolis s (1982) worry that voters might spend the penny to magnify the effect of their vote becomes quite troubling when those same voters might spend the dollar to gain larger expressive benefits from their vote. Restricted in application to small group settings where the probability of decisiveness remains high, or to settings where expressive preferences are unlikely to come into play, the DRP may prove greatly beneficial. In more normal voting environments, majority rule remains preferable. 11

VI. Bibliography Attiyeh, Greg, Robert Franciosi, and R. Mark Isaac. 2000. Experiments with the pivot process for providing public goods. Public Choice 102 (95-114). Bailey, Martin J. 1997. The demand revealing process: To distribute the surplus. Public Choice 91 (107-126). Brennan, Geoffrey and Loren Lomasky. 1993. Democracy & Decision: The Pure Theory of Electoral Preference. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Budge, Ian. 2002. Theory and Measurement of Party Policy Positions. pp. 75-90 in Budge, Ian, Hans-Dieter Klingemann, et al., Mapping Policy Preferences: Estimates for Parties, Electors, and Governments, 1945-1998. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Caplan, Bryan. 2000. Rational Irrationality: A Framework for the Neoclassical- Behavioral Debate. Eastern Economic Journal (26) 191-211. Caplan, Bryan. 2001. Rational Ignorance vs. Rational Irrationality. Kyklos (54) 3-26. Caplan, Bryan. 2002. Systematically Biased Beliefs about Economics: Robust Evidence of Judgmental Anomalies from the Survey of Americans and Economists on the Economy. Economic Journal (112) 433-58. Caplan, Bryan. 2003. The Logic of Collective Belief. Rationality and Society (forthcoming). Clarke, E.H. 1971. Multipart Pricing of Public Goods. Public Choice (11) 17-33. Green, J. and J. Laffont. 1976. Characterization of satisfactory mechanisms for the revelation of preferences for public goods. Econometrica (45) Margolis, Howard. 1982. A thought experiment on demand-revealing mechanisms. Public Choice (38) 87-91. Margolis, Howard. 1983. A note on demand-revealing. Public Choice (40) 217-25. Mulligan, Casey B. and Charles G. Hunter. 2003. The empirical frequency of a pivotal vote. Public Choice (116) 31-54. Tideman, Nicolaus and Gordon Tullock. 1976. A New and Superior Process for Making Social Choices. Journal of Political Economy (84) 1145-59. Tullock, Gordon. 1982 More thought about demand revealing. Public Choice (38) 167-70. 12