DEFENDING EQUILIBRIUM-ADJUSTMENT

Similar documents
u.s. Department of Justice

1 See, e.g., Zurcher v. Stanford Daily, 436 U.S. 547, 559 (1978) ( The Fourth Amendment has

United States Court of Appeals

United States v. Jones: The Foolish revival of the "Trespass Doctrine" in Addressing GPS Technology and the Fourth Amendment

Supreme Court Rules On GPS Trackers: Is It 1984 Yet? Legal Question of the Week Vol. 5, Number 2 January 27, 2012

United States Court of Appeals

By Jane Lynch and Jared Wagner

Divided Supreme Court Requires Warrants for Cell Phone Location Data

Body Snatchers. Heidi Reamer Anderson*

THE FOURTH AMENDMENT AND NEW TECHNOLOGIES: THE MISAPPLICATION OF ANALOGICAL REASONING

Secrecy, Intimacy, and Workable Rules: Justice Sotomayor Stakes Out the Middle Ground in United States v. Jones

United States v. Jones: GPS Monitoring, Property, and Privacy

KATZ V. UNITED STATES: BACK TO THE FUTURE?

United States Court of Appeals

Emerging Technology and the Fourth Amendment

Kyllo v. United States: Innovative or Originalist?

DRAFT [8-4-15] TUFTS UNIVERSITY EXPERIMENTAL COLLEGE FALL 2015

United States v. Jones: Fourth Amendment Applicability in the 21st Century

Petitioner, Respondent.

ORIGINALISM, PRECEDENT, AND JUDICIAL RESTRAINT

Location Privacy: The Legal Landscape. David L. Sobel Senior Counsel, EFF Stanford PNT Symposium October 29, 2014

Introduction to the Symposium on Judicial Takings

STATE OF MICHIGAN COURT OF APPEALS

Voluntary Disclosure of Information as a Proposed Standard for the Fourth Amendment's Third-Party Doctrine

When Enough is Enough: Location Tracking, Mosaic Theory, and Machine Learning

The Fourth Amendment in the Digital World: Do You Have an Expectation of Privacy on the Internet?

1 See U.S. CONST. amend. IV ( The right of the people to be secure in their persons, houses,

The Good Faith Exception is Good for Us. Jamesa J. Drake. On February 19, 2010, the Kentucky Court of Appeals decided Valesquez v.

SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES

COMMENTS DISTRICT OF COLUMBIA V. HELLER: THE INDIVIDUAL RIGHT TO BEAR ARMS

Surveillance Duration Doesn't Affect Privacy Expectations: An Empirical Test of the Mosaic Theory

RUTGERS LAW REVIEW. VOLUME 65 Summer 2013 NUMBER 4 INTRODUCTION. George C. Thomas III*

Unpacking the Dirtbox: Confronting Cell Phone Location Tracking with the Fourth Amendment

Texas Law Review Online Volume 97

A Conservative Rewriting Of The 'Right To Work'

The Interpretation/Construction Distinction in Constitutional Law: Annual Meeting of the AALS Section on Constitutional Law: Introduction

Justice Alito filed opinion concurring in the judgment, in which Justices Ginsburg, Breyer, and Kagan joined.

AN EXAMINATION OF THE COHERENCE OF FOURTH AMENDMENT JURISPRUDENCE

The Supreme Court and the Fourth Amendment -- A Wild Ride

357 (1967)) U.S. 752 (1969). 4 Id. at 763. In Chimel, the Supreme Court held that a search of the arrestee s entire house

Testimony of Kevin S. Bankston, Policy Director of New America s Open Technology Institute

No IN THE. LOS ROVELL DAHDA, Petitioner, v. UNITED STATES OF AMERICA, Respondent.

The GPS Tracking Case Fourth Amendment United States Constitution

298 SUFFOLK UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. XLVI:297

Re: AB 1327 (Gorell): Law enforcement should be required to obtain a warrant to use drones in California, except under exigent circumstances.

SCOTUSBLOG MEMORANDUM. Saturday, June 30, Re: End-of-Term Statistical Analysis October Term 2011

ELECTORAL INTEGRITY, DEPENDENCE CORRUPTION, AND WHAT S NEW UNDER THE SUN

Excerpt from Vol. 3, Issue 2 (Spring/Summer 2015)

SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES

Fordham Urban Law Journal

The Private Search Doctrine and the Evolution of Fourth Amendment Jurisprudence in the Face of New Technology: A Broad or Narrow Exception?

Interpreting the Constitution

What s So Special About Treaty Arbitration?: U.S. Supreme Court Confronts Its First International Investment Treaty Arbitration Case

IN THE SUPREME COURT OF THE STATE OF SOUTH DAKOTA, * * * * * * * *

Graham Alexander v. United States

UNITED STATES DISTRICT COURT EASTERN DISTRICT OF WISCONSIN DECISION AND ORDER DENYING DEFENDANT S MOTION TO SUPPRESS EVIDENCE (DKT. NO.

The Private Search Doctrine After Jones Andrew MacKie-Mason

ORIGINALISM AND PRECEDENT

PRAGMATISM AND PRIVACY

Comments. Siri, Can You Keep a Secret? A Balanced Approach to Fourth Amendment Principles and Location Data

The Real Issue In Fed. Circ. Dynamic Drinkware Decision

Of Inkblots and Originalism: Historical Ambiguity and the Case of the Ninth Amendment

Car-ving Out Notions of Privacy: The Impact of GPS Tracking and Why Maynard is a Move in the Right Direction

Scholarly Campbell University School of Law

California Law Review

Ch.9: The Judicial Branch

ARTIS V. DISTRICT OF COLUMBIA WHAT DID THE COURT ACTUALLY SAY?

The More Things Change: An Analysis of Recent Fourth Amendment Jurisprudence

2016 PA Super 84. Appeal from the Order April 25, 2014 In the Court of Common Pleas of Berks County Criminal Division at No(s): CP-06-CR

Sentencing May Change With 2 Kennedy Clerks On High Court

STATE OF OHIO ) IN THE COURT OF APPEALS NINTH JUDICIAL DISTRICT COUNTY OF SUMMIT ) DECISION AND JOURNAL ENTRY

Following You Here, There, and Everywhere; An Investigation of GPS Technology, Privacy, and the Fourth Amendment, 45 J. Marshall L. Rev.

In the Supreme Court of the United States

Cell Phone Location Tracking: Reforming the Standard to Reflect Modern Privacy Expectations

Testimony of Orin S. Kerr Professor, George Washington University Law School

State of New York Supreme Court, Appellate Division Third Judicial Department

Electronic Searches and Surveillance ( )

AEP v. Connecticut and the Future of the Political Question Doctrine

AP Gov Chapter 15 Outline

LEADING CASES I. CONSTITUTIONAL LAW

Nonmajority Opinions and Biconditional Rules

American Bar Association Criminal Justice Section 2017 William W. Greenhalgh Student Writing Competition Rules

Indiana Association of Professional Investigators November 16, 2017 Stephanie C. Courter

Congress, the Courts, and New Technologies: A Response to Professor Solove

sus PETITIONER'S MOTION TO TAKE JUDICIAL NOTICE MAR * MAR US TAX COURT gges t US TAX COURT 5:04 PM DENIS KLEINFELD, Petitioner,

No In the Supreme Court of the United States HECTOR ESCATON, PETITIONER RESPONDENT

UNITED STATES v. GRUBBS

Draft Principles of Scholarly Ethics

The Mosaic Theory of the Fourth Amendment

No IN THE SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES

Silence as Evidence: U.S. Supreme Court Holds That the Fifth Amendment Does Not Bar Using a Suspect s Silence as Evidence of Guilt

MARCIA HOFMANN (Cal. Bar No ) 25 Taylor Street San Francisco, CA Telephone: (415)

-- The search text of this PDF is generated from uncorrected OCR text.

Stanford Law Review Online

Introduction. REED V. TOWN OF GILBERT, ARIZ. What do we have? What can you do?

Warrantless Access to Cell Site Location Information Takes a Hit in the Fourth Circuit:

SYMPOSIUM THE GOALS OF ANTITRUST FOREWORD: ANTITRUST S PURSUIT OF PURPOSE

Syllabus Law : Surveillance Law Seminar. George Mason University Law School Fall 2015 Arlington Hall, Hazel Hall. Professor Jake Phillips

NO WARRANTS SHALL ISSUE BUT UPON PROBABLE CAUSE: THE IMPACT OF THE STORED COMMUNICATIONS ACT ON PRIVACY EXPECTATIONS

Small Cells, Big Problems: The Increasing Precision of Cell Site Location Information and the Need for Fourth Amendment Protections

Transcription:

DEFENDING EQUILIBRIUM-ADJUSTMENT Orin S. Kerr I thank Professor Christopher Slobogin for responding to my recent Article, An Equilibrium-Adjustment Theory of the Fourth Amendment. 1 My Article contended that much of today s Fourth Amendment law can be understood as the product of equilibrium-adjustment. When changing technology and social practice threaten to considerably expand or restrict government power, courts tighten or loosen Fourth Amendment restrictions to restore the status quo level of government power. That is, courts account for changing technology by adjusting rules in an effort to restore the prior equilibrium of government power. Existing Fourth Amendment doctrine therefore reflects many decades of equilibrium-adjustment over time. Professor Slobogin s response, An Original Take on Originalism, 2 rests on a simple premise suggested by its title. In Slobogin s view, equilibrium-adjustment is originalism. 3 Slobogin believes that colonial times provide the reference point for equilibrium-adjustment. 4 On this basis, any judge who engages in equilibrium-adjustment advocates an originalist vision of the Fourth Amendment. After characterizing the theory of equilibrium-adjustment as originalism, Slobogin argues that the theory is inaccurate, unworkable, and unhelpful. The theory is inaccurate because existing Fourth Amendment doctrine does not in fact track originalism. 5 And it is unworkable and unhelpful for all the reasons that Slobogin finds originalism unworkable and unhelpful. 6 I fear Professor Slobogin has misunderstood my argument. Equilibrium-adjustment is not originalism. It is a theory of maintaining the status quo balance of power, not an effort to restore eighteenth-century rules. That understanding explains why living constitutionalists and pragmatists alike have embraced equilibrium-adjustment, and why the chief attack on it has been launched on originalist grounds. It is true, * Professor, George Washington University Law School. Thanks to the editors of the Harvard Law Review for graciously allowing this response, and to Professor Slobogin for the thoughtful debate. 1 125 HARV. L. REV. 476 (2011). 2 125 HARV. L. REV. F. 14 (2011). 3 Id. at 14. 4 See id. at 15 (considering the concept of Year Zero by considering colonial times as [b]ack when the Fourth Amendment was written ). 5 See id. at 14 18. 6 See id. at 14 ( [E]quilibrium-adjustment theory is originalism, and thus suffers from all of the problems associated with that methodology. ). 84

2012] DEFENDING EQUILIBRIUM-ADJUSTMENT 85 as Slobogin says, that the theory harks back to some earlier time. 7 But that does not make it originalist. The relevant earlier time is a time before a triggering technological development, but it need not be the year the Fourth Amendment was ratified. To be sure, it is possible for originalists to adopt the method of equilibrium-adjustment. But nonoriginalists can adopt it, too. In my view, its widespread appeal is what makes equilibrium-adjustment a valuable tool for understanding Fourth Amendment law: Justices from very different interpretive schools use it. It operates equally well within all of the different theories of interpretation. Different Justices might tailor the method based on their interpretive commitments. But they all can engage in equilibrium-adjustment, and almost all do. The Supreme Court s recent decision in United States v. Jones 8 provides a revealing illustration of how equilibrium-adjustment can occur in both originalist and nonoriginalist forms. I will develop my reply in three parts. First, I will show how the theory of equilibrium-adjustment differs from originalism. Second, I will examine the Supreme Court s recent decision in United States v. Jones. Finally, I will address Professor Slobogin s criticism that the theory of equilibrium-adjustment does not necessarily determine how the Supreme Court should rule in difficult cases. I concede the point, but challenge the assumption that a theory of Fourth Amendment law should provide such answers. I. EQUILIBRIUM-ADJUSTMENT IS NOT ORIGINALISM IN DISGUISE Professor Slobogin construes my argument as having a secret originalist agenda: At bottom, he writes, equilibrium-adjustment theory is originalism. 9 As Slobogin sees it, Year Zero refers to colonial times, back when the Fourth Amendment was written. 10 The theory of equilibrium-adjustment thus posits that courts try to restore the originalist Fourth Amendment. Slobogin then argues that my argument fails because Fourth Amendment case law departs from originalism, which in any event is a problematic theory of constitutional interpretation. Slobogin s argument misfires with the first step: his assumption that Year Zero is 1791, and that a judge engaging in equilibriumadjustment must try to restore the original Fourth Amendment. Not 7 Id. at 19. 8 132 S. Ct. 945 (2012). 9 Slobogin, supra note 2, at 14. 10 Id. at 15.

86 HARVARD LAW REVIEW FORUM [Vol. 125:84 so. The theory of equilibrium-adjustment posits that existing Fourth Amendment doctrine reflects generations of past adjustments based on new technologies. We don t easily see those generations because the new technologies of the past appear to us as simply part of the present status quo. I introduced Year Zero to help reveal the past generations of change. Starting with a hypothetical baseline when no technologies existed makes it easier to see the previous generations of technological change, and the responses to them, embedded in existing doctrine. Slobogin assumes that this backward-looking approach must be originalist. Because it harks back to some earlier time, he writes, equilibrium-adjustment theory is essentially originalism in disguise. 11 There are two problems with Slobogin s assumption. First, originalist approaches generally focus on the semantic meaning of text at the time of enactment. 12 The theory of equilibriumadjustment does not do this: it is not a theory of interpreting text or original meaning. The theory focuses on maintaining levels of police power, not text or original meaning. Second, harking back to some earlier time does not necessarily mean looking back to 1791. It merely means looking back to a period before the relevant technological change occurred. Courts engaging in equilibrium-adjustment aim to return to the status quo level of police power before the triggering event. While it is possible to use 1791 as the reference point, judges can use any reference point before the technological change. So while equilibrium-adjustment may be reliably Burkean, 13 it is not particularly originalist. This difference explains why many leading examples of equilibrium-adjusting judicial opinions were authored on nonoriginalist grounds by Justices not thought of as originalists. Prominent examples discussed in my paper include Justice Brandeis s dissent in Olmstead v. United States, 14 Justice Stewart s majority opinion in Katz v. United States, 15 Justice Brennan s majority opinion in Warden v. Hayden, 16 and Justice Brown s majority opinion in Hale v. Henkel. 17 I will refer the reader to the discussion of these cases in my paper. 18 Here I mere- 11 Id. at 19. 12 See, e.g., Richard H. Fallon, Jr., Are Originalist Constitutional Theories Principled, or Are They Rationalizations for Conservatism?, 34 HARV. J.L. & PUB. POL Y 5, 7 (2011). 13 See generally Ernest Young, Rediscovering Conservatism: Burkean Political Theory and Constitutional Interpretation, 72 N.C. L. REV. 619 (1994). 14 277 U.S. 438 (1928). 15 389 U.S. 347 (1967). 16 387 U.S. 294 (1967). 17 201 U.S. 43 (1906). 18 See Kerr, supra note 1, at 509 16.

2012] DEFENDING EQUILIBRIUM-ADJUSTMENT 87 ly point out that all four opinions reflect equilibrium-adjustment but none can be considered originalist. Indeed, several of these leading examples of equilibriumadjustment have been opposed on originalist grounds. 19 Justice Black s dissent in Katz v. United States provides the most stark example. The Katz majority engaged in equilibrium-adjustment by holding that attaching a listening device to a phone booth constituted a Fourth Amendment search. In dissent, Justice Black condemned the majority for rewriting... the Fourth Amendment. 20 The Fourth Amendment was not originally intended to apply to eavesdropping, Justice Black insisted. 21 As a result, the Court could not properly regulate eavesdropping under the Fourth Amendment no matter how much technology had changed: I will not distort the words of the Amendment in order to keep the Constitution up to date or to bring it into harmony with the times. It was never meant that this Court have such power, which in effect would make us a continuously functioning constitutional convention. 22 To be clear, equilibrium-adjustment does not necessarily conflict with originalism. As my Article explains, prominent originalists like Justice Scalia accept equilibrium-adjustment. 23 But the theory of equilibrium-adjustment is a theory of responding to change rather than a theory of original meaning. II. EQUILIBRIUM-ADJUSTMENT IN UNITED STATES V. JONES The recent opinions filed in United States v. Jones 24 provide a helpful demonstration of how equilibrium-adjustment can appear both in originalist and nonoriginalist forms. The Supreme Court handed down Jones just a few weeks after my Article appeared, and the case divided the Court into two main camps. One adopted an originalist methodology; the other explicitly rejected originalism. But both approaches relied heavily on equilibrium-adjustment. The facts of Jones are simple. Investigators installed a GPS device on Jones s car and monitored the car s location for twenty-eight days. 25 As I detailed in my Article, GPS monitoring provides a plausible trig- 19 For example, the adjusting opinion in Katz drew an originalist dissent from Justice Black, and the adjusting opinion in Warden v. Hayden drew an originalist dissent by Justice Douglas, see Hayden, 387 U.S. at 313 20 (Douglas, J., dissenting). 20 Katz, 389 U.S. at 373 (Black, J., dissenting). 21 Id. 22 Id. 23 Kerr, supra note 1, at 531 ( [A]n originalist such as Justice Scalia can see equilibriumadjustment as an originalist method that ensures that the privacy protection at the time of the Framing is not eroded by technology. ). 24 132 S. Ct. 945 (2012). 25 Id. at 948.

88 HARVARD LAW REVIEW FORUM [Vol. 125:84 ger for equilibrium-adjustment. GPS devices permit significantly more surveillance than beepers: they allow monitoring with much greater detail, less cost, less oversight, and over a longer period of time than beepers. 26 In his brief, Jones relied on these differences to argue that GPS monitoring should be treated as a search: such a holding was needed to rein in the new technology that threatened privacy protections. 27 All nine Justices agreed with Jones that the facts of his case included some kind of Fourth Amendment search. They disagreed, however, on which facts and why. The majority opinion by Justice Scalia engaged in equilibriumadjustment using an originalist framework. When the Government argued that Jones had no reasonable expectation of privacy in the public location of the car, Justice Scalia responded that the Fourth Amendment should be read to protect rights beyond the reasonable expectation of privacy test. Quoting from his opinion in Kyllo v. United States, 28 Justice Scalia reasoned that the Fourth Amendment must be interpreted to assur[e] preservation of that degree of privacy against government that existed when the Fourth Amendment was adopted. 29 To assure preservation of that privacy, Justice Scalia interpreted the Fourth Amendment as protecting against common law trespasses. The installation of the GPS device with intent to use it to obtain information was a common law trespass, and therefore a Fourth Amendment search. 30 Justice Alito filed an opinion concurring in the judgment, joined by Justices Ginsburg, Breyer, and Kagan. Justice Alito criticized the majority s originalist approach as inconsistent with precedent and unworkable. 31 Instead, Justice Alito engaged in equilibrium-adjustment using the Katz reasonable expectation of privacy framework. 32 He explained that [i]n the pre-computer age, surveillance that could reveal information as extensive as GPS monitoring was impractical in most cases. 33 It would require a large team of agents, multiple vehicles, and perhaps aerial assistance. 34 Changing technology had expanded government power by making such monitoring relatively easy and cheap. 35 Accordingly, Justice Alito interpreted the Fourth 26 Kerr, supra note 1, at 500. 27 See Brief for Respondent at 24 30, United States v. Jones, 132 S. Ct. 945 (2012) (No. 10-1259). 28 533 U.S. 27 (2001). 29 Jones, 132 S. Ct. at 950 (quoting Kyllo, 533 U.S. at 34) (internal quotation marks omitted). 30 See id. at 949 52. 31 See id. at 958 62 (Alito, J., concurring in the judgment). 32 See id. at 958. 33 Id. at 963. 34 Id. 35 Id. at 964.

2012] DEFENDING EQUILIBRIUM-ADJUSTMENT 89 Amendment to limit the government s new powers. Although Justice Alito s opinion is not a model of clarity, he seems to have interpreted the reasonable expectation of privacy test to lock in prior understandings of how invasive police investigations might be. Long-term use of GPS monitoring constituted a Fourth Amendment search because it exceeded pre-gps societal expectations that such invasive monitoring was unlikely or even impossible. 36 Justice Sotomayor joined the majority opinion and filed a concurrence agreeing with and going beyond Justice Alito s rationale. Like the opinions filed by Justices Scalia and Alito, Justice Sotomayor s opinion engaged in equilibrium-adjustment. GPS monitoring may alter the relationship between citizen and government, 37 Justice Sotomayor reasoned, and the Fourth Amendment had to be interpreted to limit use of a tool so amenable to misuse. 38 Justice Sotomayor also expressed a need to revisit the third-party doctrine, the rule that information disclosed to third parties does not receive Fourth Amendment protection. That doctrine is ill suited to the digital age, Justice Sotomayor reasoned, given that now people reveal a great deal of information about themselves to third parties in the course of carrying out mundane tasks. 39 The three opinions in Jones proceed from different premises. One is originalist; two are not. But all three opinions rest on the principle of equilibrium-adjustment. All three opinions interpret the Fourth Amendment to counter technology s ability to narrow privacy. The majority opinion seeks to preserve the privacy protections that existed in 1791; the concurring opinions seek to preserve the privacy protections that existed in the pre-computer age (in Justice Alito s words) or before the digital age (in Justice Sotomayor s). But all three opinions interpret the Fourth Amendment to restore a prior level of government power. All three opinions engage in equilibrium-adjustment. III. WHAT SHOULD A THEORY OF THE FOURTH AMENDMENT DO? Explaining the differences between equilibrium-adjustment and originalism addresses the bulk of Slobogin s response. But it leaves one major criticism unanswered, and I want to respond to that here. Slobogin contends that the theory of equilibrium-adjustment fails be- 36 See id. 37 Id. at 956 (Sotomayor, J., concurring) (quoting United States v. Cuevas-Perez, 640 F.3d 272, 285 (7th Cir. 2011) (Flaum, J., concurring)) (internal quotation mark omitted). 38 Id. 39 Id. at 957.

90 HARVARD LAW REVIEW FORUM [Vol. 125:84 cause it lacks strong predictive power. 40 The theory provides an approach, but it does not indicate which side should win when the Supreme Court resolves difficult cases. According to Slobogin, the theory can differ depending upon the analyst, 41 and at least in some cases it is possible to make equilibrium-adjustment arguments that are consistent with either result. 42 This observation is true. Equilibrium-adjustment frames the debate, but it does not necessarily answer which side is right or what rule judges should announce. Different judges can use different reference points for adjustment. They can assess the need for adjustment differently, and can adjust in different ways. But is this a weakness of the theory, or a strength? Fourth Amendment law is not mathematics, and judges are not computers. No descriptive theory of the Fourth Amendment can uncontroversially explain every case. And no normative theory can announce correct outcomes every time. Our messy world of generalist judges deciding thousands of cases over many decades requires a more modest goal. In my view, any descriptive theory of the Fourth Amendment must account for that messy reality. The common wisdom found in the scholarship has taken this principle too far, I think. The law is a mess 43 and a mass of contradictions, 44 scholars often say, suggesting that no theory at all can explain it. One goal of my Article was to rescue Fourth Amendment law from this anarchic narrative and show that amidst the din there is a surprisingly helpful theory that explains what judges do when they apply the Fourth Amendment. It does not provide exact answers in every case. But I think it frames the debate and explains a great deal of how Fourth Amendment case law came to look as it does. In my view, identifying that dynamic and explaining its usefulness has significant value. Beyond explaining existing law, identifying the adjustment dynamic helps set a goal for today s judges. It teaches that every age has its new technologies that threaten to disrupt the prior equilibrium. The 1920s had the automobile. Almost a century later, we have computers and the Internet. Understanding equilibriumadjustment help us see that today s cutting-edge Fourth Amendment questions are not very different from those in the past. And it also reveals a path forward for courts seeking answers that both respond to today s problems and remain consistent with historical practice. 40 Slobogin, supra note 2, at 22. 41 Id. at 15. 42 Id. at 18. 43 Ronald J. Allen & Ross M. Rosenberg, The Fourth Amendment and the Limits of Theory: Local Versus General Theoretical Knowledge, 72 ST. JOHN S L. REV. 1149, 1149 (1998). 44 Craig M. Bradley, Two Models of the Fourth Amendment, 83 MICH. L. REV. 1468, 1468 (1985).