A Liberal Defence of Compulsory Voting : Some Reasons for Scepticism.

Similar documents
Controversy Liberalism, Democracy and the Ethics of Votingponl_

Is Compulsory Voting Justified? Submitted to Public Reason

DEMOCRACY AND EQUALITY

Incentives and the Natural Duties of Justice

Affirmative Answers to (A/T) Common Negative Arguments

The Ethics of Political Participation: Engagement and Democracy in the 21st Century

CHAPTER 2: MAJORITARIAN OR PLURALIST DEMOCRACY

Article. Reference. Democracy and Voting: A Reply to Lisa Hill. LEVER, Annabelle

Marxism. Lecture 7 Liberalism John Filling

S.L. Hurley, Justice, Luck and Knowledge, (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2003), 341 pages. ISBN: (hbk.).

Democracy and Common Valuations

Phil 115, June 20, 2007 Justice as fairness as a political conception: the fact of reasonable pluralism and recasting the ideas of Theory

Increasing Electoral Turnout among the Young

The Case for Compulsory Voting: A Critical Perspective. Annabelle Lever

When Does Equality Matter? T. M. Scanlon. Lecture 1: Introduction. Our country, and the world, are marked by extraordinarily high levels of

Is Rawls s Difference Principle Preferable to Luck Egalitarianism?

Part 2. Argument. Topic: Should American citizens be required to vote in national elections?

AN EGALITARIAN THEORY OF JUSTICE 1

Political equality, wealth and democracy

Political Beliefs and Behaviors

Lesson 10 What Is Economic Justice?

1. In the feudal period there was little idea of individuals having their own interests or

Should Americans Be Required to Vote?

NATIONAL HEARING QUESTIONS ACADEMIC YEAR

Voting rights GRAMMAR

Jan Narveson and James P. Sterba

A New Electoral System for a New Century. Eric Stevens

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Our Democracy Uncorrupted

Two Pictures of the Global-justice Debate: A Reply to Tan*

THE AGONISTIC CONSOCIATION. Mohammed Ben Jelloun. (EHESS, Paris)

In his account of justice as fairness, Rawls argues that treating the members of a

Jerry: Hi buddy! So ya didn t get out to vote for the mayor, eh? Tom: What s going to happen if I don t bother to vote? 2

John Rawls THEORY OF JUSTICE

Problems with the one-person-one-vote Principle

Pos 500 Seminar in Political Theory: Political Theory and Equality Peter Breiner

2013 Boone Municipal Election Turnout: Measuring the effects of the 2013 Board of Elections changes

ALEXIS DE TOCQUEVILLE

Scope Document. Plain English Version of AMC Disciplinary Policies and Procedures Project

INSTITUTIONAL ISSUES INVOLVING ETHICS AND JUSTICE Vol.I - Economic Justice - Hon-Lam Li

A Defense of Public Justification

Global Justice and Two Kinds of Liberalism

Rawls versus the Anarchist: Justice and Legitimacy

enforce people s contribution to the general good, as everyone naturally wants to do productive work, if they can find something they enjoy.

Philosophy 267 Fall, 2010 Professor Richard Arneson Introductory Handout revised 11/09 Texts: Course requirements: Week 1. September 28.

New Zealand Germany 2013

Robust Political Economy. Classical Liberalism and the Future of Public Policy

-Capitalism, Exploitation and Injustice-

BCGEU surveyed its own members on electoral reform. They reported widespread disaffection with the current provincial electoral system.

In his theory of justice, Rawls argues that treating the members of a society as. free and equal achieving fair cooperation among persons thus

Normative Frameworks 1 / 35

THRESHOLDS. Underlying principles. What submitters on the party vote threshold said

John Rawls, Socialist?

Comments on Schnapper and Banting & Kymlicka

A new preamble for the Australian Constitution?

AMY GUTMANN: THE CONSTRUCTIVE POTENTIAL OF COMMUNITARIAN VALUES DOES GUTMANN SUCCEED IN SHOWING THE CONSTRUCTIVE POTENTIAL OF COMMUNITARIAN VALUES?

John Rawls's Difference Principle and The Strains of Commitment: A Diagrammatic Exposition

Political Norms and Moral Values

Increasing Electoral Turnout Among the Young: Compulsory Voting or Financial Incentives?

AUSTRALIA. Date of Elections: 11 July Purpose of Elections

Justice As Fairness: Political, Not Metaphysical (Excerpts)

~ Brain Activation ~ features of. elections in Australia

Course Name - Government

Compare the vote Level 3

Political Science 103 Spring, 2018 Dr. Edward S. Cohen INTRODUCTION TO POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY

Justifying Punishment: A Response to Douglas Husak

On Human Rights by James Griffin, Oxford University Press, 2008, 339 pp.

The character of public reason in Rawls s theory of justice

RAWLS DIFFERENCE PRINCIPLE: ABSOLUTE vs. RELATIVE INEQUALITY

Compare the vote Level 1

Democratic Rights and the Choice of Economic Systems

1. What is political culture? Cite examples of political cultures other than our own.

Introduction. Cambridge University Press Rawls's Egalitarianism Alexander Kaufman Excerpt More Information

Penalizing Public Disobedience*

Definition: Property rights in oneself comparable to property rights in inanimate things

The limits of background justice. Thomas Porter. Social Philosophy & Policy volume 30, issues 1 2. Cambridge University Press

Political Science 103 Fall, 2015 Dr. Edward S. Cohen INTRODUCTION TO POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY

E-LOGOS. Rawls two principles of justice: their adoption by rational self-interested individuals. University of Economics Prague

POL 343 Democratic Theory and Globalization February 11, "The history of democratic theory II" Introduction

Voting Lesson Plan. Student Objectives. Question for Deliberation. Materials

CHAPTER 4: American Political Culture

Voting Lesson Plan. Student Objectives. Question for Deliberation. Materials

When Does Equality Matter? 1. T. M. Scanlon. The first theme of this paper is that we have many different reasons for being

John Stuart Mill ( )

I- The draft Declaration on Medically-Indicated Abortion violates the independence of physicians and their freedom of conscience

Compassion and Compulsion

AmericasBarometer Insights: 2011 Number 63

The Justification of Justice as Fairness: A Two Stage Process

J U D G E M E N T on Behalf of the Republic of Latvia in Case No February 2015, Riga

Property and Progress

Do we have a moral obligation to the homeless?

Rawls, Republicanism and Property-Owning Democracy. Stuart White, Jesus College, Oxford. Work-in-progress draft, March 2006.

Social and Political Philosophy

Who Speaks for the Poor? The Implications of Electoral Geography for the Political Representation of Low-Income Citizens

Phil 290, February 8, 2011 Christiano, The Constitution of Equality, Ch. 2 3

POLITICAL CULTURE AND LANDSCAPE; Reviewing MLK day and the difficulty in creating the holiday as an intro

Utilitarianism. Utilitarianism. Dr. Clea F. Rees. Centre for Lifelong Learning Cardiff University.

Maximizing Social Welfare or Institutionalizing Democratic Ideals? Commentary on Adam Przeworski's Article

David Dyzenhaus* RESPONSE TO IAN SHAPIRO, ON NON-DOMINATION

University of Alberta

Transcription:

1 A Liberal Defence of Compulsory Voting : Some Reasons for Scepticism. Annabelle Lever Department of Philosophy London School of Economics and Political Science (annabelle@alever.net) Justine Lacroix contends that liberals can support legal compulsion to vote on the grounds that no rights or liberties are violated by such compulsion, and because compulsion can help to minimise inequalities in political participation amongst social groups. (Lacroix, 2007) I agree with Lacroix that the most plausible forms of liberalism treat the political liberties as fundamental, and value political participation. Indeed, I would supplement her references to Constant, Tocqueville and Mill with reference to more contemporary figures such as Rawls and Dworkin. Nontheless, there are reasons to doubt that liberals can support legal compulsion, both because it is unclear that people have a moral duty to vote in most cases and because the existence of such a duty is insufficient to justify legal compulsion. Lacroix is right to insist that liberalism is consistent with the belief that political participation is a fundamental right, and that a life of political participation can have great value. Rather surprisingly, though, her examples neglect contemporary liberals, such as Rawls or Dworkin, although both make it plain that political participation can be valuable in its own right, and not merely as a means to other ends. 1 Rawls is notable, too, for insisting on the fair value of the political liberties, given their competitive character. Thus, while inequalities of income and 1 Rawls notes the typical liberal view that the political liberties are only of instrumental value, but notes that different people will have different views about this. (p.230). Moreover, at pp.233-4, he explains why equal political liberty is not solely a means to other ends, but something of value in and of itself. For Dworkin, see Sovereign Virtue: The Theory and Practice of Equality, ch. 4 and the striking, rather moving, endorsement of a form of civic republicanism in ch. 5, and its last sentence claiming that there is a way in which political community can have ethical primacy over our lives as individuals.

2 wealth may, in his view, justifiably affect the value that our other liberties have for us as they would if, say, I found it hard to make the pilgrimage to Mecca for financial reasons Rawls is very concerned to insulate democratic politics from the distorting effects of economic inequality, so far as is consistent with protecting the basic liberties in the first place. So, he claims that the constitution must take steps to enhance the value of the equal rights of participation for all members of society. It must underwrite a fair opportunity to take part in and to influence the political process.the liberties protected by the principle of participation lose much of their value whenever those who have greater private means are permitted to use their advantages to control the course of public debate.compensating steps must, then, be taken to preserve the fair value for all of the equal political liberties. For example, in a society allowing private ownership of the means of production, property and wealth must be kept widely distributed and government monies provided on a regular basis to encourage free public discussion.. (para. 36 pp. 224-225) However, it is one thing to think that the political liberties are valuable in and of themselves, and another to suppose that people have a moral duty to vote. For example, Rawls clearly supposes that, where the political liberties indeed have fair value, citizens can generally be expected to vote willingly. (para. 37, pp. 223). Still, Rawls distinction between what he calls natural duties and obligations provides one reason for doubting that there is a general duty to vote, applicable to most people in most elections, even on a self-consciously egalitarian and democratic form of liberalism. According to Rawls, it seems appropriate to distinguish between those institutions which must inevitably apply to us since we are born into them, and they regulate the full scope of our activity, and those that apply to us because we have freely done certain things as a rational way of advancing our ends. Thus, we have a natural duty to comply with the constitution, say, or with the basic laws regulating property (assuming them to be just), whereas we have an obligation to carry out the

3 duties of an office that we have succeeded in winning, or to follow the rules of associations or activities that we have joined (para. 52, pp. 343-4) Part of the point of ensuring the fair value of the political liberties, therefore, is that the effect of self-government where equal political rights have their fair value is to enhance the self-esteem and the sense of political competence of the average citizen. His awareness of his own worth developed in the smaller associations of his community is confirmed in the constitution of the whole society.this education to public spirit is necessary if citizens are to acquire an affirmative sense of political duty and obligation, that is, one that goes beyond the mere willingness to submit to law and government. (para. 37, p.234) I am no Rawls expert. However, it looks as though Rawls, here, supposes that affirmative political obligations depend for their acquisition and, perhaps, for their justification on our willing participation in the governance of our society. Such affirmative political obligations, therefore, cannot be used to justify compulsory voting, or compulsory political participation more generally. But there are deeper reasons to doubt that liberals can support compulsion, or can easily affirm that citizens generally have a moral duty to vote. The problem, essentially, is this: that liberals suppose that people can reasonably disagree about the value of political participation, compared to other activities and forms of life and, by extension, people can also disagree about the relative importance of different forms of participation, even if political participation is treated as of ultimate importance. If voting is to be a duty, we must assume that we are concerned with informed and conscientious voting so voting out of ignorance, on a whim and so on, would not count as fulfilling the duty. But it is not clear that people must acquire well informed political opinions on pain of behaving immorally. The engagement with the world which this presupposes would seem incompatible with various forms of spiritual quest

4 and with attitudes to the world that value spontaneity, living in the moment, or even a certain scepticism towards organised activities of various sorts. 2 True, there are circumstances where we may all have a duty to stand up and be counted and electoral participation apparently increases in areas contested by the far right, or by racist political parties, as those who oppose such positions generally and rightly feel the need to make their opposition known. However, while reasonable pluralism - as it has been called- 3 seems consistent with the idea that people do, sometimes, have a duty to vote, and to vote one way rather than another, it is hard to square a commitment to respect people s conscientious convictions about what makes life valuable and worth living with the idea that there is a general duty to vote. Finally, I would just emphasise the gap between the idea that there is a moral duty to vote and justification of a legal requirement to vote, even if one allows for various forms of conscientious objection and would allow as current Australian law apparently does not that the legal duty involves turning out, but no obligation to complete a legally valid ballot. 4 Of course, legal obligations do not presuppose moral obligations, so one might think that there is a case for legal compulsion even in the absence of a moral duty to vote. In either case, however, the problem of justification 2 Emersonian individualism - at least as presented by George Kateb would seem to be a prime example of this position. See Kateb, 1984 and 1992. 3 Joshua Cohen, coined the phrase in his Moral Pluralism and Political Consensus, in The Idea of Democracy, ed. Copp, Hampton and Roemer, (Cambridge, 1993), especially pp. 281-5. 4 According to Lisa Hill, a recent test case suggests that marking a ballot informally does not meet the requirements in the Act on how to vote, and is therefore an offence. Lisa Hill, (2007), p.9 Lacroix, like Hill, endorse the ECHR view that there is no violation of conscience when people are forced to vote, because they can always cast a blank vote. (Lacroix, 2007, 193). On those grounds, being forced to attend Church would not violate my conscience, as long as I do not have to pray. This is clearly not a satisfactory interpretation of freedom of conscience. Fortunately, Australian law appears to allow religious objections to voting though not, it should be noted, conscientious objections based on secular, rather than religious, grounds. Hill discusses the case of Judd v. McKeon, which involved an Australian socialist who was jailed for not voting, and notes that his claims for exemption are morally compelling in terms of the types of democratic values compulsory voting is supposed to serve. (18)

5 is this: that legal compulsion to vote will likely require sanctions for failure to vote and this raises the possibility that otherwise law-abiding citizens may be sent to prison for the failure to pay fines for not voting. So before we agree that voting should be compulsory whether on liberal or on democratic grounds we need to know why legal means should be preferred to other ways of encouraging political turnout and participation, especially by politically underrepresented social groups; and we need to know what sanctions, if any, are supported by the reasons to favour compulsion. I am sceptical that this hurdle can generally be met. Low turnout, and political alienation by the young, the poor and the uneducated are of genuine concern. But being forced to turnout is unlikely to cure alienation, nor is it much of a cure for political inequality, as voters only get to chose from a range of candidates and platforms that have already been decided. Moreover, if the papers presented at the ECPR workshop on compulsory voting - held in Helsinki this May - are anything to go by, it seems that compulsory voting has no noticeable effect on political knowledge or interest (Ballinger, 2007; Engelen and Hooghe, 2007) nor, more surprisingly, any evident effect on electoral outcomes (Czesnik, 2007 and Selb and Lachat, 2007). Compulsory voting is clearly no guarantee of egalitarian social policies; and the Australian case where compulsory voting is extremely popular and is long established shows that increasing turnout does not force parties to compete for the votes of the poor, the weak and the marginalised, as Lijphart had hoped. (Lijphart, 1997) Conversely, compulsory voting is, apparently, anathema in Sweden and other Scandinavian countries, although these are regularly held up by political and social scientists as beacons of social democracy, and as examples of how to combat the persistent under-representation of women in positions of political power.

6 In short, if you value political participation there are good reasons to treat compulsory voting with scepticism, and to look elsewhere for remedies to low and unequal electoral turnout or more fundamentally to the problems of political powerlessness and inequality that mar many contemporary democracies. BALLINGER, C. (2007) COMPULSORY VOTING: PALLIATIVE CARE FOR DEMOCRACY IN THE UK? UNPUBLISHED PAPER, PRESENTED TO THE ECPR JOINT SESSIONS WORKSHOP ON COMPULSORY VOTING, HELSINKI COHEN, J. (1993) MORAL PLURALISM AND POLITICAL CONSENSUS IN COPP, D. ET AL. THE IDEA OF DEMOCRACY, (CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS) CZESNIK, M. (2007) IS COMPULSORY VOTING A REMEDY? EVIDENCE FROM THE 2001 POLISH PARLIAMENTARY ELECTIONS. UNPUBLISHED PAPER, PRESENTED TO THE ECPR JOINT SESSIONS WORKSHOP ON COMPULSORY VOTING, HELSINKI DE CEUNINK, K. ET AL. (2007) TO VOTE OR NOT TO VOTE, THAT IS THE QUESTION! UNPULBISHED PAPER, PRESENTED TO THE ECPR JOINT SESSIONS WORKSHOP ON COMPULSORY VOTING, HELSINKI DWORKIN, R. (2000), SOVEREIGN VIRTUE: THE THEORY AND PRACTICE OF EQUALITY, (HARVARD UNIVERSITY PRESS) ENGELEN, B. AND M. HOOGHE, (2007) COMPULSORY VOTING AND ITS EFFECTS ON POLITICAL PARTICIPATION, INTEREST AND EFFICACY, UNPUBLISHED PAPER, PRESENTED TO THE ECPR JOINT SESSIONS WORKSHOP ON COMPULSORY VOTING, HELSINKI HILL, L. (2007) COMPULSORY VOTING IN AUSTRALIA: HISTORY, PUBLIC ACCEPTANCE AND JUSTIFIABILITY, UNPUBLISHED PAPER, PRESENTED TO THE ECPR JOINT SESSIONS WORKSHOP ON COMPULSORY VOTING, HELSINKI

7 KATEB, G. (1984), DEMOCRATIC INDIVIDUALITY AND THE CLAIMS OF POLITICS, POLITICAL THEORY, (12.3. PP. 331-360). KATEB, G. (1992), THE INNER OCEAN: INDIVIDUALISM AND DEMOCRATIC CULTURE, (CORNELL UNIVERSITY PRESS) LIJPHART, A. (1997) UNEQUAL PARTICIPATION: DEMOCRACY S UNRESOLVED DILEMMA, 91.1 THE AMERICAN POLITICAL SCIENCE REVIEW, PP. 1-14 RAWLS, J. (1972), A THEORY OF JUSTICE, (HARVARD UNIVERSITY PRESS) SELB, P. AND R. LACHAT, (2007) THE MORE, THE BETTER? COUNTERFACTUAL EVIDENCE ON THE EFFECT OF COMPULSORY VOTING ON THE CONSISTENCY OF PARTY CHOICE, UNPUBLISHED PAPER, PRESENTED TO THE ECPR JOINT SESSIONS WORKSHOP ON COMPULSORY VOTING, HELSINKI