Session 9. Dworkin, selection from Law s Empire

Similar documents
Political Obligation 3

Dworkin, selections from Taking Rights Seriously. Dworkin identifies these three propositions as forming the core of the legal positivist position:

Civil Disobedience and the Duty to Obey the Law: A Critical Assessment of Lefkowitz's View

Rawls versus the Anarchist: Justice and Legitimacy

Session 20 Gerald Dworkin s Paternalism

Playing Fair and Following the Rules

Thomas Hobbes: Does Might Make Right?

Community and consent: Issues from and for deliberative democratic theory

LEGAL POSITIVISM AND NATURAL LAW RECONSIDERED

Advanced Political Philosophy I: Political Authority and Obligation

POLITICAL AUTHORITY AND PERFECTIONISM: A RESPONSE TO QUONG

Democracy As Equality

Last time we discussed a stylized version of the realist view of global society.

AUTHORITY AND NORMATIVITY. Literature: A. Marmor, Philosophy of Law

24.03: Good Food 3/13/17. Justice and Food Production

Christian Aid Ireland's Submission to the Review of Ireland s Foreign Policy and External Relations

To cite this article: Anna Stilz (2011): ON THE RELATION BETWEEN DEMOCRACY AND RIGHTS, Representation, 47:1, 9-17

Questions. Hobbes. Hobbes s view of human nature. Question. What justification is there for a state? Does the state have supreme authority?

Hobbes. Questions. What justification is there for a state? Does the state have supreme authority? What limits are there upon the state?

serving the governed: on the truth in political instrumentalism daniel viehoff new york university

Social Contract Theory According to Thomas Hobbes & John Locke

Phil 290, February 8, 2011 Christiano, The Constitution of Equality, Ch. 2 3

the two explanatory forces of interests and ideas. All of the readings draw at least in part on ideas as

Theories of Justice to Health Care

Political Science Introduction to American Politics

o I agree to continue (1) o I do not agree to continue (2)

Officials and Select Committees Guidelines

The name of this organization shall be the Lebanese Club at the Massachusetts Institute of

Law and Philosophy (2015) 34: Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2015 DOI /s ARIE ROSEN BOOK REVIEW

HART S CRITIQUE OF AUSTIN S THEORY. Literature: A. Marmor, Philosophy of Law

WHISTLE BLOWING AND EMPLOYEE LOYALTY DUSKA

Global Justice and Two Kinds of Liberalism

California Bar Examination

Strategic Speech in the Law *

USPTO Trials: Understanding the Scope and Rules of Discovery

An appealing and original aspect of Mathias Risse s book On Global

Phil 115, June 20, 2007 Justice as fairness as a political conception: the fact of reasonable pluralism and recasting the ideas of Theory

Civic Republicanism and Social Justice

Co-national Obligations & Cosmopolitan Obligations towards Foreigners

Legal Reasoning, the Rule of Law, and Legal Theory: Comments on Gerald Postema, Positivism and the Separation of the Realists from their Skepticism

INDIGENOUS RIGHTS AND UNITED NATIONS STANDARDS: SELF- DETERMINATION, CULTURE AND LAND

Business Ethics Concepts and Cases Manuel G. Velasquez Seventh Edition

o I agree to continue (2) o I do not agree to continue (3)

Rethinking the Principle of Fair Play 1. Justin Tosi

Media Ethics, Class 3: What is The Media Doing, What should they do?

It s helpful to start by contrasting Raz s account of political obligation with Dworkin s.

Political Legitimacy. 1. Descriptive and Normative Concepts of Legitimacy 2. The Function of Political Legitimacy

Philosophy 34 Spring Philosophy of Law. What is law?

Political Obligation 2

TURKEY Industrial Design Law Decree-law No. 554 as amended by Law No of November 7, 1995 ENTRY INTO FORCE: November 7, 1995

GENERAL CLOSING INSTRUCTIONS. Members of the jury, it is now time for me to tell you the law that applies to

World-Wide Ethics. Chapter Six. Social Contract Theory. of the social contract theory of morality.

The limits of background justice. Thomas Porter. Social Philosophy & Policy volume 30, issues 1 2. Cambridge University Press

The legal philosophy of Ronald Dworkin.

RESPONSE TO JAMES GORDLEY'S "GOOD FAITH IN CONTRACT LAW: The Problem of Profit Maximization"

Incentives and the Natural Duties of Justice

The Traditional Social Contract Theory

A Liberal Defence of Compulsory Voting : Some Reasons for Scepticism.

EVOLUTIVE INTERPRETATION AND THE ECHR

Answer A to Question 1

EFFECTIVE VOIR DIRE, OPENING, AND CLOSING ARGUMENT FROM A PROPERTY OWNER S AND CONDEMNOR S PERSPECTIVE

Communitarianism I. Charles Taylor s Anti-Atomism. Dr. Clea F. Rees. Centre for Lifelong Learning Cardiff University

The limits of background justice. Thomas Porter. Rawls says that the primary subject of justice is what he calls the basic structure of

GUIDELINES CONCERNING COURT APPOINTMENTS OF DECISION-MAKERS PURSUANT TO C.R.S

Ekaterina Bogdanov January 18, 2012

University of Southern California Law School

The Morality of Conflict

Short Guide 04. Edward Jacobs, Judge of the Upper Tribunal. The ABC of Effective Procedural Applications The Basics of Tribunal Representation

LEGAL THEORY/ JURISPRUDENCE SUMMARY

What Is Unfair about Unequal Brute Luck? An Intergenerational Puzzle

Enhancing Police Legitimacy through the Integration of Compstat and Community Policing James J. Willis 1

THE CONSTITUTIONALITY OF THE CLIMATE STABILIZATION ACT CAMBRIDGE DRY CLEANING V. UNITED STATES

Communitarianism I. Overview and Introduction. Overview and Introduction. Taylor s Anti-Atomism. Taylor s Anti-Atomism. Principle of belonging

Volume 101 February 2017

When Does Equality Matter? T. M. Scanlon. Lecture 1: Introduction. Our country, and the world, are marked by extraordinarily high levels of

COMPARE AND CONTRAST CONSERVATISM AND SOCIALISM REFER TO BURKE AND MARX IN YOUR ANSWER

You ve Got Rights! We Defeated the British Now What? More and More Rights. Name:

Political Norms and Moral Values

CHAPTER VI. DUTY AND OBLIGATION

THE POSSIBILITY OF A FAIR PLAY ACCOUNT OF LEGITIMACY. Justin Tosi

Parsing Habermas s Bourgeois Public Sphere

MEANS PoLICE.

Politics between Philosophy and Democracy

Multicultural Greek Council Iowa State University. Constitution & Bylaws

In 1978, Congress established the Foreign Intelligence Surveillance Court, which reviews warrants related to national security investigations.

Jus in Bello through the Lens of Individual Moral Responsibility: McMahan on Killing in War

RAWLS DIFFERENCE PRINCIPLE: ABSOLUTE vs. RELATIVE INEQUALITY

Justice and collective responsibility. Zoltan Miklosi. regardless of the institutional or other relations that may obtain among them.

Justifying Punishment: A Response to Douglas Husak

The Debate of Immigration: Democracy, Autonomy, and Coercion

Chapter 40 HUMAN RELATIONS COMMITTEE

Ethics and Public Policy. Government / Public Policy 42 Spring 2016 Dartmouth College

POLE VAULT ELITE WAIVER

Governing Without Coercion 1. Governments make laws and orders that are supposed to influence people's decisions

Ethics Handout 18 Rawls, Classical Utilitarianism and Nagel, Equality

In his account of justice as fairness, Rawls argues that treating the members of a

Assessment of the Dworkin-Hart debate

Republicanism: Midway to Achieve Global Justice?

State Legitimacy and Social Order

How to approach legitimacy

Transcription:

Session 9 Dworkin, selection from Law s Empire In the selection we read, Dworkin is arguing for two conclusions simultaneously: (i) (ii) that political obligations (most centrally, the obligation to obey the law) are associative obligations, akin to obligations of family or friendship; and that his interpretive account of the role law plays in our society is both the right view to take of the law, and the role we should strive to make law fulfill better. How are these two theses related? Here s Dworkin s argument: (1) There can be legitimate political authorities only if there is a general obligation to obey the law. This is because the state s distinctive role is to enforce compliance with its orders and to punish violations, and, Dworkin says, though obligation is not a sufficient condition for coercion, it is close to a necessary one. (p. 191) Question: Is Dworkin right about this? Does political legitimacy depend on the existence of a general obligation to obey? (2) Any account of the obligation to obey the law must explain: a. how we can have such an obligation despite the fact that we don t undertake it voluntarily, in any robust sense; b. how the obligation to obey is an obligation we owe especially to our own government and fellow citizens (as opposed to equally to any government, or just government); c. how we might have this obligation to obey even when the law- independent reasons tip against obedience (since the government, if it is to be legitimate, must be entitled to punish in these cases as well). This is reflected in Dworkin s criticisms of other accounts of political obligation: - The argument from tacit consent fails because consent cannot be binding on people, in the way the argument requires, unless it is given more freely, and with more genuine alternate choice, than just by declining to build a life from nothing under a foreign flag. (pp. 192-3) - The argument from the duty to support just institutions fails because it does not tie political obligation sufficiently tightly to the particular community to which those who have the obligation belong (p. 193) - The argument from fair play fails because it cannot explain why people can incur obligations simply by receiving what they do not seek and would reject if they had the chance. (p. 194) So: we re looking for an argument that can ground a general obligation that is non- voluntarily incurred and special: owed in particular to our own government and fellow citizens. 1

Questions: Is Dworkin right that the obligation to obey has these features? (For example, is obedience owed particularly to our own gov t and fellow citizens?) The persuasiveness of Dworkin s claims here partly rests on his grouping the duty to obey together with other duties that might be described as political obligations, such as the obligation to vote, or engage in the political process, or (for officials) carry out the laws in the right way (3) Only associative obligations exhibit these characteristics: they re non- voluntarily incurred, they re owed particularly to other members of the association, and they give us reasons to do things even when the balance of association- independent reasons tips the other way. (Examples: family, friendship) Question: are family associations and friendships different from political associations in ways that might make the former give rise to associative obligations while the latter do not? Some possible relevant differences: - Size: can we really have the necessary concern for groups that exceed a certain size? - Emotion: emotions play a much more significant role in family and friend- relations. - Family relations and friendships are plausibly non- instrumentally valuable, whereas political associations might more plausibly be instrumentally valuable. - Loyalty is constitutive of friendship (and perhaps family relations of the relevant sort that give rise to obligations), but not of political associations, which can survive undiscovered acts of disobedience in a way that friendships can t really survive undiscovered disloyalty. (4) So it s plausible to think that the obligation to obey the law, if it exists, is an associative obligation. Question: even if we think political obligation is a species of genuine associative obligation, why think the form such obligation takes is a duty of obedience? Why not think the appropriate response by a member of the association to a law that tells us to do something we have most independent reason not to do is, e.g., civil disobedience? (5) Associations must meet certain conditions for associative obligations to arise: a. They must be bare communities: they must meet the genetic or geographical or other historical conditions identified by social practice as capable of constituting a fraternal community. b. They must be true communities, which require meeting 4 conditions: (i) (ii) the obligations of the community must be regarded as special: owed to fellow members of the group; the obligations must be felt as personal: owed directly to other members of the group, not to the group as a whole; (Question: why? Are all communities like this? What about athletic teams? Why does Dworkin insist on this?) 2

(iii) (iv) the obligations must be regarded as flowing from an obligation of general concern, which generates specific obligations that go beyond any black- letter agreements worked out in advance; the group s commitments must reflect equal concern for all members of the group (which needn t entail equal treatment) (Question: what does equal concern come to? Can associative obligations result from unequal associations?) c. The associations cannot be thoroughly and pervasively unjust in the sense that their commitments cannot be coherently described in any way that at the same time helps justify them. Such associations cannot generate any genuine associative obligations. (6) Communities of principle that is, communities in which the law functions the way Dworkin argues it functions (and should function) in our own community are the only ones that meet the requirements set out in (5) for generating genuine associative obligations. De facto communities of circumstance fail to meet requirement b(i): the obligations their members recognize (if they recognize any obligations) are not felt to be owed specially to fellow members of the community. Rule- book communities (remember Hart?!) fail to meet requirement b(iii): the obligations their members recognize are felt to be owed specially to fellow members of the community, but aren t seen as flowing from a requirement of general concern: they are exhausted by the content of explicitly accepted rules. - Rule- book communities are about compromising between antagonistic interests and points of view. - There seem to me to be some aspects of rule- book communities that do a very good job of representing the ideal functioning of our political community which represents, after all, a compromise between many diverse interests, moral commitments, and points of view Communities of principle meet all four conditions: their members see their obligations as owed especially to other members, as not exhausted by black- letter law but rather flowing from a set of shared principles which the laws and their enforcement presupposes, and which generate obligations not made explicit by law; and the requirement that members be able to offer a coherent account of the community s commitments that encompasses the commitments of all its members ensures equal concern. (7) So only communities of principle can support legitimate political authorities. (8) The US government, for all its faults, is a legitimate political authority (at least, we ll want to interpret it s commitments in a way that makes it legitimate. (9) So Dworkin (so he claims) must be right in interpreting the role of law in our society along the interpretive, integrity- emphasizing lines that he does. At the 3

very least, this is the only interpretation that allows our state to be legitimate, and we should strive to make it the true interpretation! Of course, this conclusion depends on the sharp claim Dworkin makes at the outset: there can be no legitimate political authority in the absence of a general obligation to obey the law. Also, as Dworkin acknowledges, the obligation to obey is (at most) a necessary condition for the legitimate use of force to ensure obedience. Why is the government justified in using force to compel fulfilling this one aspect of our political obligations, but not our other obligations (including other political obligations)? 4

MIT OpenCourseWare http://ocw.mit.edu 24.235J / 17.021J Philosophy of Law Spring 2012 For information about citing these materials or our Terms of Use, visit: http://ocw.mit.edu/terms.