Philosophy and Real Politics, by Raymond Geuss. Princeton: Princeton University Press, ix pp. $19.95 (cloth).

Similar documents
Politics between Philosophy and Democracy

THE MEANING OF IDEOLOGY

Commentary on Idil Boran, The Problem of Exogeneity in Debates on Global Justice

Political Norms and Moral Values

From the veil of ignorance to the overlapping consensus: John Rawls as a theorist of communication

CHAPTER 1 PROLOGUE: VALUES AND PERSPECTIVES

Economic philosophy of Amartya Sen Social choice as public reasoning and the capability approach. Reiko Gotoh

Phil 115, May 24, 2007 The threat of utilitarianism

CHAPTER 1 PROLOGUE: VALUES AND PERSPECTIVES

The Justification of Justice as Fairness: A Two Stage Process

David Adams UNESCO. From the International Year to a Decade for a Culture of Peace and Non-violence

RESPONSE TO JAMES GORDLEY'S "GOOD FAITH IN CONTRACT LAW: The Problem of Profit Maximization"

Last time we discussed a stylized version of the realist view of global society.

2. Tovey and Share argue: In effect, all sociologies are national sociologies Do you agree?

Notes from discussion in Erik Olin Wright Lecture #2: Diagnosis & Critique Middle East Technical University Tuesday, November 13, 2007

Prof. Ljupco Kevereski, PhD. Faculty of Education, Bitola UDK: ISBN , 16 (2011), p Original scientific paper

Grassroots Policy Project

Rawls, Islam, and political constructivism: Some questions for Tampio

LAW AND POVERTY. The role of final speaker at a two and one half day. The truth is, as could be anticipated, that your

POLITICAL SCIENCE (POLI)

Student Text Student Practice Book Activities and Projects

Critical Social Theory in Public Administration

A conception of human rights is meant to play a certain role in global political

National identity and global culture

UNM Department of History. I. Guidelines for Cases of Academic Dishonesty

Global Ethics: An Introduction Written by Kimberly Hutchings Cambridge: Polity, 2010 (ISBN: ) 244pp.

CRITIQUING POSTMODERN PHILOSOPHIES IN CONTEMPORARY FEMINIST JURISPRUDENCE

Ultimate Political Entities. The Example of The State

ON ALEJANDRO PORTES: ECONOMIC SOCIOLOGY. A SYSTEMATIC INQUIRY (Princeton: Princeton University Press, pp. )

Department of Political Science Graduate Course Descriptions Fall 2014

International Security: An Analytical Survey

Introduction. in this web service Cambridge University Press

Do we have a strong case for open borders?

Justice As Fairness: Political, Not Metaphysical (Excerpts)

SUSTAINING SOCIETIES: TOWARDS A NEW WE. The Bahá í International Community s Statement to the United Nations Conference on Sustainable Development

Summary. The Politics of Innovation in Public Transport Issues, Settings and Displacements

Legal Reasoning, the Rule of Law, and Legal Theory: Comments on Gerald Postema, Positivism and the Separation of the Realists from their Skepticism

New Directions for the Capability Approach: Deliberative Democracy and Republicanism

Ordering Power: Contentious Politics and Authoritarian Leviathans in Southeast Asia

Facts and Principles in Political Constructivism Michael Buckley Lehman College, CUNY

Ideology COLIN J. BECK

Themes and Scope of this Book

Clive Barnett, University of Exeter: Remarks on Does democracy need the city? Conversations on Power and Space in the City Workshop No.

Business Ethics Journal Review

Information Note. for IGC 39. Prepared by Mr. Ian Goss, the IGC Chair

Disagreement, Error and Two Senses of Incompatibility The Relational Function of Discursive Updating

Two Pictures of the Global-justice Debate: A Reply to Tan*

1100 Ethics July 2016

4 Activism and the Academy

Iran Academia Study Program

Are Asian Sociologies Possible? Universalism versus Particularism

FROM MODERNIZATION TO MODES OF PRODUCTION

Book Review: Lessons of Everyday Law/Le Droit du Quotidien, by Roderick A. Macdonald

What is left unsaid; implicatures in political discourse.

College of Arts and Sciences. Political Science

Socio-Legal Course Descriptions

Cemal Burak Tansel (ed)

Jan Narveson and James P. Sterba

INTERNET GOVERNANCE: STRIKING THE APPROPRIATE BALANCE BETWEEN ALL STAKEHOLDERS

Challenging Political Theory: Pluralism and Method in the Work of Bernard Williams

Intellectual Freedom Policy August 2011

Rethinking critical realism: Labour markets or capitalism?

Law and Philosophy (2015) 34: Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2015 DOI /s ARIE ROSEN BOOK REVIEW

Where does Confucian Virtuous Leadership Stand? A Critique of Daniel Bell s Beyond Liberal Democracy

S.L. Hurley, Justice, Luck and Knowledge, (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2003), 341 pages. ISBN: (hbk.).

Controversy Liberalism, Democracy and the Ethics of Votingponl_

The present volume is an accomplished theoretical inquiry. Book Review. Journal of. Economics SUMMER Carmen Elena Dorobăț VOL. 20 N O.

On Human Rights by James Griffin, Oxford University Press, 2008, 339 pp.

Was Grandpa Really a Moron?

IN THE MATTER OF AN ARBITRATION UNDER CHAPTER ELEVEN OF THE NORTH AMERICAN FREE TRADE AGREEMENT AND THE UNCITRAL ARBITRATION RULES (1976)

Dewey in Spanish. Shane Ralston. Education and Culture, Volume 22, Number 1, 2006, pp (Review)

Deep Democracy: Community, Diversity, Transformation. In recent years, scholars of American philosophy have done considerable

SPECIAL ISSUE ON TRANSITIONAL JUSTICE

The historical sociology of the future

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

F852QP. GOVERNMENT AND POLITICS Unit F852: Contemporary Government of the UK Specimen Paper. Advanced Subsidiary GCE. Time: 1 hour 30 mins

Radically Transforming Human Rights for Social Work Practice

Introduction. Animus, and Why It Matters. Which of these situations is not like the others?

This is not a book of exegesis of Aristotle s political development, nor a contribution to and attempt at

BOOK PROFILE: RELIGION, POLITICS,

The State of Our Field: Introduction to the Special Issue

Qualities of Effective Leadership and Its impact on Good Governance

The Bias of Temperament in American Politics

Press Release learning these lessons and actually implementing them are the most implication of the conclusions of the Commission.

Lilie Chouliaraki Cosmopolitanism. Book section

Programme Specification

Programme Specification

Review of Social Economy. The Uncertain Foundations of Post Keynesian Economics: Essays in Exploration. By Stephen P. Dunn.

Between justice and legal closure. Looted art claims and the passage of time

Chapter 1 The Tasks of Emancipatory Social Science draft 2.3

Power: A Radical View by Steven Lukes

Julie Doyle: Mediating Climate Change. Farnham, England: Ashgate Publishing Limited Kirsten Mogensen

Review of Roger E. Backhouse s The puzzle of modern economics: science or ideology? Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010, 214 pp.

BOOK REVIEW: WHY LA W MA TTERS BY ALON HAREL

A-Level POLITICS PAPER 3

Republicanism: Midway to Achieve Global Justice?

What is the Relationship Between The Idea of the Minimum and Distributive Justice?

How to approach legitimacy

Rockefeller College, University at Albany, SUNY Department of Political Science Graduate Course Descriptions Fall 2016

Playing Fair and Following the Rules

Transcription:

NOTE: this is the final MS, before copy-editing, of Patchen Markell, review of Raymond Geuss, Philosophy and Real Politics, published in Political Theory 38, no. 1 (February 2010): 172 77. 2010 SAGE Publications. The version of record is available online at http://dx.doi.org/ 10.1177/0090591709348870 Philosophy and Real Politics, by Raymond Geuss. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2008. ix + 116 pp. $19.95 (cloth). To anyone who is unable to endure the fate of the age like a man, we must say that he should return to the welcoming and merciful embrace of the old churches. That was the stark choice Max Weber offered his young auditors late in 1917, as he spoke against professorial prophecy and other category mistakes. i Raymond Geuss s Philosophy and Real Politics is a bracing polemic in this Weberian spirit. Its target is what Geuss calls the ethics-first approach to political philosophy, exemplified centrally by neo-kantianism, and preeminently by the work of John Rawls. Adherents of this view, Geuss says, suppose that one can complete the work of ethics first, attaining an ideal theory of how we should act preferably with as little reference to specific historical situations as possible and then in a second step...apply that theory to the action of political agents (8). Against this, Geuss defends what he calls realist political philosophy or theory (Geuss uses these terms interchangeably, and I will follow his usage here), whose patrons include not only Weber but also Nietzsche and Lenin (32). This form of political thought is devoted to the study of historically instantiated forms of collective human action, with particular attention to the configurations and distributions of power these involve; the concrete alternatives available to actors at particular times; and the modes of legitimation through which people evaluate political phenomena (22). Yes, evaluate: Geuss s brand of realism is notable because it does not

deny the political relevance or efficacy of norms, even of morality. Geuss objects only to the distorting inflation of the pre-philosophical practice of moral evaluation into a putatively all-encompassing theory of politics. Individuals or groups can cultivate their ethical intuitions and exercise their capacities for moral approval or disapproval ad libitum, he allows, as long as they do not confuse that with attaining any understanding whatever of the world in which they live, or think that their (clarified) moral intuitions have some special standing as completely adequate guides to political action (99). Nor is Geuss s brand of realism meant to be deradicalizing: one of Geuss s objections to ethics-first political philosophy, as it turns out, is that its inattention to the historical character of real politics has ideological effects, distracting political theorists from the structures of power that ought to command their attention. The purpose of this polemic, as Geuss puts it, is not to change the minds of people who already have firmly fixed settled opinions on how political philosophy must be done. Instead, writing for those who share his dissatisfaction with the ethics-first approach, or whose views of the point of political theory are unformed or unsettled, Geuss aspires to sketch a viable way of thinking about politics that is orthogonal to the mainstream of contemporary analytic political philosophy (18). The two long chapters that make up the bulk of the book pursue this aim in two different ways: the first is constructive; the second, critical. Geuss begins by elaborating his own account of the nature of politics, and draws from this a catalogue of the tasks of political theory (37). To say that we are political creatures, for Geuss, means that we are bound to each other by various relations of power, and we try to act in a concerted way under pressure of time and resources, and in such a way as to give some kind of account to ourselves and others

about why we are acting in the way we are (37). Against this background, political theory or philosophy can do (and has done) many things. It can help us understand how the organised forms of acting together in a given society actually work (37 38); it can aid us in the evaluation (and not only the moral evaluation) of political acts and arrangements; it can help us achieve a sense of orientation in relation to some larger imaginative structure that gives sense or significance to our political activity (40 42); it can help political actors reconceive their situation, and the nature of the problems they confront, by inventing new thought-instrument[s] or conceptual tool[s] (43); and it can engage in the exposure and criticism of ideological illusion, by which Geuss means the distorted presentation of particular beliefs and as though they were universal (52 53). (Geuss allows that political philosophy can also itself be ideological, either deliberately or inadvertently, if it diverts attention away from the power relations in which political issues are inevitably embedded; but this, he seems to suggest, is reputable task for political theory [54 55].) And, of course, since politics is historically located, performing any of these tasks well will demand at least some attention to the specific cultural and historical and circumstances in which political action is undertaken (13, 15). Geuss s account of the point of political theory is refreshing and inspiring. Refreshing, because it allows political theory several tasks instead of assigning it only one; because it confounds the division of labor between is and ought that has helped define relations between political theory and political science since World War II, too often with the acquiesence of political theorists; because it likewise refuses the division of labor within political theory between (to borrow the census categories of the American

Political Science Association) normative and historical approaches; and because it makes it seem puzzling rather than obviously sensible that historically minded political theorists should so commonly confine themselves to intellectual history. And inspiring, because it names, renders legible, and helps to legitimate some modes of inquiry that often fall between the cracks of the field s better-recognized rubrics. Geuss s characterization of conceptual innovation is especially compelling in this respect: such innovation, he insists, involves more than merely the pragmatic invention of tools for a theoretical purpose given in advance say, to help people judge between two possible courses of action (49); instead, it involves the application of the theoretical imagination to situations in which people are at a loss what to do not because they are unsure which option is better, but because they are confused about what is wrong or what the problem precisely is (43). I do not think I will be the only reader who will take pleasure in finding some of his or her own inchoate aspirations reflected, and made eloquent, in these pages. In the second part of the book, Geuss develops his critique of ethics-first political theory in greatest detail, exploring what he calls failures of realism in the work of Rawls and Robert Nozick (the former of whom receives the bulk of Geuss s attention). In each case, Geuss begins by exposing the historically contingent, indeed parochial character of some foundational concept that Nozick ( rights ) or Rawls ( justice ) treats ahistorically; in the latter case this initial argument opens out into a wider attack on Rawls s appeals to intuition, which for Geuss have the effect of falsely universalizing the historically specific views of Rawls s implied audience of postwar American liberals. This, being the book s most polemical part, is also likely to be the most controversial, and

while I have no particular interest in defending Rawls (indeed I am broadly sympathetic to the claim that Rawls s thought fares poorly as a theory of real politics in Geuss s sense), some aspects of Geuss s argument strike me as, at least, overstated, including especially the suggestion that Rawls s main argumentative strategy is to appeal to the intuitions of his readers, which overlooks the fact that Rawls s defense of justice as fairness depends crucially on the limits he places on the role of intuitionism in moral argument. But there is a larger issue here, for Geuss himself says that he is less interested, in this text, in the details of Rawls s view than in the particular style of theorising about politics he represents (70) a style whose importance Geuss hopes to deflate, and perhaps even to rule out of court entirely. (In a longer treatment of Rawls, Geuss has written that for those with his sort of views about politics, Rawls is not a major moral and political theorist, whose work self-evidently deserves and repays the most careful scrutiny ; ii and in the present book he writes that in real politics, theories like that of Rawls are nonstarters, except, as course, as potential ideological interventions [94] and recall that ideological intervention, as opposed to ideology-critique, appeared to be outside the family of respectable tasks for political philosophy.) It seems to me, however, that a different strategy might serve Geuss, and those who find themselves sympathetic to his line of criticism, better than the gatekeeping approach on view here. For if A Theory of Justice is indeed an attempt to reconcile Americans to an idealised version of their own social order at the end of the twentieth century (89), it is at least an extraordinarily explicit, systematic, and detailed attempt a wonderfully rich vein of source material, one would think, for anyone who wished to launch a more radical

critique of that order by identifying and sharpening its symptomatic tensions and contradictions. (I think here of Marx s attitude toward the classical political economists.) Rather than repudiate Rawls (94), in other words, why not give him the most careful scrutiny, only without assuming that such scrutiny must be oriented toward answering the same questions (or the same genre of questions) that Rawls himself asked? Indeed, this approach would, I think, be most consistent with the appealing picture of the tasks of political theory that Geuss develops in the first part of Philosophy and Real Politics, not least because it would provide an occasion to set a book like A Theory of Justice into the specific historical contexts, intellectual and otherwise, to which it belongs but to which it does not draw attention. It might also help Geuss bridge an important gap in his own distinctive brand of realism. It is by no means obvious that political realism, and in particular its focus on the concrete choices among limited alternatives made by agents with finite resources, will necessarily harmonize well with the critique of ideology, which, for Geuss, paradigmatically involves showing how the dominant frame in which a particular problem is being debated obscures the underlying issue in that case. (Geuss uses this phrase in the course of explaining why moral outrage at the unjust pricing of pharmaceuticals and medical care could be considered ideological: because it draws attention away from the deeper problem in this domain, which lies in the very existence of a free market for drugs and medical services [54].) Yet a realist focus on the limited choices facing concrete political agents could just as easily narrow as widen the political imagination in such cases, licensing the dismissal of more radical diagnoses like Geuss s on the grounds that they aren t responsive to the concrete decisions that actors must make here and now. This collapsing of the space for

serious challenges to major social and political institutions is arguably one role the language of realism played in American politics in the years following World War II. And this, in the end, is why a theorist like Geuss might profit in a surprising way from the mediating work performed by bodies of political theory like that of Rawls. Everyday practices of moral approval and disapproval tend to be closely tied to particular cases. For this reason, even when a particular case is controversial, the terms of that controversy will often be limited in scope; they may be more likely to obscure than to highlight certain background assumptions that are common to many or all of the disputants, but which might seem highly questionable indeed ideological in the longer and broader view Geuss wishes us to take. In elaborating a systematic moral theory, however, a theorist like Rawls supposes himself to be bringing the implicit structure of our ordinary moral judgments into the foreground (and also refining those judgments in the process), which means that his work already begins to transcend the limits of the discourse around this or that particular issue, and to broach larger, structural and systematic themes. To be sure, the systematic themes that concern Rawls are not the ones that concern Geuss; but you do not need to think that Rawls s theory is valid, or coherent, or that it provides an adequate political vocabulary, in order to exploit the movement that it traces from the specific towards the general, and to use its systematicity symptomatically, diagnostically to help disclose political possibilities that might seem unrealistic, in the pejorative sense, if broached in the context of a relatively narrow dispute about a single political issue. Put differently, the Weberian choice that Geuss demands of us, between non-theoretical moral evaluation and

theoretical understanding, may be too stark for Geuss himself, if he wishes to join realism to radicalism. Patchen Markell The University of Chicago AUTHOR S NOTE: Thanks to Lena Zuckerwise for helpful comments on a draft of this review. i Max Weber, Science as a Vocation, in The Vocation Lectures, ed. David Owen and Tracy B. Strong, trans. Rodney Livingstone (Indianapolis: Hackett, 2004), 30 31. ii Raymond Geuss, Outside Ethics (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2005), 39.