Response to Robert P. George, Natural Law, the Constitution, and the Theory and Practice of Judicial Review

Similar documents
Constitutional Self-Government: A Reply to Rubenfeld

Juridical Coups d état all over the place. Comment on The Juridical Coup d état and the Problem of Authority by Alec Stone Sweet

The Doctrine of Judicial Review and Natural Law

The Forgotten Principles of American Government by Daniel Bonevac

1100 Ethics July 2016

Volume 60, Issue 1 Page 241. Stanford. Cass R. Sunstein

Medellin's Clear Statement Rule: A Solution for International Delegations

Chapter 8 - Judiciary. AP Government

Law and Philosophy (2015) 34: Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2015 DOI /s ARIE ROSEN BOOK REVIEW

Rawls versus the Anarchist: Justice and Legitimacy

Controversy Liberalism, Democracy and the Ethics of Votingponl_

AP US Government: The Judiciary Test(including the Supreme Court) Study Guide There was no judicial system under the Articles of Confederation

To Say What the Law Is: Judicial Authority in a Political Context Keith E. Whittington PROSPECTUS THE ARGUMENT: The volume explores the political

Introduction 478 U.S. 186 (1986) U.S. 558 (2003). 3

Curriculum Unit. Instructional Unit

Agencies Should Ignore Distant-Future Generations

RESPONSE TO JAMES GORDLEY'S "GOOD FAITH IN CONTRACT LAW: The Problem of Profit Maximization"

INTRODUCTION THE NATURE OF THE JUDICIAL SYSTEM

AP U.S. Government and Politics: 1999 Exam

The Mason Papers Leslie Zines. All rights reserved.

The Influences of Legal Realism in Plessy, Brown and Parents Involved

A Comment on Professor David L. Shapiro s The Role of Precedent in Constitutional Adjudication: An Introspection

AP Gov Chapter 15 Outline

Course Title: Advanced Placement American Government and Politics

DR. BERNARD J. MAUSER DR. RICHARD LAND

CHAPTER ONE INTRODUCTION

Foreword: Symposium on Federal Judicial Power

The Constitution in One Sentence: Understanding the Tenth Amendment

Council President James A. Klein s memo to members: policy priorities will need to overcome partisan conflict

Politics between Philosophy and Democracy

Mapp v. ohio (1961) rights of the accused. directions

Big Idea 2 Objectives Explain the extent to which states are limited by the due process clause from infringing upon individual rights.

Chantal Mouffe On the Political

Judge Thomas Buergenthal Justice 2018: Charting the Course March 13, 2008 International Center for Ethics, Justice, and Public Life

Bradley v. American Smelting & Refining Co.,

Election Campaigns and Democracy: A Review of James A. Gardner, What Are Campaigns For? The Role of Persuasion in Electoral Law and Politics

Comments on Environmental Justice, Human Rights, and the Global South by Professor Carmen Gonzalez

Last time we discussed a stylized version of the realist view of global society.

NEW YORK UNIVERSITY Department of Politics V COMPARATIVE POLITICS Spring Michael Laver. Tel:

NEW YORK UNIVERSITY Department of Politics. V COMPARATIVE POLITICS Spring Michael Laver Tel:

Comments: Individual Versus Collective Responsibility

Government Involvement in Health Care

Freedom in a Democratic Society

[pp ] CONSTITUTIONAL CHANGE 1: FORTY ACRES AND A MULE

IN THE CIRCUIT COURT OF THE FIFTEENTH JUDICIAL CIRCUIT OF FLORIDA, IN AND FOR PALM BEACH COUNTY, FLORIDA. v. CASE NO DR001269XXXNB

Of Inkblots and Originalism: Historical Ambiguity and the Case of the Ninth Amendment

Aristotle (Odette) Aristotle s Nichomachean Ethics

Gender Equality in the Courts: Women's Work Is Never Done

Choose one question from each section to answer in the time allotted.

A BORKEAN REVIVAL INTRODUCTION

South Carolina s Exposition Against the Tariff of 1828 By John C. Calhoun (Anonymously)

The Dumbarton Oaks Proposal

LJMU Research Online

Ehrenzweig on the Law of Conflict of Laws

Interpreting the Constitution

SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES

Popular dissatisfaction with the administration of justice

EUROPEAN COMMUNITIES MEASURES AFFECTING THE APPROVAL AND MARKETING OF BIOTECH PRODUCTS (WT/DS291/292/293)

ORIGINALISM AND PRECEDENT

REDEMPTION, FAITH AND THE POST-CIVIL WAR AMENDMENT PARADOX: THE TALK

The Supreme Court, Civil Liberties, and Civil Rights

Courses PROGRAM AT THE SCHOOL OF INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS AND DIPLOMACY. Course List. The Government and Politics in China

CHAPTER 1 PROLOGUE: VALUES AND PERSPECTIVES

Judicial Legislation, by Fred V. Cahill

How have changes in technology influenced political communication and behavior? Why do levels of participation and influence in politics vary?

Penalizing Public Disobedience*

Slavery, Abortion, and the Politics of Constitutional Meaning

STATE HEARING QUESTIONS

CPI Antitrust Journal November 2010 (1)

Adam Harris. Why We Should Vote: Voting Abstention and African-Americans. Alabama A&M University. Phone: (540)

THE "UNWRITTEN CONSTITUTION" AND THE U.C.C.

WHY THE SUPREME COURT WAS CORRECT TO DENY CERTIORARI IN FTC V. RAMBUS

In Defense of Rawlsian Constructivism

Part 1. Understanding Human Rights

Two Thoughts About Obergefell v. Hodges

The Rights and Wrongs of Taking Rights Seriously

College of Arts and Sciences. Political Science

Fordham Law Review. Volume 45 Issue 4 Article 7. Recommended Citation

Cases and Materials on Remedies

Colorado and U.S. Constitutions

Definition: Property rights in oneself comparable to property rights in inanimate things

Courts, Judges, and the Law

Separation of Powers: History and Theory

Xavier University s Ethics/Religion, and Society Program The Cooperative Economy: Building a Sustainable Future Quarterly Grant Proposal

March 22, Examination of Goodwin Liu, Nominee to the United States Court of Appeals for the Ninth Circuit

Rendering Legal Assistance to Similarly Situated Individuals

APPLICATION FORM FOR PROSPECTIVE WORKSHOP DIRECTORS

Putting the Gun Control Debate in Social Perspective

***JURISDICTION: A court s power to rule on a case. There are two primary systems of courts in the U.S.:

POLITICAL SCIENCE (POL S)

Federal and State Court System CHAPTER 13

Our Democracy Uncorrupted

The author of this important volume

IV. GENERAL RECOMMENDATIONS ADOPTED BY THE COMMITTEE ON THE ELIMINATION OF DISCRIMINATION AGAINST WOMEN. Thirtieth session (2004)

A political theory of territory

NATIONAL HEARING QUESTIONS ACADEMIC YEAR

Chapter 13: The Judiciary

Toward a Feminist Theory of Justice: Political liberalism and Feminist Method

INDIANA HIGH SCHOOL HEARING QUESTIONS Congressional District / Regional Level

Landmark Case SEXUAL ORIENTATION AND THE CHARTER VRIEND v. ALBERTA

Transcription:

Fordham Law Review Volume 69 Issue 6 Article 3 2001 Response to Robert P. George, Natural Law, the Constitution, and the Theory and Practice of Judicial Review Joseph W. Koterski Recommended Citation Joseph W. Koterski, Response to Robert P. George, Natural Law, the Constitution, and the Theory and Practice of Judicial Review, 69 Fordham L. Rev. 2297 (2001). Available at: http://ir.lawnet.fordham.edu/flr/vol69/iss6/3 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by FLASH: The Fordham Law Archive of Scholarship and History. It has been accepted for inclusion in Fordham Law Review by an authorized editor of FLASH: The Fordham Law Archive of Scholarship and History. For more information, please contact tmelnick@law.fordham.edu.

RESPONSE TO ROBERT P. GEORGE, NATURAL LAW, THE CONSTITUTION, AND THE THEORY AND PRACTICE OF JUDICIAL REVIEW Joseph W. Koterski, S.J.* Hearty thanks to Professor George for a sophisticated comment on the practice of judicial review in light of natural law ethics.' In taking as controversial a case as Griswold v. Connecticut, 2 he rightly reminds those of us who are partisans of natural law theory about its checkered history in much the same way that Yves Simon's The Tradition of Natural Law does when recounting the many ways that the ideal of natural law can be used-and sometimes abusedideologically by the left and by the right in the hopes of giving the appearance of objectivity to what is really only political willfulness. 3 Whether the issue is a public matter like slavery racism, busing, desegregation or quotas, let alone the claims about marital privacy that came to the fore in Griswold, the possibility is enormous for one side or the other to use the rhetoric of "natural right" or "natural law" for something that is really a matter of political will. To put the matter another way, not every argument that claims to be a good natural law argument is really entitled to the natural law banner. The trouble, of course, is: "Who's to say?" As Stephen Krason, whom Professor George cites, likes to argue, natural law arguments depend on careful reasoning and bringing reasonable people to see the compelling nature of the arguments offered.- Hence there are good natural law arguments and bad natural law arguments, but the fact that there is disagreement should not prevent us from attempting to make such arguments. Rather, it should challenge us to make the best * Philosophical Resource Director and Associate Professor, Department of Philosophy, Fordham University. S.T.L., M. Div., Weston School of Theology: Ph.D., M.A. Philosophy, St. Louis University; H.A.B., Xavier University. 1. Robert P. George, Natural Law, the Constitution, and the Theory and Practice of Judicial Review, 69 Fordham L. Rev. 2269 (2001). 2. 381 U.S. 479 (1965). 3. Yves R. Simon, The Tradition of Natural Law (1965) 4. I mean here to refer to that pro-slavery position which invoked Aristotle's idea of "natural servitude." 5. Stephen M. Krason, Constitutional Interpretation, Unenutnerated Rights, and the Natural Law, 1 Cath. Soc. Sci. Rev. 20 (1996). 2297

2298 FORDHAM LAW REVIEW [Vol. 69 case we can, mindful of the possible pitfalls. George's reminder to us that there are competing schools of thought about judicial review is deeply appreciated. He reviews some of the different positions that can be taken about the legitimacy of the practice of judicial review as well as about the proper limits of its scope, once the practice is recognized in principle. I especially appreciated the historical notes about the difference between those legal traditions where judicial review has grown up in common law practice, and those constitutions which expressly provide for a power of judicial review, whether constituted in a limited way for the purpose of reconciling statutory law with constitutional principles or constituted more expansively so that a certain level of the judiciary is invested with the power to overturn legislation that is seen to violate natural law principles. It is my understanding that this is the situation, for instance, in Austria today. Clearly, Professor George's preference at the level of political philosophy is for restricting considerations about substantive justice to the political arena of legislation and not allowing appeals to the natural law to enter the judicial sphere by way of a natural law jurisprudence of judicial review. He allows for the possibility that a constitution may make explicit provision for a judiciary to overturn legislation on the basis of natural law considerations. His understandably pessimistic evaluation about the likelihood of judges remembering to restrain their desires to put things aright, however, leads him prudentially to prefer that this power not be explicitly assigned to the judiciary. In this paper he claims that natural law ethics itself does not determine where the power should be vested. In practice, I have absolutely no disagreement with him. But I would beg to differ with him theoretically. Let me put this as a philosophical question about the very nature of authority in general and about civil authority in particular. I grant that natural law allows for quite diverse forms of government and for different ways of vesting the various powers that properly belong to civil authorityincluding our own practice of the separation of powers into different branches so as to prevent or minimize the abuse of power. If I have understood him correctly, he holds that the natural law does not decide the question of where any power of statutory review should be located. Thus, Professor George contends that we should require an express constitutional provision for the judiciary to use substantive justice known by natural law as the standard for judgment; otherwise, they should limit themselves to questions of procedural fairness. I find it questionable to hold that there is no natural law warrant for judges especially to employ insights about substantive questions of justice to overturn legislation that violates natural law principles. Authority, it seems to me, in any of its forms, is a matter of witnessing to truths that are earlier, higher, or logically prior to itself, and using

2001] KO TERSKI RESPONSE TO GEORGE 2299 powers responsibly for that purpose. Civil authority will invariably bring itself into contempt by excessively activist judicial legislation, but civil authority can also fail by defect. It can do so, for instance in the scenario of judges who will not assert themselves to halt injustice that gets embodied in legislation, whether by the will of an activist legislature or by a legislature whipped into action by a media-induced frenzy in the populace. Indeed, such a scenario is not hard to imagine in the recent muddle over the Electoral College and could equally be the case, say, with regards to the natural human rights of immigrants in an unexpected economic downturn. Put another way, I think that we dare not restrict questions of substantive justice known by way of natural law to the realm of politics and legislation-we dare not do so because of what natural law requires. We must rather insist that the natural law requires that all three powers of government (whether these powers are separated as in our system or combined in some other form of government) need to call to mind and to act according to substantive justice and not just procedural fairness. Professor George has argued that there is nothing about the natural law that gives this role to the judicial branch, so long as some branch of government has the role. Yet I do not see that the natural law allows any branch (within a polity whose powers are separated into distinct branches) to be excused from this function. The old adage that justice needs to be in the heart of the judge applies not just to cases of equity (where a judge must go beyond the letter of the law in order to bring about justice in a situation where there would be some injustice done by strict application of the letter of the law because legislators could not foresee all possible cases and because their necessarily general perspective did not adequately take into account the relevant circumstances), but also to cases where political willfulness has brought to the fore a piece of legislation that clearly and directly violates the principles of natural law. Now there remains a useful distinction here between, on the one hand, admitting that jurists may use natural law principles to overturn legislation in the course of judicial review, and, on the other hand, attempts at judicial legislation by any activist court. In a system with separation of powers like our own, to refuse to the courts any lawmaking role at all is one thing, but it is quite another to recognize that this part of the body politic bears a unique and special responsibility for witnessing to the truths about justice and for using the powers within its discretion to overturn legislation that violates justice. Naturally, there will be a need for tremendous prudence and incredible reserve to prevent judges from straying into the judicial activism that has risked contempt, but to say that the rule of law entails that courts have no legitimate authority to witness to truths about substantive questions of justice strikes me as excessive. It is the

2300 FORDHAM LAW REVIEW [Vol. 69 moral virtue of restraint that they need, not the removal of responsibility for giving witness to what authorities are supposed to give witness in their maintenance of the common good and the rule of law.