George Mason University School of Law

Similar documents
The Unsolvable Dilemma of a Paretian Policymaker

HARVARD JOHN M. OLIN CENTER FOR LAW, ECONOMICS, AND BUSINESS

Any non-welfarist method of policy assessment violates the Pareto principle: A comment

FAIRNESS VERSUS WELFARE. Louis Kaplow & Steven Shavell. Thesis: Policy Analysis Should Be Based Exclusively on Welfare Economics

The Conflict between Notions of Fairness and the Pareto Principle

Nordic Journal of Political Economy

Some reflections on the role of moral reasoning in economics

What (if Anything) Can Economics Say About Equity?

The Fairness of Sanctions: Some Implications for Optimal Enforcement Policy

Kaplow, Louis, and Shavell, Steven. Fairness versus Welfare. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, Pp $50.00 (cloth).

Obscenity and Community Standards: A Social Choice Approach

The Restoration of Welfare Economics

MARQUETTE UNIVERSITY

Economic philosophy of Amartya Sen Social choice as public reasoning and the capability approach. Reiko Gotoh

Chapter 4: Voting and Social Choice.

Regulatory Policy Program

Voting Criteria April

University of Southern California Law School

The relation between the prosecutor, the attorney and the client in plea bargaining : a principal-agent model 1

Matthew Adler, a law professor at the Duke University, has written an amazing book in defense

Keywords: Pareto Efficiency, Wealth-Maximization, Sources of Law, Lawmaking Process, Unanimity, Product Liability.

ECONOMICS AND INEQUALITY: BLINDNESS AND INSIGHT. Sanjay Reddy. I am extremely grateful to Bina Agarwal, IAFFE S President, and to IAFFE for its

The axiomatic approach to population ethics

Economic Growth and the Interests of Future (and Past and Present) Generations: A Comment on Tyler Cowen

The George Washington University Department of Economics

THE EFFECT OF OFFER-OF-SETTLEMENT RULES ON THE TERMS OF SETTLEMENT

1 Aggregating Preferences

Agencies Should Ignore Distant-Future Generations

Problems with Group Decision Making

Problems with Group Decision Making

Rawls versus the Anarchist: Justice and Legitimacy

The interaction effect of economic freedom and democracy on corruption: A panel cross-country analysis

SYSTEM DYNAMICS Vol. II - A Pervasive Duality in Economic Systems: Implications for Development Planning - Khalid Saeed

Arrow s Impossibility Theorem on Social Choice Systems

Do not turn over until you are told to do so by the Invigilator.

University of Southern California Law School

ECONOMIC POLICIES AND SOCIO-ECONOMIC CLAUSES IN THE SOUTH AFRICAN BILL OF RIGHTS.

UC Berkeley Latin American and Caribbean Law and Economics Association (ALACDE) Annual Papers

On Sen s Liberal Paradox and its Reception within Political Theory and Welfare Economics

James M. Buchanan The Limits of Market Efficiency

Northwestern University School of Law

Planning versus Free Choice in Scientific Research

Definition: Property rights in oneself comparable to property rights in inanimate things

Essays on Incentives and Regulation

Human Development and the current economic and social challenges

Limited arbitrage is necessary and sufficient for the existence of an equilibrium

Experimental Computational Philosophy: shedding new lights on (old) philosophical debates

Christian List. 177 Mission Impossible, DPhil-thesis, University of Oxford BIBLIOGRAPHY

Wolters Kluwer. Constitutional Values and European Contract Law. Stefan Grundmann KLUWER LAW INTERNATIONAL. Law & Business

THREATS TO SUE AND COST DIVISIBILITY UNDER ASYMMETRIC INFORMATION. Alon Klement. Discussion Paper No /2000

The Economics of US-style Contingent Fees and UK-style Conditional Fees

Can Negative Utilitarianism be Salvaged?

HARVARD JOHN M. OLIN CENTER FOR LAW, ECONOMICS, AND BUSINESS

University of Pennsylvania Law Review FOUNDED 1852

COWLES FOUNDATION FOR RESEARCH IN ECONOMICS YALE UNIVERSITY

Review of Paul Anand s Happiness explained. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2016, 143 pp. TIM. E. TAYLOR

Working Paper No. 13/05. Personal responsibility and income distribution

A NOTE ON THE THEORY OF SOCIAL CHOICE

I assume familiarity with multivariate calculus and intermediate microeconomics.

Willingness to Pay versus Welfare

Reconciling Educational Adequacy and Equity Arguments Through a Rawlsian Lens

Amman, Jordan T: F: /JordanStrategyForumJSF Jordan Strategy Forum

Part III Immigration Policy: Introduction

The Social Choice Theory: Can it be considered a Complete Political Theory?

A Liberal Theory of Social Welfare: Fairness, Utility, and the Pareto Principle

CORRUPTION AND OPTIMAL LAW ENFORCEMENT. A. Mitchell Polinsky Steven Shavell. Discussion Paper No /2000. Harvard Law School Cambridge, MA 02138

Lecture 7 Act and Rule Utilitarianism. Based on slides 2011 Pearson Education, Inc. Publishing as Pearson Addison-Wesley

Tradeoffs in implementation of SDGs: how to integrate perspectives of different stakeholders?

Collective Action: Current Perspectives

Volume 60, Issue 1 Page 241. Stanford. Cass R. Sunstein

Aggregation and the Separateness of Persons

7 Chronic Poverty and Understanding Intra-household Differentiation 1

1100 Ethics July 2016

THE CAPABILITY APPROACH AS A HUMAN DEVELOPMENT PARADIGM AND ITS CRITIQUES

HARVARD JOHN M. OLIN CENTER FOR LAW, ECONOMICS, AND BUSINESS

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

VOTING ON INCOME REDISTRIBUTION: HOW A LITTLE BIT OF ALTRUISM CREATES TRANSITIVITY DONALD WITTMAN ECONOMICS DEPARTMENT UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA

Foundations of the Economic Approach to Law. Edited by AVERY WIENER KATZ

Labour market integration and its effect on child labour

Voting rules: (Dixit and Skeath, ch 14) Recall parkland provision decision:

Enriqueta Aragones Harvard University and Universitat Pompeu Fabra Andrew Postlewaite University of Pennsylvania. March 9, 2000

WHEN IS THE PREPONDERANCE OF THE EVIDENCE STANDARD OPTIMAL?

Postscript: Subjective Utilitarianism

Equality and Priority

From the veil of ignorance to the overlapping consensus: John Rawls as a theorist of communication

The public vs. private value of health, and their relationship. (Review of Daniel Hausman s Valuing Health: Well-Being, Freedom, and Suffering)

Integrating Ethics and Altruism with Economics. David Colander. December 2004 MIDDLEBURY COLLEGE ECONOMICS DISCUSSION PAPER NO.

Expected Utility, Contributory Causation, and Vegetarianism

A Welfarist Role for Nonwelfarist Rules: An Example with Envy

A CONCEPT OF PROGRESS FOR NORMATIVE ECONOMICS *

CHAPTER 19 MARKET SYSTEMS AND NORMATIVE CLAIMS Microeconomics in Context (Goodwin, et al.), 2 nd Edition

S E N, A M A R T Y A K.

On the Irrelevance of Formal General Equilibrium Analysis

MORALITY - evolutionary foundations and policy implications

Strategic Partisanship: Party Priorities, Agenda Control and the Decline of Bipartisan Cooperation in the House

HOFSTRA JAW REVIEW SYMPOSIUM: THE IMPLICATIONS OF SOCIAL CHOICE THEORY FOR LEGAL DECISIONMAKING INTRODUCTION: THE SOCIAL CHOICE PERSPECTIVE

Sentencing Guidelines, Judicial Discretion, And Social Values

PH 3022 SOCIAL AND POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY UK LEVEL 5 UK CREDITS: 15 US CREDITS: 3/0/3

NBER WORKING PAPER SERIES DISCRETIONARY POLICY AND MULTIPLE EQUILIBRIA. Robert G. King. Working Paper

Legal Change: Integrating Selective Litigation, Judicial Preferences, and Precedent

Transcription:

George Mason University School of Law Working Paper Series Year 2004 Paper 10 The Unsolvable Dilemma of a Paretian Policymaker Giuseppe Dari-Mattiacci Nuno Garoupa Universiteit van Amsterdam & George Mason University, g.darimattiacci@uva.nl Universidade Nova de Lisboa & George Mason University, ngaroupa@gmu.edu This working paper is hosted by The Berkeley Electronic Press (bepress) and may not be commercially reproduced without the permission of the copyright holder. http://law.bepress.com/gmulwps/art10 Copyright c 2004 by the authors.

The Unsolvable Dilemma of a Paretian Policymaker Giuseppe Dari-Mattiacci and Nuno Garoupa Abstract In this paper, we argue that social decisionmaking is subject to a fundamental conflict between consistency and completeness. We show that a consistent welfarist method of policy assessment, that is, one that never violates the Pareto principle, may be incomplete in the sense of being incapable of providing a solution to important social welfare problems.

The Unsolvable Dilemma of a Paretian Policymaker Giuseppe DARI-MATTIACCI Universiteit van Amsterdam George Mason University School of Law Nuno GAROUPA Universidade Nova de Lisboa CEPR, London November, 2004 The authors would like to thank Shomu Banerjee, Guilherme Carmona, Antonio Cabrales, Ward Farnsworth, João Gata, Louis Kaplow, and Jenny Monheim for helpful suggestions and extremely useful comments. Nuno Garoupa acknowledges financial support by FCT, POCTI/ECO/44146/2002. The usual disclaimers apply. Universiteit van Amsterdam ACLE, Roetersstraat 11, 1018WB Amsterdam, The Netherlands and George Mason University School of Law, 3301 Fairfax Drive, Arlington, Virginia 22201, USA. Email: gdarimat@gmu.edu. Faculdade de Economia, Universidade Nova de Lisboa, Campus de Campolide, P- 1099-032 Lisboa, Portugal. Phone: 351-21-3801600. Fax: 351-21-3870933. Email: ngaroupa@fe.unl.pt. 1 Hosted by The Berkeley Electronic Press

Abstract In this paper, we argue that social decisionmaking is subject to a fundamental conflict between consistency and completeness. We show that a consistent welfarist method of policy assessment, that is, one that never violates the Pareto principle, may be incomplete in the sense of being incapable of providing a solution to important social welfare problems. JEL: C00, D63, K00 Keywords: Individualistic social welfare, Interdependent preferences. 2 http://law.bepress.com/gmulwps/art10

1 Introduction In this paper we argue that policymaking is subject to a fundamental dilemma, one between consistency and completeness. By consistency we mean the implementation of a set of criteria for policy assessment that do not contradict each other. By completeness we refer to the ability of such a set of criteria to assess all relevant policy issues. Consistency does not imply completeness. To the contrary, as we will show, these two goals may in fact conflict. Recent literature has focused on the issue of consistency, mostly leaving the problem of completeness without discussion. 1 In particular, Kaplow and Shavell (2001) show that any non-welfarist method of policy assessment violates the Pareto principle. The implications of this result are straightforward. If policies are chosen according to criteria that are inconsistent with the welfarist method, the outcome will not maximize welfare. Consequently, they call for consistency in social decisionmaking. In our analysis we take a step further and address the issue of completeness. We analyze a model of non-trivial policy assessment that the welfarist method is potentially incapable of solving. We argue that the welfarist method may be unable to assess policies that concern the aggregation of individual preferences in a social welfare function. The reason is that, when individuals have preferences over a certain social welfare function, the problem becomes recursive and may admit no solution or an infinite number of solutions, which is not helpful for policymaking. Therefore, a consistent welfarist method may be incomplete in the sense of being incapable of providing a solution to important social welfare problems and effective policy guidance. A consequence of this conflict between consistency and and completeness is that, in many circumstances, social 1 See, however, Dari-Mattiacci (2004) considering the debate on completeness vs. consistency in mathematics and logic and its implications for welfare economics. See also McDonnel (2003) on the issue of recursivity that will be be addressed below in the text. Farnsworth (2002) addresses the issue of changes in preferences, which will be analyzed later in the text, and notices that the choice of the criterion concerning how preferences should be shaped involves non-welfarists considerations. We argue instead that, even if that criterion were entirely welfarists, the recursivity of the the logical reasoning needed to assess such policies may ultimately yield no solution to the problem. 3 Hosted by The Berkeley Electronic Press

decision-making cannot solely rest on the welfarist method. Thus, if a consistent method is incomplete, a method that guarantees completeness can only be constructed by implementing a set of criteria that allows for some internal inconsistency. The consequence is that, to be complete, social decision-making could have to take into account those fairness values, and more generally non-individualistic determinants, that were rejected at the outset because inconsistent with the Pareto principle. We should distinguish how our approach relates to Kaplow and Shavell s article from others. We do not argue, as some have done, that their analysis is incorrect. 2 In fact, what they maintain cannot be wrong as it ultimately rests on a tautology. 3 Our claim, instead, is that consistency comes at the price of incompleteness, as there are situations in which a consistent Paretian method cannot provide a satisfactory answer to the problem of ranking policies. 4 Nor do we make any statement about whether a consistent Paretian method should or should not be regarded as the preferable way to to assess social policies. We believe that Kaplow and Shavell s analysis does does not give an answer to this question 5 and nor do we. 2 See Chang (2000a and 2000b) and, for a response, Kaplow and Shavell (2000). See also Fleurbaey, Tungodden, and Chang (2003) and, for a reply, Kaplow and and Shavell (2004a). In addition, see Craswell (2003), Kornhauser (2003), and and Waldron (2003) and, for a response, Kaplow and Shavell (2003). For a more more recent critique, see Ripstein (2004) and, for a reply, Kaplow and Shavell (2004b). Finally, see Dorff (2002), Fried (2002). 3 Here we exclusively refer to the argument, and not to the article. The authors themselves qualify the core of this argument as tautological; see Kaplow and Shavell (2002, p. 7). The authors further argue that notions of fairness may be used as proxies for the Pareto principle and that notions of fairness may have evolved as rules of thumb for the implementation of the Pareto principle. These arguments are not contested here. 4 Kornhauser (2003) argues that the aggregation of preferences may be be problematic when people have preferences over different regimes of rights. This argument is similar to ours, but tries to disprove consistency rather rather than completeness as we do. For the same reason, our analysis is different different from Sen (1970). 5 Kaplow and Shavell (2002) argue that basing policy making on criteria that conflict with the Pareto principle does ultimately reduce social welfare. However, they do not systematically prove that the maximization of social welfare should be the object of policy making. See Dorff (2002) and Ferzan (2004) on this point. 4 http://law.bepress.com/gmulwps/art10

2 Analysis Let x be a complete description of the world and n the number of individuals, where x = (x 1,..., x n ) is a comprehensive account of each individual s situation. Define X to be the set of all conceivable states of the world. From Kaplow and Shavell (2001), we can make the following statements: (1) A social welfare function F is a function from X to the real line R. (2) An individual utility function for each i = 1,..., n is also a function from X to R. (3) An individualistic social welfare function is a social welfare function of the form F (U 1 (x),..., U n (x)). (4) A social welfare function is not individualistic if and only if there exist x, x X such that U i (x) = U i (x ) for all i and F (x) F (x ). (5) The weak Pareto principle is that if, for any states x, x X, we have U i (x) > U i (x ) for all i = 1,..., n, then F (x) > F (x ). (6) If a social welfare function ascribes weight to the same factor independently of its effect on individuals utilities in a non-individualistic way, then that social welfare function violates the Pareto principle (proof in Kaplow and Shavell, 2001). Suppose now that F is of the form F (U 1 (x),..., U n (x)) but U i (x, F (.)) for all i = 1,..., n. According to Bergstrom (1999), U i is an interdependent utility function such that individual i s preferences depend on his own situation but also on society welfare. 6 Then for any state of the world x it must be true that F = F (U i (x, F (.))). We are interested in whether a system of interdependent preferences determined by private subutility of x and interdependent social welfare determines a corresponding system of independent utility functions V i : X R and an independent social welfare function G(x). Unfortunately a general answer to recursive social welfare functions is not easy to find (Bergstrom, 1999; Bramoullé, 2001 and references cited therein). Multiple 6 The original terminology derives from Pollak (1976). 5 Hosted by The Berkeley Electronic Press

and infinite utilities as well as no utilities arise from the recognition that the others utility may depend on one s own utility through social welfare, and the feedback loop created by this dependency. In fact, we can say that, in general, social recursive preferences generate multiple utilities and therefore multiple social welfare functions, and only under strong assumptions, a unique system of independent utilities and therefore a unique social welfare function will exist. As an illustration, assume that U i (.) is an interdependent utility with an additively separable form (a Bergstrom-interdependent utility function): U i (x, F (.)) = u i (x) + α i F (.) where u i (x) is the private subutility of x satisfying the usual assumptions and α i is a constant. 7 Also let us also assume that social welfare is a weighted utilitarian function, such that: n n n F = β j U j (.) = β j u j (x) + F (.) β j α j j=1 j=1 j=1 The independent social welfare can be derived as: G(u 1 (x),..., u n (x)) = nj=1 β j u j (x) 1 n j=1 β j α j The independent utility function of individual i is given by: nj=1 β j u j (x) V i (x) = u i (x) + α i 1 n j=1 β j α j = 1 n j i β j α nj i j β j u j (x) 1 n u i (x) + α i j=1 β j α j 1 n j=1 β j α j There are three possible solutions to be considered: 7 Preferences can be positively interdependent or negatively interdependent, see Ok and Kockesen (2000). We do not impose any restriction on the sign of α. 6 http://law.bepress.com/gmulwps/art10

(1) n j=1 β j α j < 1: there is a unique solution to the problem of finding an independent weighted utilitarian social welfare function. This corresponds to the usual assumption taken in the altruism literature (Becker, 1974; Bernheim and Stark, 1988; Bergstrom, 1999; Bowles and Garoupa, 2002). (2) n j=1 β j α j > 1: the solution we have derived is unstable. According to Bramoullé (2001), the reasonable economic interpretation of instability should be that there is an infinite solution set to the problem of finding an independent weighted utilitarian social welfare function; a related interpretation is discussed by Postlewaite (1998). Nevertheless it is not the case that all solutions yield the same level of social welfare. Clearly other social criteria are required to help a welfarist analysis in this situation since policymaking requires the implementation of a given chosen policy. 8 (3) n j=1 β j α j = 1: there is no solution to the problem of finding an independent weighted utilitarian social welfare function. A welfarist analysis in this situation is useless, and yet policymaking requires that some policy is chosen and implemented. 3 Conclusions We have provided a framework where a consistent welfarist method of policy assessment (that is, a method based on an individualistic social welfare function) is incomplete. The reason for incompleteness is the existence of recursive interdependent preferences. Aggregated individual preferences determine social preferences which, in turn and in many important contexts, determine individual preferences. We have argued that, although under certain conditions we can use welfare economics to evaluate policies even if preferences are interdependent, in general the set of welfarist solutions is not a singleton, because a solution does not exist or because there might be more than one solution, thus requiring other decision-making criteria to make a 8 Notice also that the usual literature (Becker, 1974; Bernheim and Stark, 1988) discards this possibility because the independent utility function is decreasing in consumption. 7 Hosted by The Berkeley Electronic Press

policy recommendation. 9 Incompleteness is a relevant problem because the alternative policies to be assessed generally yield different levels of individual and social welfare. On the policy level, this situation may arise while trying to address two fundamental problems for social coexistence. One issue is the aggregation of individual preferences, 10 that is, what weight should be given to each individual in society. This problem may arise in relation to the evaluation of policies concerning issues of equality, liberty, distribution of resources and similar problems, which are likely to be of central importance for policymaking. In this case, the weight to give to individual preferences is decided according to the individual preferences themselves. The attempt to do so may thus result in a circular reasoning yielding no ultimate conclusion. While it is evident that different social welfare functions yield to the endorsement of different policies and hence to different levels of individual and social welfare, such levels may not be comparable for the criterion of assessment (the social welfare function) is also the object of such an assessment. A second order of issues concerns the way in which policies do or should influence individual preferences. 11 Education of youth is a complex endeavor in modern multicultural societies and its most discussed aspects relate precisely to the type of preferences youth should develop. Re-education of criminals or otherwise outcast individuals poses similar problems. Also in this case, the desirable set of preferences that a society should exhibit is to be decided according to individuals actual and future preferences, thus yielding the same type of circularity that we discussed above. It is evident that the assessment of such policies is an inevitable necessity, as society cannot generally afford to let such fundamental questions unanswered. Consequently, such problems, in many circumstances, will have to be resolved by resorting to precisely those criteria that give independent weight to some value other than individual welfare, because, as we have suggested, individual preferences, even if broadly defined, are recursive. As a 9 Kaplow and Shavell (2002, p. 413-418) suggest instead that, also when preferences depend on policies, a welfarist solution can be found. We argue that, to the contrary, this might not always be possible. 10 The choice of G(x) in the formal model. 11 The choice of V i (x) in the formal model. 8 http://law.bepress.com/gmulwps/art10

result, the implementation of an inconsistent method of policy assessment may be the necessary price to pay for completeness. References [1] Becker, Gary (1974), A Theory of Social Interactions, 82 Journal of Political Economy, 1063 1093. [2] Bergstrom, Theodore C. (1999), Systems of Benevolent Utility Functions, 1 Journal of Public Economic Theory, 71 100. [3] Bernheim, D. and Stark, O. (1988), Altruism Within the Family Reconsidered: Do Nice Guys Finished Last?, 78 American Economic Review, 1034 1045. [4] Bowles, Roger and Garoupa, Nuno (2002), Household Dissolution, Child Care and Divorce Law, 22 International Review of Law and Economics, 495 510. [5] Bramoullé, Yann (2001), Interdependent Utilities, Preference Indeterminacy, and Social Networks, University of Maryland unpublished manuscript. [6] Chang, Howard F. (2000a), A Liberal Theory of Social Welfare: Fairness, Utility, and the Pareto Principle, 110 Yale Law Journal, 173 235. [7] Chang, Howard F. (2000b), The Possibility of a Fair Paretian, 110 Yale Law Journal, 251 258. [8] Dari-Mattiacci, Giuseppe (2004), Goedel, Kaplow, Shavell: Consistency and Completeness in Social Decisionmaking, 79 Chicago Kent Law Review, 497 520. [9] Dorff, Michael B. (2002), Why Welfare Depends on Fairness: A Reply to Kaplow and Shavell, 75 Southern California Law Review, 847 899. [10] Farnsworth, Ward (2002), A Taste for Fairness, 102 Columbia Law Review, 1992 2026. 9 Hosted by The Berkeley Electronic Press

[11] Ferzan, Kimberly Kessler (2004), Some Sound and Fury from Kaplow and Shavell, 23 Law and Philosopy, 73 102. [12] Fleurbaey, Marc, Tungodden, Bertil, and Chang, Howard F. (2003), Any Non-welfarist Method of Policy Assessment Violates the Pareto Principle: A Comment, 111 Journal of Political Economy, 1382 1385. [13] Kaplow, Louis and Shavell, Steven (2000), Notions of Fairness versus the Pareto Principle: On the Role of Logical Consistency, 110 Yale Law Journal, 237 249. [14] Kaplow, Louis and Shavell, Steven (2001), Any Non-welfarist Method of Policy Assessment Violates the Pareto Principle, 109 Journal of Political Economy, 281 286. [15] Kaplow, Louis and Shavell, Steven (2002), Fairness versus Welfare, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA. [16] Kaplow, Louis and Shavell, Steven (2003), Fairness versus Welfare: Notes on the Pareto Principle, Preferences, and Distributive Justice, 32 Journal of Legal Studies, 331 362. [17] Kaplow, Louis and Shavell, Steven (2004a), Any Non-welfarist Method of Policy Assessment Violates the Pareto Principle: A Reply, Harvard Law School, The Center for Law, Economics, and Business Discussion Paper No. 455. [18] Kaplow, Louis and Shavell, Steven (2004b), Notes on Welfarist versus Deontological Principles, Economics and Philosophy, forthcoming. [19] Kornhauser, Lewis A. (2003), Preferences, Well-Being, and Morality in Social Decisions, 32 Journal of Legal Studies, 303 329. [20] McDonnel, Brett (2003), Economists New Argument, Public Law and Legal Theory Research Paper Series 03-3, University of Minnesota Law School. [21] Ok, Efe A. and Kockesen, Levent (2000), Negatively Interdependent Preferences, 17 Social Choice and Welfare, 533 558. 10 http://law.bepress.com/gmulwps/art10

[22] Pollak, Robert A. (1976), Interdependent Preferences, 66 American Economic Review, 309 320. [23] Postlewaite, Andrew (1998), The Social Basis of Interdependent Preferences, 42 European Economic Review, 779 800. [24] Ripstein, Arthur (2004), Too Much Invested to Quit, Economics and Philosophy, forthcoming. [25] Sen, Amartya (1970), The Impossibility of a Paretian Liberal, 78 Journal of Political Economy, 152 157. [26] Waldron, Jeremy (2003), Locating Distribution, 32 Journal of Legal Studies, 277 302. 11 Hosted by The Berkeley Electronic Press