Conor Foley, The Thin Blue Line: How Humanitarianism Went to War (London: Verso, 2008). 266 pages. Hardback (ISBN-13: ),

Similar documents
Veronika Bílková: Responsibility to Protect: New hope or old hypocrisy?, Charles University in Prague, Faculty of Law, Prague, 2010, 178 p.

Global Ethics: An Introduction Written by Kimberly Hutchings Cambridge: Polity, 2010 (ISBN: ) 244pp.

The Moral Myth and the. Abuse of Humanitarian Intervention

HUMANITARIAN PRINCIPLES: ENGAGING WITH NON-STATE ACTORS

CONTEXTUALISM AND GLOBAL JUSTICE

The Concept of Normative Power in World Politics

What Does It Mean to Understand Human Rights as Essentially Triggers for Intervention?

A Necessary Discussion About International Law

LJMU Research Online

Darfur: Assessing the Assessments

Mainstreaming Human Security? Concepts and Implications for Development Assistance. Opening Presentation for the Panel Discussion 1

Catholic-inspired NGOs FORUM Forum des ONG d inspiration catholique

The responsibility to protect doctrine Coherent after all: A reply to Friberg-Fernros and Brommesson

The evolution of human rights

Humanitarian Space: Concept, Definitions and Uses Meeting Summary Humanitarian Policy Group, Overseas Development Institute 20 th October 2010

Ensuring Accountability in Post-2015: Potential Threats to Education Rights

The Kelvingrove Review Issue 2

How to approach legitimacy

Democracy, Sovereignty and Security in Europe

What Happened To Human Security?

Examiners Report January GCE Government & Politics 6GP03 3B

On Human Rights by James Griffin, Oxford University Press, 2008, 339 pp.

Book Reviews. Julian Culp, Global Justice and Development, Palgrave Macmillan, Basingstoke, UK, 2014, Pp. xi+215, ISBN:

Norm dynamics and ambiguity in South African foreign policy: The case of the no-fly zone over Libya

Part 1. Understanding Human Rights

NETWORK WAR JOURNALISM: ANALYSIS OF MEDIA COVERAGE OF THE 2011 CRISIS IN SOMALIA

Globalization and food sovereignty: Global and local change in the new politics of food

Bringing human rights home: refugees, reparation, and the responsibility to protect

Status and the Challenge of Rising Powers by Steven Ward

Legitimacy in the use of force: Opinio or Juris?

The Rhetoric of Populism: How to Give Voice to the People?

No real development without human rights

TURKEY Check Against Delivery. Statement by H.E. Sebahattin ÖZTÜRK Minister of Interior / Republic of Turkey

Mark Scheme (Results) January GCE Government & Politics 6GP03 3D GLOBAL POLITICS

HUMAN RIGHTS AND THE NEW WORLD ORDER

CHRISTOFOROS IOANNIDIS

Chapter 2: Core Values and Support for Anti-Terrorism Measures.

Engage Education Foundation

worthwhile to pose several basic questions regarding this notion. Should the Insular Cases be simply discarded? Can they be simply

Mark Scheme (Results) January GCE Government & Politics 6GP03 3B POLITICAL IDEOLOGIES

The Legitimacy of Humanitarian Intervention in International Society of The 21 st Century

The G20 as a Summit Process: Including New Agenda Issues such as Human Security. Paul James

Normative and Descriptive Views of the Policy Process

Mr. President, Mr. Secretary-General, Your Excellencies, Ladies and Gentlemen,

1100 Ethics July 2016

INCAF response to Pathways for Peace: Inclusive approaches to preventing violent conflict

R2P or Not R2P? More Statebuilding, Less Responsibility

The use of cyber force: Is the jus ad bellum ready? Christian Henderson *

A Brief Review of the Iranian Islamic Human Rights Commission's Activities Regarding International Criminal Justice

UNHCR PRESENTATION. The Challenges of Mixed Migration Flows: An Overview of Protracted Situations within the Context of the Bali Process

Republicanism: Midway to Achieve Global Justice?

Mehrdad Payandeh, Internationales Gemeinschaftsrecht Summary

Hugo Slim is currently a Chief Scholar at the Centre for Humanitarian

Summary of expert meeting: "Mediation and engaging with proscribed armed groups" 29 March 2012

Part I Introduction. [11:00 7/12/ pierce-ch01.tex] Job No: 5052 Pierce: Research Methods in Politics Page: 1 1 8

Mr. President, Mr. President,

on 2 June 2008 "Change and dynamism in the humanitarian world challenges to the independence of humanitarian aid"

The Legal Status of Humanitarian Intervention

The Justification of Justice as Fairness: A Two Stage Process

Analysis of the Draft Defence Strategy of the Slovak Republic 2017

European Parliament recommendation to the Council of 18 April 2013 on the UN principle of the Responsibility to Protect ( R2P ) (2012/2143(INI))

Chapter VI Identification of customary international law

Success of the NATO Warsaw Summit but what will follow?

Examiners report 2009

University of Waterloo Department of Political Science Winter 2009 PSCI 658 HUMAN RIGHTS IN THE GLOBALIZED WORLD

Two Pictures of the Global-justice Debate: A Reply to Tan*

CONSERVATISM: A DEFENCE FOR THE PRIVILEGED AND PROSPEROUS?

Marco Scalvini Book review: the European public sphere and the media: Europe in crisis

Peace and conflict in Africa

Global Justice. Wednesdays (314) :00 4:00 pm Office Hours: Seigle 282 Tuesdays, 9:30 11:30 am

Federalism, Decentralisation and Conflict. Management in Multicultural Societies

Exploring Civilian Protection: A Seminar Series

Pearson Edexcel GCE in Government & Politics (6GP04/4B) Paper 4B: Ideological Traditions

Examiners Report June GCE Government and Politics 6GP03 3D

Christian Aid Ireland's Submission to the Review of Ireland s Foreign Policy and External Relations

Eternity Clauses: a Safeguard of Democratic Order and Constitutional Identity

Constitutionalism of Climate Justice: Towards an International Legal Framework to Respond to Climate Related Migration and Displacement

Universal Human Rights in Theory and Practice

Srictly embargoed until 24 April h00 CET

ANDREAS ZIMMERMANN & RAINER HOFMANN, ED., UNITY AND DIVERSITY IN INTERNATIONAL LAW (BERLIN: DUNCKER & HUMBLOT, 2006) By Mario Prost

Examiners Report June 2010

HOSTILITIES UNDER INTERNATIONAL LAW

DEVELOPING OR PREVENTATIVE ECONOMIC GLOBALIZATION FOR THE ECONOMY OF THE REGION WITH SPECIAL EMPHASIS ON THE ECONOMY OF KOSOVO

STATEMENT AT THE UNITED NATIONS GENERAL ASSEMBLY DEBATE ON THE RESPONSIBILITY TO PROTECT

Exam Questions By Year IR 214. How important was soft power in ending the Cold War?

Statement EU civil-military cooperation: A comprehensive approach. By Dr. Bas Rietjens (Netherlands Defence Academy)

Programme Specification

Examiners Report June GCE Government and Politics 6GP03 3D

DÓCHAS STRATEGY

PEACEBUILDING PROGRAM Program Memo Ariadne Papagapitos, Program Officer March 2011

Book Review by Marcelo Vieta

The Thorny Issues Surrounding International Intervention

HELEN CLARK. A Better, Fairer, Safer World. New Zealand s Candidate for United Nations Secretary-General

The Embassy of Iraq avails itself of this opportunity to renew to the Department of States the assurances of its highest considerations.

To Say What the Law Is: Judicial Authority in a Political Context Keith E. Whittington PROSPECTUS THE ARGUMENT: The volume explores the political

Your address: University Registry, King Edward VII Avenue, Cathays Park, Cardiff CF10 3NS

Commission on the Status of Women Forty-eighth session New York, 1-12 March 2004 PANEL I

PANEL II: GLOBAL ATTITUDES ON THE ROLE OF THE

Statement by Ms. Patricia O Brien Under-Secretary-General for Legal Affairs, The Legal Counsel

RESEARCH ON HUMANITARIAN POLICY (HUMPOL)

Transcription:

Conor Foley, The Thin Blue Line: How Humanitarianism Went to War (London: Verso, 2008). 266 pages. Hardback (ISBN-13:9781844672899), 14.99. Review by Akihiro Ueda The front cover to The Thin Blue Line: How Humanitarianism Went to War 1 introduces the book in the following manner: Conor Foley explores how the doctrine of humanitarian intervention has been used to allow states to invade other nations in the name of human rights. In the same vein, Amy Goodman began with the following question in an interview with Conor Foley on Democracy Now!, a daily TV/radio news programme: How is it used? How is humanitarianism and humanitarian intervention used? 2 If readers get the impression that this book provides a critique of humanitarian intervention in the name of human rights, which the above description of the book may appear to imply, then they will have been misled. The book is not simply about justifying or not justifying military intervention. 3 On the contrary, it insists that making such a choice on the matter is difficult. Underpinned with his own experience as a humanitarian worker, Foley s discussion explores the strait between anti-imperialism and liberal interventionism. After all, this book is about the thin blue line : the struggle, frustration, dilemma, or contradiction in choosing a side on the rectitude of military humanitarian intervention. The debates between anti-imperialists and liberal interventionists highlight one of the key issues of humanitarian intervention: 4 what is the nature of intervention in the name of human rights? As manifested in the dialogue of the UN General Assembly on the Responsibility to Protect of 23 July 2009, this issue is far from settled. 5 On the one hand, anti-imperialists hold the view that the invasion of Iraq in 2003 was, as Foley puts it, the culmination of a period of misguided western intervention that has seen the weakening of both national sovereignty and international law. 6 On the other hand, liberal interventionists maintain the view that Iraq was primarily a contest between good and evil. 7 The former insist that the invasion of Iraq was unjust, while the latter believe it was praiseworthy. This tension between anti-imperialists and liberal interventionists is 1 C. Foley, The Thin Blue Line: How Humanitarianism Went to War (London: Verso, 2008). 2 Democracy Now! Available at: http://www.democracynow.org/2009/2/13/conor_foley_the_thin_blue_line. 3 For further discussion of the humanitarian intervention, see: A. Hehir, Humanitarian Intervention After Kosovo: Iraq, Darfur and the Record of Global Civil Society (Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2008); F. R. Tesón, Humanitarian Intervention: An Inquiry into Law and Morality, 2nd ed. (Irvington-On-Hudson: Transnational, 1997); J. L. Holzgrefe and R. O. Keohane (ed.), Humanitarian Intervention: Ethical, Legal and Political Dilemmas (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003); S. Chesterman, Just War or Just Peace?: Humanitarian Intervention and International Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001); G. Robertson, Crimes Against Humanity: The Struggle for Global Justice, Revised and updated ed. (London: Penguin, 2006). 4 Notably, see: A. Orford, Reading Humanitarian Intervention: Human Rights and the Use of Force in International Law, First Edition (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007). 5 At the Opening of the Thematic Dialogue of the General Assembly on the Responsibility to Protect, New York, 23 July 2009. Available at http://www.un.org/ga/president/63/statements/openingr2p230709.shtml. 6 Foley, see fn.1 above, p.2. 7 Foley, p.2.

not simply a reflection of different views on Iraq, but rather represents two opposing views on humanitarian intervention in general. In the real world of international relations, liberal interventionists are gradually prevailing over anti-imperialists. The main focus of Foley s analysis is a reflection of this tendency as manifested in his area of expertise: human rights and humanitarian organisations. According to Foley, human rights organisations seek to promote universal observance of and respect for human rights. 8 Human rights activists are interventionists in support of these objectives. 9 Contrary to this, humanitarian organisations have traditionally relied on neutrality 10 to gain access to places where humanitarian catastrophes take place. Since the 1990s however, as Foley observes, these two movements have come closer together. They are now described under the single label political humanitarianism. In other words, humanitarian organisations are gradually abandoning their neutrality, and pursuing certain political objectives. Both human rights and humanitarian activists are now interventionists. Foley s main focus of attention is, in his own words, the consequences [this shift] has had both for the human rights movement and for traditional humanitarianism. 11 The scope of his scrutiny covers not just instances of interventions in Iraq but also in Somalia (Chapter 2), Kosovo (Chapter 3), Afghanistan (Chapter 4), and Sri Lanka and Indonesia (Chapter 5). In Chapter 3, which deals with Kosovo, Foley provides a clear account, with a good quantity of evidence, of how human rights organizations such as Human Rights Watch have gradually become supporters of NATO s air strikes against Serbian forces. 12 In the case of Afghanistan, he provides a vivid example of the situation based on his own experience. For example, he writes that the main problem facing our legal aid centres [which he worked for] was that there were practically no legal mechanisms with which to work. 13 Lawyers, therefore, relied primarily on convening Shuras and Jigas (traditional meetings of elders) to mediate settlements. 14 Moreover, he also discusses three developing themes on intervention: the Responsibility to Protect (Chapter 6), the International Criminal Court (Chapter 7), and humanitarian accountability (Chapter 8). On the theme of Responsibility to Protect, Foley supposes that it can be considered a small advance for the interventionist cause, although the UN s reaction shows that the issue is far from settled. 15 On the International Criminal Court, Foley describes the atmosphere among Human Rights workers as follows: Everyone I spoke to expressed the same view, that the ICC s intervention was ill-thought-out and counter-productive. 16 On humanitarian accountability, he points out important issues while being generally supportive of the idea. He holds that the basic problem with the concept of humanitarian accountability is that it fails to address the huge difference in power between the different parties. 17 So what is Foley s position? Is he anti-imperialist or liberal interventionist? He is neither. Foley 8 Foley, p.3. 9 Foley, p.3. 10 Foley, p.4. 11 Foley, p.4. 12 Foley, pp.74-5. 13 Foley, p.105. 14 Foley, p.105. 15 Foley, p.158. 16 Foley, p.172. 17 Foley, p.204. 127

explicitly states that both views are wrong. 18 This is why it is misleading to describe his book as simply providing a critique on the doctrine of humanitarian intervention. Without doubt, Foley severely criticises liberal interventionists. For instance, he argues that humanitarian agencies failed to build links with Somali civil society by calling for military intervention. 19 In strong terms, Foley asserts that The problem with trying to adhere to universal standards or a legally-defined rights-based approach is that, abstracted from particular contexts, they are often at best meaningless and at worst could prevent agencies from achieving any good. 20 While criticising liberal interventionists, he does not give unconditional support to antiimperialists either. Foley rightly observes that there is a reason, indeed a good reason, for the rise of political humanitarianism. There was wide recognition that the traditional Red Cross approach to humanitarian crises had limitations. Foley criticises, for instance, Herman and Ghannoushi s arguments as circular: it seems to condemn the international community for both action and inaction. 21 Action is required, according to Foley. Underlying this position is the notion of a responsibility to act. Foley strongly believes that we must do something, while rejecting liberal interventionism. For him, the notion of a responsibility to act motivates those who care about human rights in far-off places and it was what had taken [him] from Kosovo to Kabul. the idea that we should do something to help alleviate human suffering underpins our basic concept of global solidarity. 22 What is the solution then? Unfortunately, Foley s own perspective on humanitarian intervention is not fully developed in this book. Nevertheless, he does provide some direction to what he believes is a better viewpoint. Foley argues that both anti-imperialists and liberal interventionists are wrong. What is required is a much more pragmatic and realistic approach. 23 A useful starting point, according to Foley, would be to acknowledge that the conception of human rights western liberals have created, refined and prepackaged for export, is not the only one in existence. 24 His alternative is to build a broader dialogue. By broader dialogue, Foley means to include many different and important actors in the forum. Foley provides an example of the World Social Forum, which has now become an important arena for south-south debate. 25 In so doing, he argues, respect for human dignity, personal freedom and individual autonomy can be located in discussions of how to address the injustices caused by the imbalances of wealth and power in the world today. 26 Foley s book naturally raises many questions and doubts. What is the foundation of his approach? Is it fair to make such a simple distinction between liberal interventionists and antiimperialists? How is his argument different to that given in Responsibility to Protect, Report of the International Commission on Intervention and State Sovereignty? 27 It is worth highlighting 18 Foley, p.232. 19 Foley, p.36. 20 Foley, p.209. 21 Foley, p.223. 22 Foley, p.3. 23 Foley, p.232. 24 Foley, p.235. 25 Foley, p.235. 26 Foley, p.235. 27 International Commission on Intervention and State Sovereignty, The Responsibility to Protect (Ottawa: 128

two questions: the first relates to methodology, while the second concerns his pragmatic and realistic approach to the issue. While Foley points out that the issue of humanitarianism has been subject to very little academic scrutiny and remains surrounded by many myths and misconceptions, 28 he openly admits that this book is written from the perspective of a subjective partisan within the debates that have shaped my views and opinions. 29 Can academic scrutiny and what he calls a subjective partisan perspective be reconciled? To begin with, what he considers academic scrutiny or theory is not clearly defined. Nor is subjective partisan perspective. Nevertheless, it seems reasonable to reconstruct his methodology in the following manner. Foley seems to believe that theory is represented in the form of international human rights and humanitarian law. 30 The subjective partisan perspective (or practice ) seems to signify his own pragmatic and realistic approach to the issues of humanitarian crises in the field in opposition to two rival schools of thought anti-imperialists and liberal interventionists. Theory and practice are interrelated because theory cannot provide actual meaning on its own. In Foley s terms, there is still considerable disagreement about what international law actually means on certain subjects. 31 This is where practice comes in. Both anti-imperialists and liberal interventionists struggle to project their aspirations to international law. So does Foley. In other words, it seems possible (and even interesting) to read this book as Foley s attempt to shift the perception of international human rights and humanitarian law to a more realistic and sensible one. This is undoubtedly a very ambitious enterprise. Foley s strategy for this ambitious aim is strikingly unique. While most attempts to reconstruct international law in one s own favour work inside of the legal discourse, Foley s approach stays aloof from such discourse to some extent. Former ICJ Judge Rosalyn Higgins work would provide a good example of working inside of the discourse. She believes that international law is not a system of neutral rules but a tool for the attainment of certain declared values, such as human rights. Based on this belief, she argues that, on the issue of humanitarian intervention, deciding whether a claim invoking any given norm is made in good faith or abusively will always require contextual analysis. 32 In other words, Higgins attempts to justify humanitarian intervention under certain conditions in law by replacing a static approach with a dynamic or contextual approach to law. This argument is a legal argument more than anything else. Foley s greatest strength is his own experience in the field rather than what he would call dry legal theory. 33 As readers may see, Foley s personal experiences (sometimes supplemented by those of his colleagues) always follow a general explanation of law and facts in each chapter. Such personal experience should provide readers with material to understand the impact and International Development Research Centre, 2001). On the Responsibility to Protect, see: A. J. Bellamy, Responsibility to Protect (Cambridge: Polity Press, 2008); G. J Evans, The Responsibility to Protect: Ending Mass Atrocity Crimes Once and for All (Washington, D.C: Brookings Institution Press, 2008); T. G. Weiss, Humanitarian Intervention: Ideas in Action (Cambridge: Polity Press, 2007). 28 Foley, p.20 (italics added). 29 Foley, p.20 (italics added). 30 Foley, p.15. 31 Foley, p.15. 32 R. Higgins, Problems and Process: International Law and How We Use It (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1994) p.245. 33 Foley, p.15. 129

consequences of international human rights and humanitarian law construed and used by liberal interventionists in humanitarian fields. Moreover, it should persuade readers to take up or join a more pragmatic and realistic approach. Might one conclude that theory and practice or academic scrutiny and a subjective partisan perspective in Foley s terminology have finally met and been reconciled? I have some doubts. Firstly, while Foley focuses on the impact and consequences of political humanitarianism, these do not necessarily lead to new interpretations of the law. Impacts and consequences are only one factor amongst many for assessing the concept of human rights law. According to Article 31 of the Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties, for instance, a treaty shall be interpreted in good faith in accordance with the ordinary meaning to be given to the terms of the treaty in their context and in the light of its object and purpose. 34 Legal positivists would always say that alas, Foley s argument expresses legal policy, lex ferenda, rather than what is law, lex lata. Secondly, a particular point of view is always assumed as underlying any assessment of the consequences of the conduct. In fact, this is the very source of the dispute between liberal interventionists and anti-imperialists. Intervention, for the former, is a necessary evil for the sake of promoting human rights, while the latter see it as the erosion of the state sovereignty the last shield from imperialism. Foley s position on this issue is not entirely clear. Finally, his reference to human rights and humanitarian law is so brief and basic that it lacks actual interpretation of particular rules or principles from his pragmatic and realistic approach. This makes it extremely difficult for the reader to understand the link between the theoretical and personal experience sections in each chapter. The second point of concern with Foley s book is his pragmatic and realistic approach to the issue. Foley s approach must be elucidated. Again, the terms pragmatic and realistic are not clearly defined in the book. Nevertheless, Foley s point is relatively clear. He warns western liberals that they must think more seriously about the supposed universal values they hope their interventions will promote. 35 Foley insists that a broader dialogue with local communities and people is needed. 36 In other words, Foley criticises what Jack Donnelly would call radical universalism which holds that culture is irrelevant to the universal validity of moral rights and rules. 37 Foley would rather maintain, in Donnelly s terms, weak cultural relativism which considers culture a secondary source of the validity of a right or rule. 38 To put it differently, a universal concept of human rights should be interpreted or applied differently across differing cultural contexts. This, for Foley, seems to be pragmatic and realistic. While this position is more or less the dominant position in human rights discourse, Foley s contribution is that he illustrates actual dialogues manifested in events such as the World Social Forum 39 and the campaign for the International Criminal Court. 40 His approach is based on the observation that it is difficult to draw a single thread through what went right and wrong during the various humanitarian 34 Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties, adopted 23 May 1969, entered into force 27 January 1980, United Nations, Treaty Series, vol.1155, p.331. 35 Foley, p.234. 36 Foley, p.235. 37 J. Donnelly, Universal Human Rights in Theory and Practice, 2nd ed. (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 2003) p.89. This may not capture Foley s position accurately as his position is not concerned directly with the validity of norms. Nevertheless, Donnelly s typology seems useful for analogical purposes. Therefore, for the purpose of this review, I shall use Donnelly s typology regardless. 38 Foley, p.235. 39 Foley, p.235. 40 Foley, ch.7. 130

interventions of the last couple of decades. 41 This perspective may, first, lead to the conclusion that international human rights and humanitarian law are in fact useless in practice, and second, undermine coherency in the application of human rights. Weak cultural relativism is a promising approach in human rights discourse. Nevertheless, it raises a crucial question. Where is the limit? How does a universal concept of human rights constrain interpretation or dialogue in its application? Foley seems to believe that international human rights and humanitarian law provide an objective framework. 42 However, he does not provide enough of an illustration of how this framework actually constrains practice or movements. There is always a risk, accordingly, of construing international human rights and humanitarian law beyond their framework. More importantly, Foley s approach may effectively undermine the coherence of human rights and humanitarian norms. In other words, there is a danger of falling into the trap of the doublestandard. This has always been a criticism against the claim of the right to humanitarian intervention. For example, intervention did not take place in Darfur even when the scale of the crisis in Darfur exceeded that of Kosovo in 1999. 43 According to the report submitted by the UN Secretary General, the death toll in Darfur is over two million, and four million have lost their homes. 44 Rwanda in 1994 and Iraq in 2003 may be regarded as other good examples. Foley would argue that having a double-standard and putting the right treatment in the right place are completely different. Indeed, they are different. However, without a clear theoretical framework and code of conduct, it seems difficult to distinguish the two. We might have to wait to see such progress in his next book. Despite the above criticisms, this book makes an excellent contribution to the field of study and will benefit both academics and students. Foley s attempt to provide a bridge between theory and practice is a challenging task which academics may want to join. Moreover, because of Foley s attempt to avoid using jargon, those members of the general public who share Foley s aspiration of responsibility to act will also benefit enormously. Accordingly, this timely book is another welcome addition to the discussion. 41 Foley, pp.232-3. 42 Foley, p.15. 43 Human Rights Council, Report of the High-Level Mission on the Situation of Human Rights in Darfur Pursuant to Human Rights Council Decision S-4/101, 9 March 2007, p.22, available at http://www.unhcr.org/refworld/country,,unhrc,,sdn,456d621e2,46237e782,0.html. 44 Report of the Secretary-General on the Sudan, UN Doc.S/2004/453. 131