Kimberley N. Trapp* 1 The Inter-state Reading of Article The Use of Force against Terrorists: A Reply to Christian J. Tams

Similar documents
SHORTER ARTICLES, COMMENTS, AND NOTES

VI. READING ASSIGNMENTS International Law (Laws ) Fall 2008

CASE CONCERNING MILITARY AND PARAMILITARY ACTIVITIES IN AND AGAINST NICARAGUA. (Nicaragua v. United States of America) ICJ Decision of 27 June 1986

TOPIC EIGHT: USE OF FORCE. The use of force is of particular concern to the international community.

Book Review: War Law Understanding International Law and Armed Conflict, by Michael Byers

DECLARATION OF JUDGE SKOTNIKOV

Dapo Akande* and Sangeeta Shah**

The Use of Force by Non- State Actors and the Limits of Attribution of Conduct: A Rejoinder to Ilias Plakokefalos

The human rights implications of targeted killings. Christof Heyns, UN Special Rapporteur on extrajudicial, summary or arbitrary executions

THE JUS AD BELLUM AND ENTITIES SHORT OF STATEHOOD IN THE REPORT ON THE CONFLICT IN GEORGIA

WAR ON TERROR. Shristhi Debuka 1

International Court of Justice

Briefing on Sixth Committee of the United Nations General Assembly 1. History of the Sixth Committee

COLLECTIVE SECURITY AND THE USE OF FORCE

Natalia Ochoa-Ruiz and Esther Salamanca-Aguado

State responsibility and State liability in international law. Sigmar Stadlmeier

International Law, Human Rights and Corporations: Emerging Issues. Paper for the IBA Conference October 2007

STATE RESPONSIBILITY MR. SANTIAGO VILLALPANDO. Santiago, Chile 24 April 19 May 2017

The Kosovo Opinion and General International Law: How Far-reaching and Controversial is the ICJ s Reasoning?

Conditions for the lawful exercise of the right of self-defence in international law

JCE IN INTERNATIONAL LAW. Dubrovnik, Professor Maja Seršić

Humanity as the A and Ω of Sovereignty: A Rejoinder to Emily Kidd White, Catherine E. Sweetser, Emma Dunlop and Amrita Kapur

Human Rights and the Fight against Terrorism: Martin Scheinin Åbo Akademi University UN Special Rapporteur on

The use of cyber force: Is the jus ad bellum ready? Christian Henderson *

Access from the University of Nottingham repository:

INTERNATIONAL HUMAN RIGHTS LAW

Session 1: TREATY LAW

Report of the Republic of El Salvador pursuant to United Nations General Assembly resolution 66/103

SEPARATE OPINION OF JUDGE SETTE-CAMARA

THE FIGHT AGAINST THE ISLAMIC STATE IN SYRIA: TOWARDS THE MODIFICATION OF THE RIGHT TO SELF-DEFENCE?

(JUS AD BELLUM ) YEMEN: INTERNATIONAL HUMANITARIAN LAW (IHL), INTERNATIONAL HUMAN RIGHTS LAW (IHRL) & THE USE OF FORCE BY A STATE

Principles for an Internationally Legally Binding Instrument on TNC and other Business Enterprises with respect to Human Rights

Precluding Wrongfulness or Responsibility: A Plea for Excuses

Self-Defence Against Terrorism - before and after 11 September

SETTLEMENT OF DISPUTES CLAUSES. [Agenda item 15] Note by the Secretariat

Command Responsibility. Joaquin G. Bernas, S.J. The death and disappearances of members of media and of people with the same

1. Summary. In the unanimously decided case of Al Nashiri v. Poland, the European Court of Human

SEPARATE OPINION OF JUDGE SIMMA

The Human Right to Peace

INTERNATIONAL LAW COMMISSION Sixty-eighth session Geneva, 2 May 10 June and 4 July 12 August 2016 Check against delivery

HAUT-COMMISSARIAT AUX DROITS DE L HOMME OFFICE OF THE HIGH COMMISSIONER FOR HUMAN RIGHTS PALAIS DES NATIONS 1211 GENEVA 10, SWITZERLAND

INTERNATIONAL COURT OF JUSTICE YEAR MAY 2011 CASE CONCERNING IRAQ: SOVEREIGNTY & JUS AD BELLUM

The death of Osama Bin Laden

Treatise on International Criminal Law

RESEARCH PAPER SERIES

Nuclear Weapons and International Law

2016 FDI MOOT Africa Regional Rounds SKELETAL BRIEF FOR CLAIMANT

A Matter of Interest: Diplomatic Protection and State Responsibility Erga Omnes

Threat or Use of Force at Sea

Internment in Armed Conflict: Basic Rules and Challenges. International Committee of the Red Cross (ICRC) Opinion Paper, November 2014

Translated from Spanish 7-1-SG/35

INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF RESEARCH AND ANALYSIS VOLUME 4 ISSUE 2 ISSN

Counter-terrorism strategies, human rights and international law: meeting the challenges

Statewatch briefing on the European Evidence Warrant to the European Parliament

29. Security Council action regarding the terrorist attacks in Buenos Aires and London

Resolution adopted by the General Assembly. [on the report of the Sixth Committee (A/56/589 and Corr.1)]

Aiding and Assisting: Challenges in Armed Conflict and Counterterrorism

The Internet in Bello: Cyber War Law, Ethics & Policy Seminar held 18 November 2011, Berkeley Law

The legal basis for the invasion of Afghanistan

Setting a time limit: The case for a protocol on prolonged occupation

Article 6. [Exercise of jurisdiction] [Preconditions to the exercise of jurisdiction]

International Law Journal symposium on State Ethics, 20 February 2012, Harvard Law School

No. 2010/25 22 July Accordance with international law of the unilateral declaration of independence in respect of Kosovo.

BEYOND THE LIMITS OF INTERNATIONAL LAW: TERRORISM AND THE CONDUCT OF STATE AND NON-STATE ACTORS. Bengi KADIOĞLU*

Security Council Counter-Terrorism-Committee, New York, 24 October 2005.

I. INTRODUCTION II. EVALUATING THE DIRECT CONNECTION REQUIREMENT IN RESPECT OF THE FIRST AND SECOND COUNTER-CLAIMS

Amicus Memorandum to the Chair of the United Nations Negotiating Conference for a Convention on the Prohibition of Nuclear Weapons

STATUTE OF THE INTERNATIONAL CRIMINAL TRIBUNAL

International Law and the Use of Armed Force by States

TO: Members of the Preparatory Committee on the Establishment of an International Criminal Court

Andrew Clapham* Abstract. ... The Role of the Individual in International Law

Enforcing Obligations Erga Omnes in International Law

STEERING COMMITTEE FOR HUMAN RIGHTS (CDDH) COMMITTEE OF EXPERTS ON THE SYSTEM OF THE EUROPEAN CONVENTION ON HUMAN RIGHTS (DH-SYSC)

Arbitrary Detention and International Law. The Torkel Opsahl Memorial Lecture 2015 by Mads Andenæs

State of Necessity: Effect on Compensation. Sergey Ripinsky 1 15 October 2007

The international law framework regulating the use of armed drones

Fiji Comments on the Discussion Paper on implementation of the Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court

IMMUNITY FOR INTERNATIONAL CRIMES. Jo Stigen Oslo, 9 March 2015

The Protection of the Civilian Population and NATO Bombing on Yugoslavia: Comments on a Report to the Prosecutor of the ICTY

Examiners report 2010

JEAN-CHRISTOPHE MARTIN, LES RÈGLES INTERNATIONALES RELATIVES À LA LUTTE CONTRE LE TERRORISME, (BRUXELLES: BRUYLANT, 2006) Par Kimberley N.

Attacks on Medical Units in International Humanitarian and Human Rights Law

The 2010 United States National Security Strategy and the Obama Doctrine of Necessary Force

A Necessary Discussion About International Law

A/CN.4/498/Add.2. General Assembly. United Nations. Second report on State responsibility. Contents

Q & A: What is Additional Protocol I to the Geneva Conventions and Should the US Ratify It?

GUIDELINES ON INTERNATIONAL PROTECTION: Application of the Exclusion Clauses: Article 1F of the 1951 Convention relating to the Status of Refugees

Middlesex University Research Repository

ІNTERNATІΟNAL TRANЅFER ΟF ЅALW: LІMІTATІΟNЅ AND PRΟBLEMЅ

ILC The Environment in Armed Conflicts Draft Principles by Stavros-Evdokimos Pantazopoulos*

Roger S. Clark* Abstract

G. State Responsibility

Having regard to the Treaty on the Functioning of the European Union, and in particular Article 16 thereof,

COURSE CONTENTS: INTERNATIONAL HUMAN RIGHTS SECOND SEMESTER OF 2014

ANNEX I: APPLICABLE INTERNATIONAL LEGAL FRAMEWORK

The Inherent Right to Self- Defence and Proportionality in Jus Ad Bellum

3. For these reasons, I wish to append to the Judgment my own separate opinion, which is confined to these two issues.

THE INTERNATIONAL CRIMES (TRIBUNALS) ACT, 1973

Democracy, and the Evolution of International. to Eyal Benvenisti and George Downs. Tom Ginsburg* ... National Courts, Domestic

Exploring Civilian Protection: A Seminar Series

Transcription:

The European Journal of International Law Vol. 20 no. 4 EJIL 2010; all rights reserved... The Use of Force against Terrorists: A Reply to Christian J. Tams Kimberley N. Trapp* In his recent article The Use of Force Against Terrorists, 1 Professor Tams provides a thoughtful overview of developments in the jus ad bellum over the past 20 years. His analysis focuses on the right to use force in self-defence, particularly as regards the permissibility of extra-territorial military responses to terrorist attacks by non-state actors. The thrust of Professor Tams argument is that the relevant state practice suggests an evolution in the law of self-defence moving away from a restrictive analysis of Article 51 to a broader interpretation which more easily accommodates anti-terrorist force. In this comment, I will focus on Professor Tams approach to questions of attribution and the inter-state reading of Article 51, in particular his more moderate (but still important) re-reading 2 of the standard of attribution applicable in the terrorism context. Tams, The Use of Force against Terrorists, 20 EJIL (2009) 359, http://ejil.oxfordjournals.org/ cgi/reprint/20/2/359. * Lecturer in Law, Newnham College, University of Cambridge. Email: knt22@cam.ac.uk. 1 Tams, The Use of Force Against Terrorists, 20 EJIL (2009) 359. 2 Ibid., at 385. EJIL (2009), Vol. 20 No. 4, 1049 1055 1 The Inter-state Reading of Article 51 The starting point of Professor Tams discussion is that Article 51 must be understood in an inter-state context as an exception to the comprehensive ban on the inter-state use of force 3 set out in Article 2(4). Professor Tams notes the efforts of some commentators to divorce Article 51 from an inter-state context by positing a right to use defensive force in response to attacks by non-state actors irrespective of the territorial state s non-involvement therein, 4 but remains committed to an inter-state reading of the right to use force in self-defence. I agree entirely with Professor Tams approach on this point, as it is the only one which is consistent with the logic of the UN Charter. Article 2(4) prohibits the threat or use of force against the territorial integrity or political independence of any state. Using defensive force against the base of operations of non-state terrorist actors within a foreign host state s territory, even if that force targets only the non-state actors, still amounts to a violation of the host state s territorial integrity. If Article 51 is to be a 3 Ibid. 4 Ibid. doi: 10.1093/ejil/chp101

1050 EJIL 20 (2009), 1049 1055 true exception to the prohibition on the use of force as set out in Article 2(4), it must in some way excuse the violation of the host state s territorial integrity. 2 An Attribution-based Definition of Armed Attack The obvious difficulty with maintaining an inter-state reading of Article 51 in an age of terrorism is that terrorist attacks are rarely carried out by states themselves. The more common scenario is for non-state terrorist actors, acting from a foreign host state s territory, to carry out cross-border attacks. Professor Tams adopts the legal mechanism which has traditionally been relied on to preserve an inter-state reading of Article 51, yet accommodate the need to respond to attacks by non-state actors, i.e. that of attribution. 5 By requiring that armed attacks by non-state terrorist actors be attributable to the host state in whose territory defensive force is used, the violation of the host state s territorial integrity is excused. The further complication with adopting an attribution-based definition of armed attack is that it is difficult to re - concile with recent state practice in the 5 Professor Tams notes the argument that nothing in Art. 51 limits armed attacks to those carried out by states (see in particular the Separate Opinion of Judge Higgins in Wall Advisory Opinion [2004] ICJ Rep 136, at para. 33), and characterizes the ICJ s re-reading of Art. 51 in Nicaragua (defining armed attack as attacks carried out by one state against another) as one which will haunt the Court some 15 years later. He nevertheless maintains attribution as a necessary element of the right to use force in selfdefence in response to armed attacks by non-state actors: Tams, supra note 1, at 369, 384 385. terrorism context without doing some mischief to the secondary rules of state responsibility. The threshold of attribution which the International Court has set for an armed attack by non-state actors to be attributable to a state for the purposes of self-defence is very high indeed relying as it does on Article 3(g) of the Definition of Aggression. 6 But, as Professor Tams notes, an attributionbased definition of armed attack, coupled with such a high threshold for attributability, fails to account for recent uses of defensive force in response to terrorist attacks. In the state practice Professor Tams reviews briefly, 7 terrorist attacks were carried out by non-state actors from foreign territory, but were not attributable to the host state on the basis of the International Law Commission s Articles on State Responsibility (or Article 3(g) of the Definition of Aggression for that matter). Nevertheless, uses of defensive force in response to these terrorist attacks 6 Nicaragua, Merits [1986] ICJ Rep 14, at para. 195; DRC v. Uganda, Judgment of 19 Dec. 2005, available at: www.icj-cij.org/docket/files/70/6503. pdf, at para. 146. Professor Tams refers to the effective control test as a basis for attributing non-state armed attacks to a host state: Tams, supra note 1, at 385 386. In neither Nicaragua nor DRC v. Uganda, however, does the Court rely on the effective control test as a basis for attribution in the self-defence context. Effective control is the standard of attribution which the Court formulates in Nicaragua in the context of US responsibility for an internationally wrongful act (in particular the humanitarian law violations committed by the Contras) not in the context of US claims to have been acting in collective self-defence of El Salvador. This is not to say that effective control could not be used as a basis for attributing non-state armed attacks to the host state, just that the Court has not done so. 7 Tams, supra note 1, at 379 381.

The Use of Force against Terrorists: A Reply to Christian J. Tams 1051 were widely accepted as legitimate by the international community. In order to square the legitimacy of these defensive operations against an attribution-based definition of armed attack, Professor Tams argues that the threshold for attribution is evolving downwards, and he resuscitates a longrejected basis for attributing non-state conduct to a state aiding and abetting or complicity. 8 If complicity is a basis for attribution in the terrorism context, so the argument goes, then a state s support for terrorists acting from its territory (whether active or passive) effectively makes the complicit (and host) state the author of any terrorist attack launched from its territory, and thereby excuses the violation of that state s territorial integrity when defensive force is used against the non-state terrorist actors operating therefrom, consistent with an inter-state reading of Article 51. Professor Tams qualifies his re-reading of the standard of attribution as a more moderate (but still important) re-reading 9 when compared with the alternative ways of accommodating recent state practice, which he characterizes as radical. 10 Indeed Professor Tams complicity approach is more moderate than the one alternative he considers namely dispensing with the attribution requirement set out in Nicaragua without, however, replacing that requirement with some element which preserves an inter-state reading of Article 51 (i.e. excuses the violation of the host state s territorial integrity). 11 Professor Tams describes the radical approach as one which results in a right to use force in self-defence against all types of armed attacks, irrespective of any state involvement, which provides a justification for the attack on terrorists, [but does not] explain why states were entitled to violate the territorial sovereignty of the state in which they were based. 12 In considering only the one radical alternative, however, Professor Tams presents us with a false choice either maintain legal coherence by qualifying complicity as a basis of attribution or abandon the inter-state reading of Article 51. 3 The Alternative There is, however, a second alternative which squares recent state practice in the terrorism context against the International Court s jurisprudence, while maintaining an inter-state reading of Article 51, without doing mischief to the rules of attribution (which mischief I will discuss further below). First, as I have argued elsewhere, 13 a careful reading of the International Court of Justice s (ICJ s) jurisprudence reveals that it does not actually require armed attacks by non-state actors to be attributable to the host state before defensive force can be used against (and only against) those non-state actors in the host state s territory. The alternative reading of the Court s jurisprudence suggested below is context-sensitive, and does not divorce the Court s pronouncements on the applicable law from the factual context which the Court was addressing. 8 Ibid., at 385 386. 9 Ibid., at 385. 10 Ibid. 11 Ibid., at 383 385. 12 Ibid., at 385. 13 See Trapp, Back to Basics: Necessity, Proportionality and the Right of Self-Defence against non- State Terrorist Actors, 56 ICLQ (2007) 141.

1052 EJIL 20 (2009), 1049 1055 In Nicaragua and DRC v. Uganda, most often cited for the attribution-based definition of armed attack, the uses of defensive force either targeted government forces and installations or were far removed from the border area from which non-state actors launched their attacks. In Nicaragua, the ICJ considered whether American assistance to the Nicaraguan contra forces amounted to a legitimate exercise of the right of collective self-defence. The US claimed to be acting (primarily) in defence of El Salvador, which was the victim of armed attacks by rebel groups allegedly supplied with arms through Nicaragua with the active support, or at the very least complicity, of the Nicaraguan government. 14 Although the contras main targets were Sandinista troops, there were numerous reports of attacks on non-combatants, 15 and Nicaragua alleged a US-devised strategy for the contras to attack economic targets like electrical plants and storage facilities in Nicaragua. 16 The ICJ noted that to defend El Salvador against rebel attacks the US might have arranged for the deployment of a strong patrol force in El Salvador and Honduras, along the frontiers of these States with Nicaragua, and that it is difficult to accept that [the US] should have continued to carry out military and paramilitary activities against Nicaragua if their only purpose was, as alleged, to serve as a riposte in the exercise of the right of self-defence. 17 In DRC v. Uganda, the Court considered 14 The ICJ held that Nicaragua was not in fact responsible for the arms traffic, to the extent that such arms traffic existed: see Nicaragua, Merits, supra note 6, at paras 154 155. 15 Ibid., at para. 113. 16 Ibid., at para. 105. 17 Ibid., at para. 156. whether Uganda s use of force in the DRC s territory, ostensibly in response to armed attacks by anti-ugandan rebel groups, was a legitimate exercise of selfdefence. The ICJ emphasized that Uganda s defensive measures were carried out against the DRC, 18 particularly noting the fact that Ugandan military action was directed largely against towns and villages far removed from the territory from which anti-ugandan rebels operated. 19 In both cases, the Court held that a use of defensive force would have been legitimate only if the non-state actors had been sent by or on behalf of the state against which defensive force was used. The Court s insistence that armed attacks be attributable to a state before they give rise to a right to use force in self-defence, however, has to be understood in the context of its findings of fact. These decisions should be read as drawing a distinction between uses of defensive force against a host state in which case the armed attacks being responded to must be attributable to that state and uses of defensive force against (and only against) non-state actors within a host state s territory, without pronouncing on the legitimacy thereof (as the issue, on the facts, was not before the Court). Indeed, in DRC v. Uganda, the Court expressly refused to rule on the circumstances in which the latter use of force would be legitimate 20 suggesting perhaps that attribution would not be required. Professor Tams does note that the Court seems to leave the question of defensive force against irregulars open in DRC v. Uganda. But rather than read the jurisprudence as 18 DRC v. Uganda, Judgment, supra note 6, at paras 118 and 147. 19 Ibid., at paras 81 86. 20 Ibid., at para. 147.

The Use of Force against Terrorists: A Reply to Christian J. Tams 1053 suggested above, he maintains attributability as a necessary requirement for all acts of self-defence (even those directed exclusively at non-state actors within a foreign state s territory) and re-introduces complicity as a standard of attribution. The question remains: without attributability, how is the inter-state reading of armed attack to be preserved in particular, how can a use of defensive force directed against non-state terrorist actors in a foreign host state s territory be squared with that host state s territorial integrity? The customary international law requirement of necessity answers the call. 21 If a host state is doing everything possible to prevent its territory from being used as a base for terrorist operations, then a use of defensive force in that state s territory is simply not necessary and the matter should be addressed through cooperative arrangements with the host state. If a state is complicit in its territory being used as a base for terrorist operations, then a use of defensive force in response to terrorist attacks by non-state actors from that state s territory is necessary, and the complicity provides the justification for the violation of the host state s territorial integrity. Professor Tams makes the point himself that the international community is much less likely to deny, as a matter of principle, that states can invoke self-defence against terrorist attacks not imputable to another state. Instead the debate has shifted towards issues of necessity and proportionality.... 22 He further refers to this potential mechanism for preserving an inter-state reading of Article 51 in footnote 176, noting that some (unnamed) commentators typically refer 21 Trapp, supra note 13. 22 Tams, supra note 1, at 381. back to the arguments about the unwillingness (or even inability) of the territorial state to prevent terrorist activities conduct which in turn means that the territorial state had to accept the use of force against its territory. But Professor Tams then asserts that this however means that at some level issues of state involvement re-enter the debate. Precisely! Issues of state involvement have to enter the debate if an inter-state reading of Article 51 is to be maintained. The question is whether that state involvement needs to be qualified as anything more than it is. Indeed, Professor Tams concludes that contemporary practice suggests that a territorial state has to accept anti-terrorist measures of self-defence directed against its territory where it is responsible for complicity in the activities of terrorists based on its territory either because of its support below the level of direction and control [i.e. generally accepted bases of attribution] or because it has provided a safe haven for terrorists. Professor Tams clearly recognizes that complicity plays a role in excusing a violation of the host state s territorial integrity but, having so recognized, he takes the unnecessary step of subsuming that complicity within attribution in order to maintain the framework he has adopted. The requirement that armed attacks be attributable to the host state is nothing more than a mechanism for maintaining an inter-state reading of Article 51 and ensuring that defensive force is a true exception to the prohibition on the use of force against the territorial integrity or political independence of another state. But the attribution requirement is derived from a reading of the ICJ s jurisprudence which is divorced from the factual context of the relevant decisions and cannot be

1054 EJIL 20 (2009), 1049 1055 squared with recent state practice in the terrorism context without resuscitating longrejected bases of attribution (as discussed further below). Professor Tams distorts the level of state involvement in terrorism (complicity pure and simple) by labelling it a basis of attribution (with all that this implies about who done it ) when there is an alternative framework available which preserves an inter-state reading of Article 51 without muddying the conceptual waters. 4 Mischief to the Rules of Attribution Early codification efforts and arbitral decisions did not unambiguously distinguish between state responsibility based on the attributability of un-prevented or unpunished private conduct and responsibility based on the failure to prevent or punish private conduct where there was an international obligation to do so. But this artificial way of linking private conduct to the state, rather than focusing on whether the state had an independent obligation to prevent or punish the conduct, was gradually abandoned in the period between World War I and World War II. 23 The International Law Commission (ILC), in its Articles on State Responsibility, and international jurisprudence have since firmly rejected complicity or acquiescence in private conduct as a basis of attribution. 24 23 See in particular Janes Case (US v. Mexico), United States and United Mexican States General Claims Commission, Opinion of Commissioners, IV Reports of International Arbitral Awards (1926) 82. 24 See Genocide Case, Merits, judgment of 26 Feb. 2007, available at: www.icj-cij.org/docket/files /91/13685.pdf, at para. 420, in which the ICJ considered state responsibility for complicity in genocide, an ancillary offence under the Genocide Convention, and clearly distinguished it from a standard of attribution. As customary international law matured, primary obligations were more clearly articulated: states are under an obligation themselves to refrain from engaging in certain conduct (for instance terrorism), to refrain from supporting such conduct, and to prevent private actors from engaging in such conduct from their territory. There was therefore no need to hold a state directly responsible for supported or unprevented private conduct via attribution through its complicity therein, because the state could be held responsible for the independent breach of its obligations to refrain from supporting or to prevent international terrorism. The distorting effect of Professor Tams argument on attribution is even clearer in the state responsibility context. 25 While there is a driving force behind Professor Tams reading down of the rules of attribution in the jus ad bellum context namely to preserve the inter-state reading of Article 51 there is absolutely no reason at all to label complicity a basis of attribution in the state responsibility context. If applied in the state responsibility context, Professor Tams argument collapses a primary rule into a secondary rule of state responsibility. States 25 Professor Tams discusses his proposed departure from the effective control test of attribution in the context of the ILC s Articles on State Responsibility and the ICJ s decision in the Genocide Case (Tams, supra note 1, at 386) both of which are obviously about state responsibility and not Art. 51. He also refers to aiding and abetting as broadening the forms of support which trigger a territorial state s responsibility, ibid. Both of these statements suggest that Professor Tams considers complicity qua attribution to be a lex specialis which operates in both the jus ad bellum and state responsibility terrorism contexts even though the focus of his article is the jus ad bellum.

The Use of Force against Terrorists: A Reply to Christian J. Tams 1055 are under customary international law and treaty obligations to refrain from engaging in terrorist activities, to refrain from supporting such activities, and to prevent terrorist activities within their territories. 26 Complicity in terrorist activities, whether the result of support for or a deliberate failure to prevent terrorism, is in breach of an independent obligation under both customary international and treaty law. An argument that states should be held directly responsible for positive conduct (the commission of a terrorist act) on the basis of attributability, when all they may be guilty of is an omission (a however deliberate failure to prevent) renders many of the primary rules of international law in the terrorism context redundant and is difficult to distinguish from that (in)famous Bush-ism, we will make no distinction between the terrorists who committed these acts and those who harbor them. Professor Tams does of course note that his reading down of the rules of attribution in the terrorism context is not necessarily a positive development, but nevertheless considers his position (at least in the jus ad bellum context) to be a more moderate (but still important) re-reading 27 than the alternatives. Given the alternative suggested above, which preserves an inter-state reading of Article 51 by relying on the customary international law elements of self-defence (and therefore surely could not be characterised as radical ) this is simply not the case. Special Rapporteur on State Responsibility Ago s widely acknowledged stroke of genius was to draw a clear distinction between the primary and secondary rules of state responsibility. The conceptual clarity which thereafter emerged in the ILC s work on state responsibility should be celebrated, not undermined. Surely collapsing the distinction in the terrorism context is what amounts to a radical re-reading. 26 The treaty basis for the obligation to refrain from engaging in terrorist activities or supporting such activities is the series of terrorism suppression conventions adopted under the auspices of the ICAO, IMO, and UN (for instance the Terrorist Bombing Convention) which require states to prevent certain acts of international terrorism. Based on the ICJ s decision in the Genocide Case, Merits, supra note 24, an obligation to prevent implies an obligation to refrain from engaging in the conduct to be prevented and to refrain from ancillary crimes in reference to such conduct (such as aiding and abetting or supporting). 27 Tams, supra note 1, at 385.