Responsible Victims and (Partly) Justified Offenders

Similar documents
VOLUNTARY MANSLAUGHTER INCLUDING SELF-DEFENSE (IN THE HEAT OF

Question With what crime or crimes should Dan be charged? Discuss. 2. What defense or defenses might Dan assert? Discuss.

The defendant has been charged with second degree murder. 1

QUESTION What charges can reasonably be brought against Steve? Discuss. 2. What charges can reasonably be brought against Will? Discuss.

The defendant has been charged with second degree murder. 1. Under the law and the evidence in this case, it is your duty to return

Case 1:11-cr KBM Document 149 Filed 12/13/12 Page 1 of 10 IN THE DISTRICT COURT OF THE UNITED STATES FOR THE DISTRICT OF NEW MEXICO

ADMINISTRATION OF JUSTICE GENERAL ASPECTS OF CRIMINAL LAW. Name: Period: Row:

Section 20 Mistake as to a Justification 631. Chapter 4. Offenses Against the Person Article 1. Homicide Section Murder in the First Degree

21. Creating criminal offences

Criminal Justice: A Brief Introduction Twelfth Edition

LEVEL 3 - UNIT 3 - CRIMINAL LAW SUGGESTED ANSWERS JUNE 2011

Contents PART 1: CRIMINAL LIABILITY. Table of Statutes. Table of Secondary Legislation. Table of Cases

NEGLIGENCE. All four of the following must be demonstrated for a legal claim of negligence to be successful:

California Bar Examination

Florida Jury Instructions. 7.2 MURDER FIRST DEGREE (1)(a), Fla. Stat.

CHAPTER 4, On Liberty. Does Mill Qualify the Liberty Principle to Death? Dick Arneson For PHILOSOPHY 166 FALL, 2006

Summer 2008 August 1, 2008 SAMPLE ANSWER TO FINAL EXAM MULTIPLE CHOICE

Victim Protection in Criminal Proceedings Legislation: A pan-european Comparison"

SELF-DEFENSE EXAMPLE WITH ALL ASSAULTS INVOLVING DEADLY FORCE.

THE FAILURE TO CHARGE ON ALL OF THESE MATTERS CONSTITUTES REVERSIBLE ERROR

Section 17 Lesser Evils Defense 535. Chapter Ten. Offenses Against the Person. Article One. Causing Death

HSC Legal Studies. Year 2017 Mark Pages 46 Published Feb 6, Legal Studies: Crime. By Rose (99.4 ATAR)

Washoe Tribe of Nevada and California. Law & Order Code TITLE 3 TORTS. [Last Amended 10/1/04. Current Through 2/3/09.]

UNIT 2 Part 1 CRIMINAL LAW

IN THE COURT OF CRIMINAL APPEALS OF TENNESSEE AT KNOXVILLE October 27, 2009 Session

SUMMER 2009 August 7, 2009 FINAL EXAM SAMPLE ANSWER

ASSAULT IN LAWFUL DEFENSE OF A [FAMILY MEMBER] [THIRD PERSON] (DEFENSE TO ASSAULTS NOT INVOLVING DEADLY FORCE).

Introduction to Criminal Law

214 Part III Homicide and Related Issues

Civil Liability Amendment (Personal Responsibility) Act 2002 No 92

Question 1. On what theory or theories might damages be recovered, and what defenses might reasonably be raised in actions by:

Please do not cite; it s drafty in here.

Particular Crimes can be grouped under 3 headings: Crimes against people Crimes against property Crimes against business interests

STATE OF MICHIGAN COURT OF APPEALS

CRIMINAL LAW ESSAY SERIES ESSAY QUESTION #2 MODEL ANSWER. 1. With what crime or crimes should Dan be charged? Discuss.

THE FAILURE TO CHARGE ON ALL OF THESE MATTERS CONSTITUTES REVERSIBLE ERROR.

1. The physical element of a crime is the a. mens rea b. actus reus c. offence d. intention

CRIMINAL LAW CHART OF BLACK LETTER LAW DEFINITIONS & ELEMENTS

Offences 3. S300 Unlawful homicide 3. S302(1)(a) Intentional Murder 4. S303 Manslaughter 7. S335 Common Assault 9

Verbal Abuse and the Aggressor Doctrine

692 Part VI.b Excuse Defenses

GUILT ASPECTS OF COMPARATIVE LAW

Unit One Introduction to law

FALL 2013 December 14, 2013 FINAL EXAM SAMPLE ANSWER MULTIPLE CHOICE

MODEL INSTRUCTION ASSAULT ON A LAW ENFORCEMENT OFFICER ARREST SITUATIONS.

THE CRIMINAL EQUATION

Restatement (Second) of Torts 496A (1965) Assumption of Risk

PRINCIPLES OF EUROPEAN TORT LAW

Question 2. With what crimes, if any, could Al be charged and what defenses, if any, could he assert? Discuss.

Topic 5 Non-fatal,Non-sexual offences against the person

Civil Law is known as Private Law. Regulates disputes between individuals; between parties; and between individuals and parties.

I. Limits of Criminal law a. Due process b. Principle of legality c. Void for vagueness II. Mental State a. Traditional law i.

STATE OF MICHIGAN COURT OF APPEALS

208.81F ASSAULT ON AN OFFICER AND SIMPLE ASSAULT ARREST SITUATIONS (ALL ISSUES IN DISPUTE).

TORTS SPECIFIC TORTS NEGLIGENCE

Fall 2008 January 1, 2009 SAMPLE ANSWER TO FINAL EXAM MULTIPLE CHOICE

STATE OF MICHIGAN COURT OF APPEALS

NOTE WELL: Use only with N.C.P.I.--Crim , A, , A, , and when no evidence of deadly force. 1

CAUSATION & RISK. Upping the risk: when does it count? James Townsend, Guildhall Chambers

Introduction to Criminal Law

TYPES OF MONETARY DAMAGES

Criminal Law, Class #525_0AC_5101, with Duncan M START OF EXAM. In CL: He should not prevail. In CL, once an attempt has been made, D cannot

APPENDIX E. MINORITY REPORT 7.7 Manslaughter

STATE OF MICHIGAN COURT OF APPEALS

OBJECTIVES: Differentiate between federal and state laws and develop understanding between crimes against people, and crimes against property.

H 5104 S T A T E O F R H O D E I S L A N D

THE LAW PROFESSOR TORT LAW ESSAY SERIES ESSAY QUESTION #3 MODEL ANSWER

[page Snyman] 1. Legality 2. Conduct 3. Causation 4. Unlawfulness 5. Criminal accountability/ capacity 6. Fault

H 5447 S T A T E O F R H O D E I S L A N D

Section 9 Causation 291

The section Causation: Actual Cause and Proximate Cause from Business Law and the Legal Environment was adapted by The Saylor Foundation under a

Criminal Justice in America CJ Chapter 4 James J. Drylie, Ph.D.

Judicial Branch. Why this is important What do I do if I m arrested? What are my rights? What happens in court?

Criminal Law Doctrine and Theory

The Limits of Self-Defense

LAWS206 TORTS Semester Georgia Gamble

CRIMINAL OFFENCES (AMENDMENT) ACT 2012

Negligent In Your Legal Knowledge?

The HIDDEN COST Of Proving Your Innocence

SOC 3395: Criminal Justice & Corrections Lecture 4&5: Criminal Law & Criminal Justice in Canada II:

Question 1. Under what theory or theories might Paul recover, and what is his likelihood of success, against: a. Charlie? b. KiddieRides-R-Us?

Court of Appeals of Ohio

CRIM EXAM NOTES. Table of Contents. Weeks 1-4

No. IN THE SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES. October Term 2013

Criminal Law Outline intent crime

Elon University School of Law Honor Code Preamble

Indicate the answer choice that best completes the statement or answers the question.

Question 2. Dawn lives in an apartment with her dog Fluffy and her boyfriend Bill. A year ago Bill began buying and selling illegal drugs.

Business Law Tort Law Unit Textbook

The defendant has been charged with first degree murder.

IN THE UNITED STATES COURT OF APPEALS FOR THE ELEVENTH CIRCUIT. No D.C. Docket No. 4:16-cr WTM-GRS-1

Reality of Consent. Reality of Consent. Reality of Consent. Chapter 13

CALIFORNIA HOMICIDE LAW IN THE NEW MILLENNIUM

Civil Justice for Victims of Crime in Ohio

TORT LAW. By Helen Jordan, Elaine Martinez, and Jim Ponce

Unions Tasmania Tasmanian Branch of the ACTU

v No Wayne Circuit Court

California Bar Examination

Legal Liability in Adventure Tourism

Title 17-A: MAINE CRIMINAL CODE

Transcription:

Responsible Victims and (Partly) Justified Offenders R. A. Duff VERA BERGELSON, VICTIMS RIGHTS AND VICTIMS WRONGS: COMPARATIVE LIABILITY IN CRIMINAL LAW (Stanford University Press 2009) If you negligently cause damage to my property, I can sue you for the cost of repairing it or replacing it. However, if you can show that my negligent conduct contributed to the causation of the damage, that will significantly affect my claim. As Vera Bergelson notes (pp. 52 56), on a draconian version of the doctrine of contributory negligence, it destroys my case I can claim nothing from you. On a more plausible and less draconian version of the doctrine, as a doctrine of comparative negligence, it reduces the amount I can claim; I must now share the cost of the damage in proportion to my negligent contribution to it. In tort law, the victim s conduct, in particular the victim s faulty conduct, thus plays a crucial role in determinations of liability. In criminal law, by contrast, matters seem very different. Unless the victim s conduct was such as to defeat the claim that the defendant caused the relevant harm, it does not qualify or undermine the defendant s liability in the way that it can in tort law. I might have negligently or recklessly placed myself or my property at risk, but if you caused damage to me or my property, either on purpose or through your reckless conduct, you are guilty of a criminal offense, and my recklessness or negligence does not seem to defeat, or even qualify, your guilt. One of Bergelson s aims is to point out how misleading that familiar contrast between tort law and criminal law is by reminding us of some familiar ways in which the victim s (or alleged victim s) conduct can make a significant difference to the defendant s liability. If V consented to what D did to him, or at least voluntarily assumed the risk that D would do that, then D might be entitled to a complete acquittal (or to conviction only of a lesser crime or at least to some mitigation of sentence). The same is true if D acted defensively to ward off V s attack or if V provoked D. But her aims are more ambitious than such a reminder of familiar features of our criminal law. Bergelson also wants to explain and justify (and show the unity of) such provisions by a more general account of the ways in which victims conduct can affect defendants liability, and to ground that account in a conception of rights as essentially conditional on the right-holder s own conduct. What makes a difference to D s criminal liability in the familiar kinds of case noted above is that in each case, V by his own acts, has waived or Professor, Department of Philosophy, University of Stirling and Minnesota Law School. 209

210 OHIO STATE JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW [Vol 8:209 reduced his right not to be harmed. (P. 4.) Such waiving or reducing, which can be voluntary or involuntary, provides D with either a complete or at least a partial justification for his deed. This account, Bergelson argues, makes good and coherent sense of aspects of our existing criminal law. It also, she thinks, enables us to see how our criminal law can be improved to do justice to the difference that victims conduct should make to defendants liability. In the course of this overall argument, we get detailed discussions of the proper contours of the defenses (consent, self-defense, and provocation) on which her account focuses; but I will focus here on the overall argument and some of the questions that it provokes. I. TORT LAW AND CRIMINAL LAW First, I think we should set aside the analogy that Bergelson draws between tort law and criminal law, since it is at best unhelpful (and at worst misleading). Although, as she notes (p. 52), the distinction between tort law and criminal law is blurred by provisions for punitive damages in tort law, and compensation or restitution orders in criminal law, the basic logic of the two kinds of law differs in a way that renders them disanalogous for present purposes. In a paradigm tort law case, what is at stake is who should bear the cost of the harm or damage that has been caused a cost that is supposed to be, at least in principle, finite and determinable. The doctrine of comparative fault holds, rather plausibly, that the cost should be allocated in proportion to the faulty contribution that each of the parties involved made to the harm: if the plaintiff s negligence contributed to the causation of the harm, she should bear some of the cost; likewise, if more than one defendant contributed to the causation of the harm, the cost of repair or compensation should be shared between them. In this context we can properly say, with Bergelson, that it would be unfair to assign all the responsibility for an injury to one party, the [defendant], and completely ignore the victim s contribution, if that contribution was itself faulty. (P. 53.) Furthermore, in this context, responsibility shared is responsibility reduced for each of those who share it: to the extent the injurious result is attributable to an act of another, the offender should not bear responsibility for it. (P. 54.) If you and I must share responsibility for the damage to my property, we must share the cost of repairing it; I cannot claim that you should pay the whole cost. Equally, if my car is destroyed as the result of the negligent behavior of ten other people, I am entitled to claim the full cost of replacing it from the ten of them. However, I cannot claim that each should pay the full cost; rather, each should pay one-tenth. We can also say in the context of the criminal law that it would be unfair to assign all the responsibility for an injury to the defendant if the victim was also, at least to some degree, responsible for the harm that he suffered; but the meaning and implications of this claim are now quite different, because the responsibility at stake is now quite different. The question now is not who is or should be held liable to carry the cost of repairing the harm, but rather who is or should be held

2010] RESPONSIBLE VICTIMS AND (PARTLY) JUSTIFIED OFFENDERS 211 liable to conviction and punishment for culpably causing that harm. In this context, responsibility that is shared is not thereby necessarily reduced, since it is not now responsibility as to a finite burden. If my car is destroyed by an act of criminal vandalism, it might turn out that there was just one perpetrator, who was solely responsible for destroying it, or ten, who destroyed it between them. Yet in the latter case, no one would suggest that the criminal responsibility of each perpetrator is reduced, or that each should be convicted of a lesser crime or receive a lighter sentence. To argue or show in the context of tort law that the plaintiff was partly responsible for the harm that she suffered is thus already to argue or show that the defendant s responsibility is reduced, and that his liability how much he should have to pay is also reduced. To argue or show in the context of criminal law that the victim was partly responsible for the crime is not in the same way already to argue or show that the defendant s responsibility is reduced, or that his liability the offense of which he is convicted and the punishment that he receives should also be reduced. We need some further argument for those further claims. Furthermore, in tort law, what seems to be crucial, on Bergelson s account, is the victim-plaintiff s fault. What reduces the defendant s responsibility is not just that the victim-plaintiff played a causal role in the occurrence of the harm, but that she was at fault in doing so. 1 But it is not the victim s fault that is crucial in the criminal context. This is clearest in the case of consent: whether consent negates an element of the offense, or provides a justification for its commission, its normative efficacy does not typically depend on its being wrongful or faulty. But the point also applies to self-defense, since both culpable and innocent aggressors, on Bergelson s account, waive their rights and thus justify the defender s action. (P. 72.) 2 An attacker might thus be free of fault, but his attack still justifies his target s use of defensive force. Only in the case of provocation, therefore, is the victim s fault crucial to the reduction of the defendant s responsibility or liability; the victim s fault does not provide a unifying rationale. II. RIGHT-WAIVING, CRIME AND JUSTIFICATION Second, what does provide the unifying rationale is the suggestion that, in all three kinds of case, the (alleged) victim has waived or reduced his right not to be harmed. (P. 4.) That waiver might be voluntary, as when the victim consents to or assumes the risk of what is done; or it might be involuntary, for instance when 1 Although it must also be a good, and complete, defense to a claim in tort law that the plaintiff consented to what the defendant did, there are clearly plenty of other ways, beyond those involving some contributory fault, in which the plaintiff s conduct can affect the defendant s liability. 2 More precisely, aggressors who chose to change their moral status vis-à-vis the perpetrator thereby waive or forfeit their rights, even if their attack was excused or justified; when the aggressor or threat lacks such power of choice, his rights are overridden rather than waived or forfeited. (P. 76.)

212 OHIO STATE JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW [Vol 8:209 the victim somehow assault[ed] an important right of the perpetrator (p. 107), thus justifying or partly justifying the perpetrator s action. 3 Now there are familiar worries about the suggestion that we can understand such justifications as selfdefense in terms of a waiving of rights (some of which Bergelson addresses), but there is a particular worry about how this suggestion fits with other aspects of her account. She insists that an agent can plead justification only if she was both aware of and motivated by the factors that ground the justification (p. 63) she must have acted in order to achieve [the] better balance of harms and evils that makes her action justifiable. (P. 93, emphasis added.) Bergelson also argues that conduct should be criminal only if it either violates the victim s rights or disregards the victim s dignity. (P. 67.) These three propositions, however, seem to be inconsistent. If V has waived his right not to be harmed in a certain way, then one who harms him in that way has not violated his rights, whether or not she knows that V has waived his rights, or knows the facts in virtue of which V counts as having waived his rights, or is motivated by any morally proper intention. If the harmer has not violated V s rights, she has committed a crime only if, in acting as she did, she disregarded V s dignity; but nothing in Bergelson s discussion of dignity and how it is violated suggests that this will always be so that I violate another s dignity whenever I act in a way that would violate a right if she had not waived it. If by attacking you I waive my right not to be killed, then in killing me you do not violate my right, whatever you know about the situation and whatever your motives. Likewise, if by putting a television that I no longer need at the roadside I thereby waive my rights as its owner and invite anyone to take it, someone who takes it does not violate my rights, even if he thinks he is stealing it without my consent. So it seems that Bergelson cannot maintain both her account of justification and her claim that what gives D a defense in the cases she discusses is that V has waived his rights. I think that Bergelson is right about justifications. If a liability-negating factor is properly classed as a matter of justification, rather than as negating an element of the offense, then the defendant who seeks an acquittal on the basis of that factor must adduce evidence not merely of its existence, but that she was aware of and motivated by it. But her account of the nature of crime makes the violation of rights (or dignity) an essential element of the offense itself if V has waived or reduced his rights, then the offense has not been committed (or has not been committed in its most serious form), and D need make no claim about what she knew or what motivated her. If Bergelson is to sustain her (plausible) conception of justification, she must therefore either revise her conception of crime, and argue that I can commit a criminal wrong against V without infringing either his rights or his dignity (which does not look a plausible route for her to 3 It is not entirely clear how the idea of an involuntary waiver or reduction of rights fits with the claim that a right is waived or forfeited only when the agent chooses to change their moral status vis-à-vis the perpetrator (p. 76), since a chosen change of moral status is hardly involuntary.

2010] RESPONSIBLE VICTIMS AND (PARTLY) JUSTIFIED OFFENDERS 213 take), or abandon her claim that when V s conduct precludes or qualifies D s liability, that is because V has waived or reduced his right not to be harmed. (P. 4.) III. WHAT RIGHTS ARE WAIVED (OR REDUCED)? Third, there is a further, familiar puzzle about just which rights V should be taken to have waived or reduced, especially in the contexts of self-defense and provocation (it is easier to work out what rights V has waived in the contexts of consent and assumption of risk). Take first the case in which V s conduct gives D a complete justification for her action a case of self-defense, for instance. If the only way in which D can protect herself against a murderous attack by V is to kill V, she is justified in doing that; so on Bergelson s account, V has waived his right not to be killed. Suppose, however, that D could easily defend herself by causing a harm less serious than death to V, either by injuring V, perhaps, or by damaging V s property (suppose V is, as D knows, so attached to his car that D could divert him from his attack for long enough to make her own safe escape simply by throwing a rock at his car, for example). Under such circumstances, D is fully justified only in doing that lesser harm to V; if she kills V, thus using more force and causing more harm than is reasonably necessary to defend herself, she can claim only partial justification. (P. 105.) So it seems that in this case, V has not waived his right not to be killed (for if he had waived it, D would not commit a criminal wrong in killing him); but he has waived his right not to suffer whatever harm (whatever infringement of what would have been a right had he not waived it) is reasonably necessary for D to cause in defending herself. One implication of this picture is that what rights I waive by my action can depend not just on the nature of that action, but also on the circumstances that determine what must be done to frustrate my attack. If two people mount wouldbe murderous attacks that are similar in their culpability and seriousness, one might think that both should be taken to have waived the same rights, to the same extent; but if fortuitously, one attack could be warded off without causing fatal, or even serious, harm to the attacker, whilst the other can be warded off only by killing him, it seems that, on Bergelson s account, they have waived different rights the latter, but not the former, has waived his right not to be killed. Perhaps, as Bergelson suggests, a suitably context-sensitive, relational account of rights would allow for this, but there is another, more serious problem about the rights that are, and those that are not, waived, and the relation between them which is also a puzzle about what it means to reduce one s rights. If D kills V when she could have warded off his attack by simply wounding him, or by damaging his car, she has presumably violated his right not to be killed a right that he has not waived. He has waived his right not to be wounded, or not to have his property damaged; but D s action does not answer to that waiving, since she does not wound him (unless death is classed as a particularly serious wound) or damage his property. On Bergelson s account, she is partly

214 OHIO STATE JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW [Vol 8:209 justified in killing him. (P. 105.) But how? It must be because he has reduced his right(s); but what does that mean? Bergelson s answer seems to be that he has reduced his overall right not to be harmed, by waiving some of the specific rights that constitute that overall right. (P. 91.) He has waived his specific right not to be wounded, or not to have his property damaged, and that waiving reduces the weight or value of the overall right not to be harmed. So whilst in killing him D does violate his right not to be killed, and thus his overall right not to be harmed, that violation constitutes a less serious wrong. But this seems a very strange picture (and it is not helpful to treat all specific rights, as Bergelson s account seems to commit her to treating them, as instantiations of a general right not to be harmed). My right not to be killed is surely not reduced in weight or in value by my waiving my right that my property not be damaged; and even if we look only at harms of the same general type, such as bodily harms, it seems odd to suggest that in waiving my right not to be wounded I also reduce the weight or value of my right not to be killed. Maybe a more detailed development and explication of Bergelson s account would show either that these puzzles are not real or that they can be resolved; but the book does not offer us enough explanation to show this, and must thus leave us with the strong suspicion that we cannot explain these ways in which the victim s conduct can affect the defendant s liability by talking of waiving or reducing rights. IV. VICTIM NEGLIGENCE AND CRIMINAL LIABILITY Finally, can the victim s negligence, if it contributes to the causation of the relevant harm (but not so significantly as to negate the defendant s causal responsibility) make a difference to the defendant s criminal liability? It is striking that whilst the issue of victim fault in tort law arises most typically when the fault consists in negligence, 4 Bergelson s discussion of criminal law focuses on the difference that the alleged victim s intentional conduct can make to the defendant s liability. Indeed, it sometimes looks as if only what V does intentionally can affect D s liability: The victim s conduct should mitigate the perpetrator s liability only when the victim has waived his rights voluntarily, by consent or assumption of risk, or lost them involuntarily, by attacking or threatening some legally recognized rights of others. (P. 123.) 5 4 As in Beul v. ASSE Int l. Inc., 233 F.3d 441, 451 (7 th Cir. 2000), from which she quotes the judicial claim by Judge Posner that [v]ictim fault is not a defense, either partial or complete, to criminal liability (P. 2.) 5 She is here discussing cases in which D uses force against V in response to, or to ward off, a threat of harm that V creates.

2010] RESPONSIBLE VICTIMS AND (PARTLY) JUSTIFIED OFFENDERS 215 For she sets tight constraints on assumption of risk: V can be taken to have assumed a risk of harm only if he purposefully engage[s] in a risky activity (p. 104), and may not be deemed to have assumed the risk of unlawful conduct by another. (P. 100, emphasis omitted.) We have also seen already that even involuntary right-waiving requires that V chose to change [his] moral status vis-àvis the perpetrator (p. 76); this might cover cases in which V s conduct was reckless rather than intentional, but does not capture merely negligent conduct. Now Bergelson does not actually limit involuntary right-waiving to cases in which V chooses to change his moral status, since she argues in the passage from which I have just quoted that V s negligent risk-creation can reduce D s liability (to a limited extent) when D uses force against V in response to that risk. (P. 123.) But what should we make of the familiar tort law case in which V s negligence plays a casual role in the occurrence of the relevant harm not the kind of case in which V creates a risk to which D then responds, but the kind of case in which civil courts would talk of contributory negligence? Bergelson mentions this kind of case briefly, towards the end of the book: if V is injured or killed by D s car, when D is drunk or speeding, D s liability should be reduced if V s own negligence played a significant role in the causation of the accident. (Pp. 156 57.) But how is this consistent with her account? V has certainly not involuntarily waived or reduced his rights, since I involuntarily waive or reduce my rights against another only if I act in a way that breaches some duty I owe her that is, only if she has a right that I not act thus. (P. 105.) Nor does it seem that V has voluntarily waived or reduced his rights he did not consent to being crashed into by D; in many cases we could not plausibly say that he purposefully engage[d] in a risky activity (p. 104) that led to the accident; and since D s drunken or excessively fast driving is unlawful, V cannot, in any case, be taken to have assumed the risk of it. 6 Or should we say that what matters in such cases of recklessness or negligence is comparative causation (pp. 144 54): that the extent of D s responsibility for the harm that V suffers is conditioned by the causal contribution that each made to the occurrence of the harm (p. 146)? But this brings us to a point noted earlier: that while in tort law responsibility shared is usually responsibility reduced for each of those who share it, the same is not true in criminal law. There would be an interesting and striking analogy between criminal law and tort law if the victim s faulty (reckless or negligent) conduct should mitigate the defendant s criminal liability, as it can mitigate his civil liability; but Bergelson s 6 I m taking unlawful conduct at face value, to cover not just intentional attacks on another, but offenses of recklessness or negligence. A narrower reading might be suggested by the passage that Bergelson quotes in support of this limitation on what risks we can be deemed to have assumed: people must be able to assume that others will do them no intended injury (p. 100, quoting ROSCOE POUND, AN INTRODUCTION TO THE PHILOSOPHY OF LAW 169 (1922)); so perhaps it could be said that although I cannot assume the risk that another will attack me, I can assume the risk that he will recklessly or negligently endanger me. But what would justify this narrower reading?

216 OHIO STATE JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW [Vol 8:209 brief comments on this issue are apparently at odds with the core of her argument in this book, which emphasizes the victim s purposive conduct, and she does not say enough to show whether that apparent inconsistency is real or not. There are, as Bergelson shows, important questions about the ways in which the (alleged) victim s conduct can affect the defendant s criminal liability, and about whether we can find a unitary theory to explain them all. This book proposes an ambitious unifying theory; but its argument is too often underdeveloped, and (as I have tried to indicate) has too many internal problems, to persuade us that it offers a promising route to understanding criminal liability in comparative terms.