Hobbes Today: Insights for the 21st Century, ed.s.a.lloyd(cambridge University Press: New York, 2013), 353 pp., 65.00, ISBN

Similar documents
Social Contract Theory

Hobbes Today. Insights for the 21st Century

Reclaiming the Rights of the Hobbesian Subject

MODERN POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY (Autumn Term, 2014)

On Human Rights by James Griffin, Oxford University Press, 2008, 339 pp.

Rawls, Islam, and political constructivism: Some questions for Tampio

POLITICAL AUTHORITY AND PERFECTIONISM: A RESPONSE TO QUONG

Instructor: Margaret Kohn. Fall, Thursday, Office Hours: Thursday 1:00-2:00 (SS3118)

Politics between Philosophy and Democracy

New Directions for the Capability Approach: Deliberative Democracy and Republicanism

Rawls versus the Anarchist: Justice and Legitimacy

Controversy Liberalism, Democracy and the Ethics of Votingponl_

Modern Political Thinkers and Ideas

POSC 6100 Political Philosophy

AMY GUTMANN: THE CONSTRUCTIVE POTENTIAL OF COMMUNITARIAN VALUES DOES GUTMANN SUCCEED IN SHOWING THE CONSTRUCTIVE POTENTIAL OF COMMUNITARIAN VALUES?

Choose one question from each section to answer in the time allotted.

Reply to Professor Klosko

Jan Narveson and James P. Sterba

John Rawls. Cambridge University Press John Rawls: An Introduction Percy B. Lehning Frontmatter More information

Choose one question from each section to answer in the time allotted.

Nel Noddings. Chapter 9: Social and Political Philosophy. Two Competing Emphases in Social & Political Philosophy: Assumptions of liberalism:

Justifying the State. Protection and Power

Political Obligation 2

Reflections on Citizens Juries: the case of the Citizens Jury on genetic testing for common disorders

Political Science 771 Modern Political Thought Fall 2010 Tuesday, 3:30pm to 5:45pm, 115 Murphey

Hobbes, Locke, Montesquieu, and Rousseau on Government

S.L. Hurley, Justice, Luck and Knowledge, (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2003), 341 pages. ISBN: (hbk.).

The Morality of Conflict

The public vs. private value of health, and their relationship. (Review of Daniel Hausman s Valuing Health: Well-Being, Freedom, and Suffering)

Introduction. Cambridge University Press Global Distributive Justice Chris Armstrong Excerpt More information

We recommend you cite the published version. The publisher s URL is:

Social and Political Philosophy

No man is an island. By Ingemund Hägg 2. John Stuart Mill, liberalism and flawed attacks by anti-liberals 1. The human being

Theories of Justice. Is economic inequality unjust? Ever? Always? Why?

Book Prospectus. The Political in Political Economy: from Thomas Hobbes to John Rawls

On the Irrelevance of Formal General Equilibrium Analysis

Ordering Power: Contentious Politics and Authoritarian Leviathans in Southeast Asia

Political Science 103 Spring, 2018 Dr. Edward S. Cohen INTRODUCTION TO POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY

Why Government? Activity, pg 1. Name: Page 8 of 26

Bernd Lahno Can the Social Contract Be Signed by an Invisible Hand? A New Debate on an Old Question *

Lesson 3: The Declaration s Ideas

Introduction[1] The obstacle

Political Science 103 Fall, 2015 Dr. Edward S. Cohen INTRODUCTION TO POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY

CHAPTER 1 PROLOGUE: VALUES AND PERSPECTIVES

Do we have a strong case for open borders?

Facts and Principles in Political Constructivism Michael Buckley Lehman College, CUNY

The Original Position

CONTEXTUALISM AND GLOBAL JUSTICE

Freedom in a Democratic Society

Social Contract Theory According to Thomas Hobbes & John Locke

On Original Appropriation. Peter Vallentyne, University of Missouri-Columbia

Beccaria s Dream On Criminal Law and Nodal Governance. Klaas Rozemond Associate professor of Criminal Law VU University Amsterdam

BOOK REVIEWS. Dr. Dragica Vujadinović * Ronald Dworkin, Justice for Hedgehogs, Cambridge, London: Harvard University Press, 2011, 506.

Law and Philosophy (2015) 34: Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2015 DOI /s ARIE ROSEN BOOK REVIEW

Unit 1 Guided Notes: Foundations of Government

Review of Christian List and Philip Pettit s Group agency: the possibility, design, and status of corporate agents

Answer the following in your notebook:

POL 10a: Introduction to Political Theory Spring 2017 Room: Golding 101 T, Th 2:00 3:20 PM

Two Pictures of the Global-justice Debate: A Reply to Tan*

Jus in Bello through the Lens of Individual Moral Responsibility: McMahan on Killing in War

Civil Disobedience and the Duty to Obey the Law: A Critical Assessment of Lefkowitz's View

The Justification of Justice as Fairness: A Two Stage Process

A Liberal Defence of Compulsory Voting : Some Reasons for Scepticism.

CHAPTER 1 PROLOGUE: VALUES AND PERSPECTIVES

Introduction to Political Thought

In search of moral leadership

Philosophers that Influenced American Government

NEWS XCHANGE EDITORIAL TERMS OF REFERENCE NEWS XCHANGE.

MODERN POLITICAL THOUGHT

Utilitarianism, Game Theory and the Social Contract

Is the Ideal of a Deliberative Democracy Coherent?

Introduction. Jonathan S. Davies and David L. Imbroscio State University of New York Press, Albany

PHIL 240 Introduction to Political Philosophy

Deep Democracy: Community, Diversity, Transformation. In recent years, scholars of American philosophy have done considerable

Morality and Foreign Policy

Proceduralism and Epistemic Value of Democracy

Election Campaigns and Democracy: A Review of James A. Gardner, What Are Campaigns For? The Role of Persuasion in Electoral Law and Politics

The Social Contract Class Syllabus

Phil 115, May 24, 2007 The threat of utilitarianism

LGST 226: Markets, Morality, and Capitalism Robert Hughes Fall 2016 Syllabus

LESSON ONE: THE DECLARATION OF INDEPENDENCE

The Empire of Civilization:

Directions: Read the documents in Part A and answer the questions after each document. Then, read the directions for Part B and write your essay.

Social Contract Theory

This response discusses the arguments and

Women, armed conflict and international law

STEVEN WALL. Associate Professor. Department of Philosophy, University of Connecticut (2008 to 2010)

IN THE MATTER OF THE POLICE ACT, R.S.B.C. 1996, C. 367, AS AMENDED

THE DECLARATION OF INDEPENDENCE

(Review) Globalizing Roman Culture: Unity, Diversity and Empire

Honors World History Harkness Seminars and Homework for Unit 4 Chapters 16 and and Documents

Adaptive Preferences and Women's Empowerment

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at

Review of Prudential Public Leadership: Promoting Ethics in Public Policy and Administration. By John Uhr. New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2015.

Legal Reasoning, the Rule of Law, and Legal Theory: Comments on Gerald Postema, Positivism and the Separation of the Realists from their Skepticism

Questions. Hobbes. Hobbes s view of human nature. Question. What justification is there for a state? Does the state have supreme authority?

Hobbes. Questions. What justification is there for a state? Does the state have supreme authority? What limits are there upon the state?

1. In the feudal period there was little idea of individuals having their own interests or

The character of public reason in Rawls s theory of justice

Freedom and the Limits of State Intervention. Suzie Kim Fall

Transcription:

Hobbes Today: Insights for the 21st Century, ed.s.a.lloyd(cambridge University Press: New York, 2013), 353 pp., 65.00, ISBN 978 1 10 700059 9. What does Hobbes offer that is useful to us today? The editor of this book, Sharon Lloyd, has recruited a superb array of scholars to answer this question. The book has sixteen chapters, by both Hobbes specialists and non-hobbes scholars. For reasons of space, I will focus on nine chapters: three which broadly succeed in getting contemporary insights from Hobbes (by Kinch Hoekstra, Jerry Gaus and Aaron James), three which fall a little short (by Eleanor Curran, Alice Ristroph and Maryam Qudrat), and three which are rather less effective (by Joshua Cohen, David Braybrooke and Neil McArthur). It can be harder than we think to enlighten modern issues with historical ideas, I suggest. I thus conclude by offering an appropriately Hobbesian solution to the danger of overstating Hobbes s contemporary relevance. The book does not start promisingly, with two chapters which do not tell us much about Hobbes today. Joshua Cohen s chapter, unfortunately entitled Getting Past Hobbes, implies that Rousseau is more useful for us than Hobbes. Cohen offers a thoughtful reading of Hobbes and a sophisticated normative argument, but this is more Rousseau Today than Hobbes Today. The late David Braybrooke s five-page chapter builds on the Hobbesian idea of mutual expectations of mutual forbearance. Supporters and members of one political party, argues Braybrooke, should treat those of another party with respect; otherwise they risk deadlock, even civil war. I m not convinced that disrespect is likely to cause civil war, though, or that greater partisan respect would have averted many past civil wars. Braybrooke s examples, his language of bipartisanship, and his reference to one party displac[ing] another peacefully, also imply an American conception of party politics quite different to the more consensual and cooperative style found to greater degrees in many other countries. I like Braybrooke s prescriptions but I do not find them especially Hobbesian or especially insightful for today. After two disappointing chapters, Eleanor Curran fires the book into life with a careful, incisive and unorthodox reading of Hobbes on rights which, she argues, sidesteps some difficulties in contemporary rights theories. This is exactly the right approach for the book. However, the particular details of Curran s argument do not convince me. She equates Hobbesian rights being grounded in liberty with Hobbesian rights being liberties (pp. 28, 31, 42 3), and likewise treats interest theories of rights as holding that rights are interests (p. 45). But for interest theorists, rights merely protect interests: interests ground rights only in the sense that certain interests justify particular rights under appropriate circumstances. 1 So too for Hobbes, surely, as Curran indeed had previously argued: Hobbes s justification for the individual holding such 1 See for example Joseph Raz, Ethics in the Public Domain: Essays in the Morality of Law and Politics (Oxford, revised edition, 1995), pp. 45 6, 48 55, 58 9. HISTORY OF POLITICAL THOUGHT. Vol. XXXVI. No. 2. Summer 2015

BOOK REVIEWS 391 rights is that it is in her vital interest to do so, because the protection of certain liberties are necessary for the possibility of peace and a commodious life. 2 Curran also imputes a liberty theory of rights to Rawls (p. 47), but like Hobbes, Rawls is defending a right to liberties, consistent with an interest theory of rights. Curran defends the contemporary relevance of Hobbes s theory of rights partly because she takes the interest theory of rights to imply that all interests must become rights (p. 46). But that is too extreme a form of the interest theory. Ultimately, I am not convinced that Curran s new interpretation of Hobbes is an advance on modern theories of rights. Kinch Hoekstra challenges the common view that Hobbes saw humans as naturally equal, amassing textual evidence that Hobbes recognized normatively relevant natural inequalities (pp. 77 82). Hobbes s insight for us, argues Hoekstra, is less the traditional view that we can destroy each other if we wish, and more that we must acknowledge one another as equals because we will otherwise be inclined to destroy one another (p. 77, 108 12). This strikes me as a plausible reading of Hobbes and a sensible contribution. A sensible contribution is not necessarily a significant contribution, though. And here Hoekstra faces something which is a problem for anyone trying to make Hobbes relevant today: Hobbes s prime concern was avoiding a return to a state of nature, but in many parts of the world we have other concerns. In terms of avoiding a return to a state of nature, I suspect we learn more from Rorty, who emphasizes acknowledging each other as humans (probably a more useful idea in such situations than acknowledging each other as equals) and learning to feel others pain a sentimentalist, Humean approach, not a Hobbesian one. 3 Jerry Gaus uses Hobbes and Locke to challenge public reason liberalism, the dominant liberal theory today. Gaus notes that contemporary political philosophy is deeply impressed by its reinvention of the wheel : Hobbes posed a strong challenge to a key form of public-reason liberalism, and Locke replied in two ways, one of which remains importantly undeveloped in contemporary liberalism. Gaus s position is perhaps more Lockean than Hobbesian, and his final suggestion Hobbes s concern that disagreement may be too deep for reasonable agreement certainly does not need to come from Hobbes. But Gaus does not pretend that the challenges and solutions are uniquely Hobbesian, and his chapter is a masterclass in using historical authors to probe important contemporary issues in a sophisticated way. Neil McArthur s chapter on Hobbes s economic ideas is promising but ultimately a touch disappointing. McArthur overlooks equity, increasingly 2 Eleanor Curran, Hobbes s Theory of Rights A Modern Interest Theory, The Journal of Ethics, 6 (1) (2002), pp. 63 86, at p. 86. 3 Richard Rorty, Truth and Progress (Cambridge, 1998), pp. 167 70, 177 85.

392 BOOK REVIEWS recognized as a central normative principle for Hobbes. 4 Equity, alongside treating others equally, may be a better Hobbesian justification of welfarestate taxes than McArthur s important, prudential reading of this aspect of Hobbes s economics; but either way, the debate between normative and prudential justifications of welfarist policies would make a useful addition to this short chapter. McArthur also claims that the central end of Hobbes s state is protecting people s private liberty within the context of a free market (p. 181). Here I disagree with McArthur. I do agree that Hobbes can be read as a rational choice theorist (pp. 178 9), but I have concerns about the way that McArthur, like many commentators, refers to rational deliberation (p. 179), which is an un-hobbesian term. 5 Alice Ristroph argues that Hobbesian punishment is imperfectly legitimate, since the person being punished retains the right to resist. I see no contradiction here, but I like Ristroph s view that today we punish too much. However, when she argues that we should avoid assuming that punishment is legitimate and focus more on seeing if punishment is justified rather than seeking justifications for punishment, I remain unconvinced that this is a Hobbesian insight, and I also worry that it may be a false dichotomy. I may be wrong here: to demonstrate this, Ristroph could give examples of authors who hold the latter view but not the former. Fleshing out the contemporary angle would help to justify the relevance of Hobbes today. Maryam Qudrat s chapter is refreshing: rather than straining to show Hobbes s relevance today, she argues against him, specifically his educational theory. Hobbesian indoctrination would not give enough citizens enough attachment to the state, she argues. Unless citizens can think critically about the regime, the regime will melt easily, since those who do not think critically cannot develop the principled commitments needed for stability. Here and elsewhere she uses the example of Afghanistan. The Taliban was doomed to fall because it did not attract a principled commitment to itself (p. 234). Indeed, Qudrat shows that the Taliban abused the Koran and other Islamic texts to justify its position in ways that actually weakened it in the end, highlighting the danger of giving the state the power to interpret religious texts. I m sympathetic to Qudrat s arguments and to her excellent use of a case study to test Hobbes s normative theory. I wonder if she could have drawn on modern research to back up her claims about education and attachment, and she does not address the existing literature on Hobbes on education, which 4 See e.g. Johan Olsthoorn, Hobbes s Account of Distributive Justice as Equity, British Journal for the History of Philosophy, 21 (1) (2013), pp. 13 33. 5 For a critique of this anachronism, see Adrian Blau, Reason, Deliberation, and the Passions, in The Oxford Handbook of Hobbes, ed. A.P. Martinich and Kinch Hoekstra (forthcoming), Section 6; and see Sections 4.1 and 4.5 for other criticisms of anachronistic misreadings of Hobbes on reason and deliberation. Currently available at http://www.oxfordhandbooks.com/view/10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199791941.001.0001/ oxfordhb-9780199791941-e-004

BOOK REVIEWS 393 sometimes treats Hobbes more broadly and more favourably than she does. 6 These small changes would have turned a strong chapter into a first-rate one. Aaron James argues that Hobbes raises fundamental questions for international politics. We can read the state of nature as an assurance game, where uncertainty about how others will act gives us absolute liberty rights to defend ourselves. James argues that we should not let the abstractions of contemporary ideal theory ignore the normatively relevant fact that epistemic considerations about uncertainty affect what agents have reason to do. For James, uncertainty is particularly important at the global level, and he thus argues for questions of global justice to be tackled at the international rather than global/cosmopolitan level. This is a valuable contribution to a contemporary debate, although as with Gaus, it may not be as Hobbesian as it looks: much of the work in the chapter is done with the idea of an assurance game, which Hobbes may have been the first to use but which is certainly not unique to him, and much of the rest of the work is done by the idea of a global state of nature, an idea which needs careful handling. 7 But I don t think this affects the broader thrust of James s argument. The book s index is more quarter-hearted than half-hearted. Even the introduction is sketchy: the summaries of the book s chapters start in the fourth paragraph. More problematic is the lack of a concluding chapter summarizing those areas where Hobbes is relevant today and, importantly, where he is not. Such a concluding chapter would have made up for the overly strong claims of several chapters, and of Lloyd s introduction in particular, where she declares that the answer to whether Hobbes has anything to say to us today is a resounding Yes! (p. xi). I don t think this is borne out, and in some chapters the Yes! is more confounding than resounding. In every chapter discussed above, a bit or a lot more work is needed to show that insights are actually Hobbes s or that these insights are useful today. Demonstrating contemporary relevance in historical texts is often harder than it seems. An appropriately Hobbesian strategy would thus have been to inform chapterwriters that an impartial arbitrator would be commenting even-handedly on claims about contemporary relevance, at the conference out of which this book grew, and in the book s final chapter. Such an experience would not be very pleasant, and one would want to avoid a situation where the book s own editor demolishes one of the chapters, 8 but such an approach would have put the fear of a mortal god into chapter-writers and might have encouraged more expounding and less resounding. The result would have been a more nuanced 6 For example, Teresa Bejan, Teaching the Leviathan: Thomas Hobbes on Education, Oxford Review of Education, 36 (5) (2010), pp. 607 26. 7 See Noel Malcolm, Aspects of Hobbes (Oxford, 2002), pp. 437 40. 8 As with Geoffrey Evans, Class and Vote: Disrupting the Orthodoxy, in The End of Class Politics? Class Voting in Comparative Context, ed. Geoffrey Evans (Oxford, 1999), pp. 323 34, at pp. 324 6.

394 BOOK REVIEWS analysis of what is and is not of contemporary relevance in Hobbes, and would have been a fitting review and conclusion to the already high-class and often top-class scholarship in this book. Instead, we have a book which will certainly interest Hobbes scholars but which still leaves question-marks about the importance of Hobbes today. Adrian Blau KING S COLLEGE LONDON