LOGROLLING. Nicholas R. Miller Department of Political Science University of Maryland Baltimore County Baltimore, Maryland

Similar documents
Agendas and Strategic Voting

Sincere versus sophisticated voting when legislators vote sequentially

Sincere Versus Sophisticated Voting When Legislators Vote Sequentially

FAIR REPUTATIONS: A GAME-THEORETIC MECHANISM FOR E-COMMERCE DISPUTES*

INTERNATIONAL ECONOMICS, FINANCE AND TRADE Vol. II - Strategic Interaction, Trade Policy, and National Welfare - Bharati Basu

CHAPTER 9 Conclusions: Political Equality and the Beauty of Cycling

AGENDAS AND SINCERITY: A SECOND RESPONSE TO SCHWARTZ

Reading vs. Seeing. Federal and state government are often looked at as separate entities but upon

James M. Buchanan The Limits of Market Efficiency

Do Voters Have a Duty to Promote the Common Good? A Comment on Brennan s The Ethics of Voting

Agendas and sincerity: a second response to Schwartz

Are Second-Best Tariffs Good Enough?

The Economic Effects of Judicial Selection Dr. John A. Dove Faulkner Lecture Outline

Experimental economics and public choice

The origins of public finance, as a field of study though most certainly not

Political Science 200A Week 8. Social Dilemmas

Interests, Interactions, and Institutions. Interests: Actors and Preferences. Interests: Actors and Preferences. Interests: Actors and Preferences

HANDBOOK OF SOCIAL CHOICE AND VOTING Jac C. Heckelman and Nicholas R. Miller, editors.

Transparency, Accountability and Citizen s Engagement

Public Choice. Peter T. Calcagno. College of Charleston. Rhonda Free, ed. (Sage Publishers, 2010) Revised Draft 7/7/2009.

Magruder s American Government

1 Introduction. Cambridge University Press International Institutions and National Policies Xinyuan Dai Excerpt More information

1100 Ethics July 2016

The Provision of Public Goods Under Alternative. Electoral Incentives

Agricultural Policy Analysis: Discussion

P1: aaa SJNW N stylea.cls (2005/11/30 v1.0 LaTeX Springer document class) January 2, :37

Chapter 9: Social Choice: The Impossible Dream Lesson Plan

How much benevolence is benevolent enough?

Chapter 14. The Causes and Effects of Rational Abstention

An example of public goods

Voter Sovereignty and Election Outcomes

The Analytics of the Wage Effect of Immigration. George J. Borjas Harvard University September 2009

Self-Organization and Cooperation in Social Systems

Politics and Public Policy

SOURCES OF GOVERNMENTAL FAILURE AND IMPERFECT INFORMATION AS POLITICAL FAILURE

Magruder s American Government

The Integer Arithmetic of Legislative Dynamics

Magruder s American Government

6. Problems and dangers of democracy. By Claudio Foliti

Vermont Legislative Research Shop

Political Sophistication and Third-Party Voting in Recent Presidential Elections

Political Sophistication and Third-Party Voting in Recent Presidential Elections

University of North Dakota. American Government I

GAME THEORY. Analysis of Conflict ROGER B. MYERSON. HARVARD UNIVERSITY PRESS Cambridge, Massachusetts London, England

CAN FAIR VOTING SYSTEMS REALLY MAKE A DIFFERENCE?

1. Free trade refers to a situation where a government does not attempt to influence through quotas

CALIFORNIA INSTITUTE OF TECHNOLOGY SOCIAL SCIENCE WORKING PAPER 142 DIVISION OF THE HUMANITIES AND SOCIAL SCIENCES PASADENA. CALIFORNIA /'/'

CHAPTER 19 MARKET SYSTEMS AND NORMATIVE CLAIMS Microeconomics in Context (Goodwin, et al.), 2 nd Edition

Global overview of women s political participation and implementation of the quota system

The Provision of Public Goods, and the Matter of the Revelation of True Preferences: Two Views

Arguments for and against electoral system change in Ireland

Testing Political Economy Models of Reform in the Laboratory

Notes for Session 7 Basic Voting Theory and Arrow s Theorem

On Original Appropriation. Peter Vallentyne, University of Missouri-Columbia

Part 1 True or False, and explain. You will earn 3 points for correctly identifying true or false, and 7 points for the explanation.

Gordon Tullock and the Demand-Revealing Process

Social Science and History: How Predictable is Political Behavior?

Political Science 10: Introduction to American Politics Week 10

Homework 4 solutions

Problems with Group Decision Making

Natural Resource Regimes: A Behavioral Institutions Approach

A NOTE ON THE THEORY OF SOCIAL CHOICE

Random tie-breaking in STV

Non-global social contracts: A note on inefficient social institutions*

Preview. Chapter 9. The Cases for Free Trade. The Cases for Free Trade (cont.) The Political Economy of Trade Policy

CARLETON ECONOMIC PAPERS

and Collective Goods Princeton: Princeton University Press, Pp xvii, 161 $6.00

Persuasion in Politics

Problems with Group Decision Making

Expressive voting and government redistribution: Testing Tullock s charity of the uncharitable

The World Trade Organization and the future of multilateralism Note Key principles behind GATT general principle rules based not results based

Institutionalization: New Concepts and New Methods. Randolph Stevenson--- Rice University. Keith E. Hamm---Rice University

International Business Economics

Prof. Bryan Caplan Econ 812

What is Fairness? Allan Drazen Sandridge Lecture Virginia Association of Economists March 16, 2017

Lecture 18 Sociology 621 November 14, 2011 Class Struggle and Class Compromise

School of Economics Shandong University Jinan, China Pr JOSSELIN March 2010

Example 8.2 The Economics of Terrorism: Externalities and Strategic Interaction

Brexit Referendum: An Incomplete Verdict

International Cooperation, Parties and. Ideology - Very preliminary and incomplete

Prof. Bryan Caplan Econ 854

Postscript: Subjective Utilitarianism

The Economics of GATT: Making Economic Sense out of a Mercantilist Institution. Robert W. Staiger The University of Wisconsin

Dresden Discussion Paper Series in Economics

THE CONSTITUTIONALIZATION OF MONEY James M. Buchanan

As you may have heard, there has been some discussion about possibly changing Canada's electoral system. We want to ask people their views on this.

MATH4999 Capstone Projects in Mathematics and Economics Topic 3 Voting methods and social choice theory

Elections and referendums

Institutions, Institutional Change and Economic Performance by Douglass C. North Cambridge University Press, 1990

Agenda trees and sincere voting: a response to Schwartz

PS 124A Midterm, Fall 2013

In Defense of Majoritarianism

Political Campaign. Volunteers in a get-out-the-vote campaign in Portland, Oregon, urge people to vote during the 2004 presidential

The Entitlement Theory 1 Robert Nozick

The Future of Public Choice

GE172 State and Local Government [Onsite]

Transitions to Democracy

THE FUTURE OF ANALYTICAL POLITICS...

POLITICAL POWER AND ENDOGENOUS POLICY FORMATION OUTLINE

Political Selection and Persistence of Bad Governments

Transcription:

LOGROLLING Nicholas R. Miller Department of Political Science University of Maryland Baltimore County Baltimore, Maryland 21250 May 20, 1999 An entry in The Encyclopedia of Democratic Thought (Routledge) edited by Paul Barry Clarke and Joe Foweraker

Logrolling page 2 LOGROLLING Logrolling refers to the exchange of political support, particularly in the legislative process. The term arose, with disreputable connotations, within the discourse of (extremely) practical American politics. In recent decades the term has entered the vocabulary of academic political science, and some political theorists have argued that logrolling can promote the efficient and equitable satisfaction of political interests and values. The term logrolling evidently arose on the early American frontier. When trees were cut to clear land for farming and to build log houses, heavy logs had to be rolled out of clearings and to building sites a task beyond the strength of a single person or family. Hence reciprocity arose among neighbors: I ll help roll your logs if you ll help roll mine. By 1809, the term was applied by commentators and editorialists to characterize but also to condemn as immoral assorted instances of political trading in the early American republic. (See the entries in Safire, 1993, and Sperber and Trittschuh, 1962.) The negative connotations associated with logrolling might seem puzzling. After all, the frontier practice after which it is named was surely constructive and praiseworthy. And logrolling may appear to be analogous to voluntary economic exchange, the desirability of which is supported by a massive edifice of theory and evidence. Indeed, the earliest use of the term in academic social science did not condemn it. While conceding that it is a term of opprobrium, Arthur Bentley asserted that log-rolling, or give and take, appears as the very nature of the [legislative] process. It is compromise... in the practical form with which every legislator who gets results through government is acquainted. It is trading. It is the adjustment of interests. (1908, pp. 370-378.) By the late 1950s and early 1960s, some economists (notably James Buchanan and Gordon Tullock, 1962) and political scientists drew an explicit analogy between economic and political exchange, from which they often drew positive normative implications as well. Since then, the phenomenon of logrolling has received considerable attention in political science and political theory. Focus on the welfare implications of logrolling has raised a number of analytical problems. These include: the prevalence of logrolling as a function of the nature of decision rules, electoral systems, and party systems; the extent to which logrolling takes account of preference intensities ; whether logrolling avoids or generates the cyclical majority problem; and whether logrolling produces stable and predictable outcomes. Let us consider some of these issues by means of stylized examples. First, we have the case of ordinary economic exchange. Suppose A grows nothing but apples and B nothing but oranges, so A controls the allocation of apples between them and B the allocation of oranges. Since each actor prefers more fruit to less, neither would unilaterally transfer fruit to the other. But if A and B each prefers a mixed diet, they can both benefit by trading fruit. We may note three points. First, the fact of mutually beneficial trade depends on finer aspects of the actors preferences (their marginal rates of substitution ) that are otherwise irrelevant. Second, since the trade is in private goods, no one else

Logrolling page 3 is affected and mutually advantageous trade unambiguously increases social welfare. Third, if (say) apples come in season before oranges, B would have to be able to make a credible promise (e.g., by means of an enforceable contract) to A for the gains from trade to be realized. Second, let us consider political exchange in a non-legislative (e.g., bureaucratic) context. Suppose that A and B are political actors who unilaterally control issues X and Y respectively. Each issue can be resolved in one of two ways: x 1, x 2 and y 1, y 2 respectively. A prefers x 1 to x 2 and y 2 to y 1, while B has the opposite preference on each issue. Thus if A and B act unilaterally, the outcome is (x 1, y 1 ). But if both prefer (x 2, y 2 ) to (x 1, y 1 ), they can benefit from a logrolling agreement such that each trades his preference on the issue he controls (but cares less about) for his preference on the issue he doesn t control (but cares more about). We can draw the following conclusions. First, while logrolling (like economic exchange) depends on finer preference information, it does not depend on interpersonal comparison of preference intensities. Second, a logrolling agreement is unambiguously welfare increasing if no other actors are affected by issues X and Y or if A and B are perfect representative agents of the affected groups. But this proviso is unlikely to be realized in a political context, so the welfare implications are uncertain. Third, non-legislative logrolling agreements cannot be upset by other actors. Next, let us suppose that A and B are legislators, each endowed with a single vote on each of two legislative issues X and Y, on which their preferences are the same as those specified above. Pork-barrel (or distributive ) politics, which arises when the central government finances the construction of public works projects whose benefits are received locally, may give rise to such preferences, especially if legislators are elected from small districts that approximate the catchment area for benefits. Suppose further that A and B are each in the minority with respect to the issue they care more about (e.g., their own projects), but that the support of the other legislator would convert each minority into a majority. Then A and B can engage in a logroll (or vote trade ), each agreeing to vote contrary to his preference on the issue he cares less about, thereby switching the legislative outcome from (x 1, y 1 ) to (x 2, y 2 ) in the manner they both prefer. But in legislative context, the actors are trading only votes on issues not unilateral control so the preferences and actions of other legislators are relevant. Even if A and B are perfect representative agents of their constituents, the (potential) switch from (x 1, y 1 ) to (x 2, y 2 ) clearly affects other legislators and their constituents, and other legislators with opposite preferences between (x 1, y 1 ) and (x 2, y 2 ) may be in position to counter-logroll, neutralizing the potential effect of the vote trade between A and B. However, if the coalition of A and B constitutes a majority of the legislature (i.e., if the body has only three members or if A and B are sufficiently large blocs with identical relevant preferences), their logrolling agreement cannot be upset by the residual minority. The term logrolling is often reserved to describe the formation of such a majority-sized coalition of minorities (of course, a coalition encompassing many issues may be needed), while vote trading is applied to the kind of pairwise trading described above.

Logrolling page 4 While such majoritarian logrolling cannot be upset by the minority outside the supporting coalition, excluded legislators can try to break apart the logrolling coalition by offering proposals to knock out one or a few projects. Any such proposal advantages everyone except the few beneficiaries, which implies that logrolling agreements are intrinsically unstable. (This also implies that logrolling is feasible only in the presence of cyclical majority preference over the possible outcomes a point discovered independently and more or simultaneously by many different researchers in the early 1970s; see Miller, 1977, for a general review.) It is generally believed that this kind of explicit logrolling is especially prevalent and visible in the U.S. Congress prevalent because of its single-member district system and because a checks and balances structure requires broad-based coalitions and visible because weak party discipline allows members to cut their own deals. But implicit logrolling engineered by political entrepreneurs attempting to assemble winning coalitions is undoubtedly even more widespread, occurring in the construction of legislative programs and party platforms or manifestos, within one-party cabinets, and in inter-party negotiations leading to coalition governments. Finally, let us reconsider the welfare implications of legislative logrolling, using the example of pork-barrel politics. We have two possibilities: (i) the proposed projects are (on average) efficient, i.e., their benefits exceed their costs; or (ii) they are (on average) inefficient, i.e., their costs exceed their benefits. The virtue of logrolling is that even efficient projects cannot command anything like majority support as stand-alone proposals, so logrolling (of some type) is necessary to assemble the support needed to authorize them. The defect of logrolling is that even somewhat inefficient projects can be packaged together to secure majority support. Indeed, if a logrolling coalition is built up sequentially, something like an n-person Prisoner s Dilemma may result: at every stage, each legislator has a strong incentive to see his own project included in the logrolling agreement but, as more other projects are included as well, the net advantage to each member of the expanding logrolling coalition diminishes and may become negative, with the result the everyone would be better off if the logrolling process had never started. (This is essentially the story told by E. E. Schattschneider, 1935, concerning the Smoot-Hawley Tariff passed by the U.S. Congress in 1930, and this scenario is explored formally by Riker and Brams, 1973.) Thus we cannot make a conclusive normative judgment concerning logrolling. But the widespread condemnation of the practice appears to be based on largely unexamined presuppositions rather than analysis. Most students of politics are probably inclined to endorse Bentley s assessment and to be skeptical of proposals (e.g., to use new technologies to set up a referendum democracy) that would wholly preclude logrolling.

Logrolling page 5 References Bentley, Arthur (1908) The Process of Government, Chicago: University of Chicago Press Buchanan, J. M., and Tullock, G. (1962) The Calculus of Consent The Logical Foundations of Constitutional Democracy, Ann Arbor: University Of Michigan Press Miller, N. R. (1977) Logrolling, Vote Trading, and the Paradox of Voting: A Game-Theoretical Overview, Public Choice, 30: 52-75 Riker, W. H., and Brams, S. J. (1973) The Paradox of Vote Trading, American Political Science Review, 62, 4: 1235-47 Safire, W. (1993) Safire s New Political Dictionary, New York: Random House Schattschneider, E. E. (1935 ) Politics, Pressures and the Tariff, Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice- Hall Sperber, H., and Trittschuh, T. (1962) American Political Terms: An Historical Dictionary, Detroit: Wayne State University Press