Social Responsibility of Business by Milton Friedman New York Times Magazine, 13 September 1970, pp. 33, Milton Friedman

Similar documents
From The Collected Works of Milton Friedman, compiled and edited by Robert Leeson and Charles G. Palm.

From The Collected Works of Milton Friedman, compiled and edited by Robert Leeson and Charles G. Palm.

On the Irrelevance of Formal General Equilibrium Analysis

Why Does Inequality Matter? T. M. Scanlon. Chapter 8: Unequal Outcomes. It is well known that there has been an enormous increase in inequality in the

RESPONSE TO JAMES GORDLEY'S "GOOD FAITH IN CONTRACT LAW: The Problem of Profit Maximization"

Laissez-Faire vs. Socialism Who is responsible?

AMY GUTMANN: THE CONSTRUCTIVE POTENTIAL OF COMMUNITARIAN VALUES DOES GUTMANN SUCCEED IN SHOWING THE CONSTRUCTIVE POTENTIAL OF COMMUNITARIAN VALUES?

13 Arguments for Liberal Capitalism in 13 Minutes

From The Collected Works of Milton Friedman, compiled and edited by Robert Leeson and Charles G. Palm.

* Economies and Values

Public Schools: Make Them Private by Milton Friedman (1995)

Subverting the Orthodoxy

Constitutionalism and Rule of Law in the Republic of Korea

PROTOCOL 1: MOVING HUMANITARIAN LAW BACKWARDS

This book has a simple and straightforward message. The

Towards Sustainable Economy and Society Under Current Globalization Trends and Within Planetary Boundaries: A Tribute to Hirofumi Uzawa

The Justification of Justice as Fairness: A Two Stage Process

COMPARATIVE ECONOMIC SYSTEMS: PAST, PRESENT, AND FUTURE BEFORE YOU BEGIN

ANARCHISM: What it is, and what it ain t...

MGT610 2 nd Quiz solved by Masoodkhan before midterm spring 2012

The Determinacy of Republican Policy: A Reply to McMahon

Preservation Policy: A Challenging Task Both on a National and Local Level 1

The dictatorship of EU Political Commissioners: State communism, here we come

From The Collected Works of Milton Friedman, compiled and edited by Robert Leeson and Charles G. Palm.

Synthesizing Rights and Utility: John Stuart Mill ( )

Chapter 3:4: Safety Nets

IMMIGRATION, ASYLUM AND NATIONALITY BILL HL BILL 43 PART TWO EMPLOYMENT FOR GRAND COMMITTEE 11 JANUARY

Study Questions for George Reisman's Capitalism: A Treatise on Economics

THE HEALTH AGENDA FOR THE FUTURE

The Economics of Milton Friedman

Anti Bribery and Corruption Policy. Regulatory Compliance Department. Compliance and Legal Management Group

A Few Contributions of Economic Theory to Social Welfare Policy Analysis

United Nations dialogue with Member States on rule of law at the international level

S.L. Hurley, Justice, Luck and Knowledge, (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2003), 341 pages. ISBN: (hbk.).

From The Collected Works of Milton Friedman, compiled and edited by Robert Leeson and Charles G. Palm.

NEW YORK STATE ORNITHOLOGICAL ASSOCIATION, INC. A NEW YORK STATE NOT-FOR-PROFIT CORPORATION

Chapter - II. Origin and Development of Liability Of Corporations for. Environment Pollution

ABA Formal Op. 334 Page 1 ABA Comm. on Ethics and Professional Responsibility, Formal Op American Bar Association

The Gold Standard and

NORTH SLOPE BOROUGH ORDINANCE SERIAL NO

A COMMENTARY ON PUBLIC FUNDS OR PUBLICLY FUNDED BENEFITS AND THE REGULATION OF JUDICIAL CAMPAIGNS

APPRAISAL OF THE FAR EAST AND LATIN AMERICAN TEAM REPORTS IN THE WORLD FOREIGN TRADE SETTING

gave stock to influential politicians. And the Whiskey Ring in the Grant administration united Republicans officials, tax collectors, and whiskey

Advocating for Canadians and Charities

PHILOSOPHY OF ECONOMICS & POLITICS

Comments on Justin Weinberg s Is Government Supererogation Possible? Public Reason Political Philosophy Symposium Friday October 17, 2008

Robert s Rules of Order. (Newly Revised) s.com. Summary of Conference Procedures. Why Use Robert s Rules?

POSTGRADUTAE PROGRAM: BUSINESS ETHICS AND SOCIAL ACCOUNTING, SOME GENERAL CONSIDERATIONS TO INTEGRATE THE PAPERS AND THE SLIDES OF THE COURSE

From The Collected Works of Milton Friedman, compiled and edited by Robert Leeson and Charles G. Palm.

THE REAL RIGHT TO MEDICAL CARE VERSUS SOCIALIZED MEDICINE. George Reisman. A Publication of

DRAFT UNITED NATIONS CODE OF CONDUCT ON TRANSNATIONAL CORPORATIONS * [1983 version]

Who will speak, and who will listen? Comments on Burawoy and public sociology 1

Topic 1: Moral Reasoning and ethical theory

Short Guide 04. Edward Jacobs, Judge of the Upper Tribunal. The ABC of Effective Procedural Applications The Basics of Tribunal Representation

SOCIAL WELFARE IN THE PUBLIC-PRIVATE STATE

Politics between Philosophy and Democracy

ADDRESS BY GATT DIRECTOR-GENERAL TO UNCTAD VIII IN CARTAGENA, COLOMBIA

The origins of public finance, as a field of study though most certainly not

The Social Market Economy in Germany and in Europe - Principles and Perspectives

Self-interest, deregulation and trust

The Entitlement Theory 1 Robert Nozick

Plato s Concept of Justice: Prepared by, Mr. Thomas G.M., Associate Professor, Pompei College Aikala DK

Introduction. Is It Time to Abolish the Minimum Wage? Nate Moroney, Josh Carlson, Andreas Syz. April 5, 2004

The Enlightenment. The Age of Reason

Defining political participation: how to pinpoint an elusive target? 2014 Marc Hooghe

ANNEX DRAFT OVERARCHING FRAMEWORK OF ENGAGEMENT WITH NON-STATE ACTORS

When Jobs Require Unjust Acts: Resolving the Conflict between Role Obligations and Common Morality

Responsible Victims and (Partly) Justified Offenders

BB315014S Sustainable Management Futures 27 MARCH 2012

Do we have a strong case for open borders?

POLITICAL AUTHORITY AND PERFECTIONISM: A RESPONSE TO QUONG

Adam Smith International Human Trafficking and Modern Slavery Policy

CODE OF ETHICS FOR PARLIAMENTARIANS INCLUDING MINISTERS

Corporate Fund-Raising Creating Strategic Partnerships with Donors. Denise Couyoumdjian General Manager Libertad y Desarrollo

MCOM 301: Media Laws & Ethics

11/7/2011. Section 1: Answering the Three Economic Questions. Section 2: The Free Market

B 3. THE PROPER ECONOMIC ROLES OF GOVERNMENT

SOCI 423: THEORIES OF SOCIAL DEVELOPMENT

Session 20 Gerald Dworkin s Paternalism

The Justification of Human Rights

Review of Christian List and Philip Pettit s Group agency: the possibility, design, and status of corporate agents

Monetary Theory and Central Banking By Allan H. Meltzer * Carnegie Mellon University and The American Enterprise Institute

Transparency, Accountability and Citizen s Engagement

Rawls versus the Anarchist: Justice and Legitimacy

that keeps judges' hands off the economic system.

Volume 8. Occupation and the Emergence of Two States, Political Principles of the Social Democratic Party (May 1946)

24.03: Good Food 3/13/17. Justice and Food Production

Journal of Conflict Transformation & Security

John Stuart Mill, Principles of Political Economy, 7 th edition (1870)

Premise. The social mission and objectives

Meeting Plato s challenge?

Adam Harris. Why We Should Vote: Voting Abstention and African-Americans. Alabama A&M University. Phone: (540)

Charles I Plosser: A progress report on our monetary policy framework

COMPARATIVE ADVANTAGE

ECONOMIC POLICYMAKING CHAPTER 17, Government in America

What Is Contemporary Critique Of Biopolitics?

a state of change Not for profit newsletter February 2014 Introduction In this issue Each year brings new challenges to non-profit organizations,

Running head: THE AMERICAN DREAM. The American Dream: Dead, Alive, or on Hold? Brandon King University of Cincinnati

preserving individual freedom is government s primary responsibility, even if it prevents government from achieving some other noble goal?

Visegrad Youth. Comparative review of the situation of young people in the V4 countries

Transcription:

Social Responsibility of Business by Milton Friedman New York Times Magazine, 13 September 1970, pp. 33, 122-126 Milton Friedman When I hear businessmen speak eloquently about the social responsibilities of business in a free-enterprise system, I am reminded of the wonderful line about the Frenchman who discovered at the age of 70 that he had been speaking prose all his life. The businessmen believe that they are defending free enterprise when they declaim that business is not concerned merely with profit but also with promoting desirable social ends; that business has a social conscience and takes seriously its responsibilities for providing employment, eliminating discrimination, avoiding pollution and whatever else may be the catchwords of the contemporary crop of reformers. In fact they are or would be if they or anyone else took them seriously preaching pure and unadulterated socialism. Businessmen who talk this way are unwitting puppets of the intellectual forces that have been undermining the basis of a free society these past decades. The discussions of the social responsibilities of business are notable for their analytical looseness and lack of rigor. What does it mean to say that business has responsibilities? Only people can have responsibilities. A corporation is an artificial person and in this sense may have artificial responsibilities, but business as a whole cannot be said to have responsibilities, even in this vague sense. The first step toward clarity to examining the doctrine of the social responsibility of business is to ask precisely what it implies for whom. Presumably, the individuals who are to be responsible are businessmen, which means individual proprietors or corporate executives. Most of the discussion of social responsibility is directed at corporations, so in what follows I shall mostly neglect the individual proprietors and speak of corporate executives. In a free-enterprise, private-property system, a corporate executive is an employee of the owners of the business. He has direct responsibility to his employers. That responsibility is to conduct the business in accordance with their desires, which generally will be to make as much money as possible while conforming to the basic rules of the society, both those embodied in law and those embodied in ethical custom. Of course, in some cases his employers may have a different objective. A group of persons might establish a corporation for an eleemosynary purpose for example, a hospital or a school. The manager of such a corporation will not have money profit as his objectives but the rendering of certain services. In either case, the key point is that, in his capacity as a corporate executive, the manager is the agent of the individuals who own the corporation or establish the eleemosynary institution, and his primary responsibility is to them. Needless to say, this does not mean that it is easy to judge how well he is performing his task. But at least the criterion of performance is straightforward, and the persons among whom a voluntary contractual arrangement exists are clearly defined. 1

Of course, the corporate executive is also a person in his own right. As a person, he may have many other responsibilities that he recognizes or assumes voluntary to his family, his conscience, his feelings of charity, his church, his clubs, his city, his country. He may feel impelled by these responsibilities to devote part of his income to causes he regards as worthy, to refuse to work for particular corporations, even to leave his job, for example, to join his country s armed forces. If we wish, we may refer to some of these responsibilities as social responsibilities. But in these respects he is acting as a principal, not an agent; he is spending his own money or time or energy, not the money of his employers or the time or energy he has contracted to devote to their purposes. If these are social responsibilities, they are the social responsibilities of individuals, not of business. What does it mean to say that the corporate executive has a social responsibility in his capacity as businessman? If this statement is not pure rhetoric, it must mean that he is to act in some way that is not in the interest of his employers. For example, that he is to refrain from increasing the price of the product in order to contribute to the social objective of preventing inflation, even though a price increase would be in the best interests of the corporation. Or that he is to make expenditures on reducing pollution beyond the amount that is in the best interests of the corporation or that is required by law in order to contribute to the social objective of improving the environment. Or that, at the expense of corporate profits, he is to hire hardcore unemployed instead of better qualified available workmen to contribute to the social objective of reducing poverty. In each of these cases, the corporate executive would be spending someone else s money for a general social interest. Insofar as his actions in accord with his social responsibility reduce returns to stockholders, he is spending their money. Insofar as his actions raise the price to customers, he is spending customers money. Insofar as his actions lower the wages of some employees, he is spending their money. The stockholders or the customers or the employees could separately spend their own money on the particular action if they wished to do so. The executive is exercising a distinct social responsibility, rather than serving as an agent of the stockholders or the customers or the employees, only if he spends the money in a different way than they would have spent it. But if he does this, he is in effect imposing taxes, on the one hand, and deciding how the tax proceeds shall be spent, on the other. This process raises political questions on two levels: principle and consequences. On the level of political principle, the imposition of taxes and the expenditure of tax proceeds are governmental functions. We have established elaborate constitutional, parliamentary and judicial provisions to control these functions, to assure that taxes are imposed so far as possible in accordance with the preferences and desires of the public after all, taxation without representation was one of the battle cries of the American Revolution. We have a system of checks and balances to separate the legislative function of imposing taxes and enacting expenditures from the executive function of collecting taxes and administering expenditure programs and from the judicial function of mediating disputes and interpreting the law. 2

Here the businessman self-selected or appointed directly or indirectly by stockholders is to be simultaneously legislator, executive and jurist. He is to decide whom to tax by how much and for what purpose, and he is to spend the proceeds all this guided only by general exhortations from on high to restrain inflation, improve the environment, fight poverty and so on and on. The whole justification for permitting the corporate executive to be selected by the stockholders is that the executive is an agent serving the interests of his principal. This justification disappears when the corporate executive imposes taxes and spends the proceeds for social purposes. He becomes in effect a public employee, a civil servant, even though he remains in name an employee of a private enterprise. On grounds of political principle, it is intolerable that such civil servants insofar as their actions in the name of social responsibility are real and not just window dressing should be selected as they are now. If they are to be civil servants, then they must be elected through a political process. If they are to impose taxes and make expenditures to foster social objectives, then political machinery must be set up to make the assessment of taxes and to determine through a political process the objectives to be served. This is the basic reason why the doctrine of social responsibility involves the acceptance of the socialist view that political mechanisms, not market mechanisms, are the appropriate way to determine the allocation of scarce resources to alternative uses. On the grounds of consequences, can the corporate executive in fact discharge his alleged social responsibilities? On the one hand, suppose he could get away with spending the stockholders or customers or employees money. How is he to know how to spend it? He is told that he must contribute to fighting inflation. How is he to know what action of his will contribute to that end? He is presumably an expert in running his company in producing a product or selling it or financing it. But nothing about his selection makes him an expert on inflation. Will his holding down the price of his product reduce inflationary pressure? Or, by leaving more spending power in the hands of his customers, simply divert it elsewhere? Or, by forcing him to produce less because of the lower price, will it simply contribute to shortages? Even if he could answer these questions, how much cost is he justified in imposing on his stockholders, customers, and employees for this social purpose? What is his appropriate share and what is the appropriate share of others? And, whether he wants to or not, can he get away with spending his stockholders, customers or employees money? Will not the stockholders fire him? (Either the present ones or those who take over when his actions in the name of social responsibility have reduced the corporation s profits and the price of its stock.) His customers and his employees can desert him for other producers and employers less scrupulous in exercising their social responsibilities. This facet of social responsibility doctrine is brought into sharp relief when the doctrine is used to justify wage restraint by trade unions. The conflict of interest is naked and clear when union officials are asked to subordinate the interest of their members to some more general purpose. If union officials try to enforce wage restraint, the consequence is likely to be wildcat strikes, rank-and-file revolts and the emergence of strong competitors for their jobs. We thus have the ironic phenomenon that union leaders at least in the U.S. have objected to Government interference with the market far more consistently and courageously than have business leaders. 3

The difficulty of exercising social responsibility illustrates, of course, the great virtue of private competitive enterprise it forces people to be responsible for their own actions and makes it difficult for them to exploit other people for either selfish or unselfish purposes. They can do good but only at their own expense. Many a reader who has followed the argument this far may be tempted to remonstrate that it is all well and good to speak of Government s having the responsibility to impose taxes and determine expenditures for such social purposes as controlling pollution or training the hardcore unemployed, but that the problems are too urgent to wait on the slow course of political processes, that the exercise of social responsibility by businessmen is a quicker and surer way to solve pressing current problems. Aside from the question of fact I share Adam Smith s skepticism about the benefits that can be expected from those who affect to trade for the public good this argument must be rejected on grounds of principle. What it amounts to is an assertion that those who favor the taxes and expenditures in question have failed to persuade a majority of their fellow citizens to be of like mind and that they are seeking to attain by undemocratic procedures what they cannot attain by democratic procedures. In a free society it is hard for evil people to do evil, especially since one man s good is another s evil. I have, for simplicity, concentrated on the special case of the corporate executive, except only for the brief digression on trade unions. But precisely the same argument applies to the newer phenomenon of calling upon stockholders to require corporations to exercise social responsibility (the recent G.M. crusade for example). In most of these cases, what is in effect involved is some stockholders trying to get other stockholders (or customers or employees) to contribute against their will to social causes favored by the activists. Insofar as they succeed, they are again imposing taxes and spending the proceeds. The situation of the individual proprietor is somewhat different. If he acts to reduce the returns of his enterprise in order to exercise his social responsibility, he is spending his own money, not someone else s. If he wishes to spend his money on such purposes, that is his right, and I cannot see that there is any objection to his doing so. In the process, he, too, may impose costs on employees and customers. However, because he is far less likely than a large corporation or union to have monopolistic power, any such side effects will tend to be minor. Of course, in practice the doctrine of social responsibility is frequently a cloak for actions that are justified on other grounds rather than a reason for those actions. To illustrate, it may well be in the long-run interest of a corporation that is a major employer in a small community to devote resources to providing amenities to that community or to improving its government. That may make it easier to attract desirable employees, it may reduce the wage bill or lessen losses from pilferage and sabotage or have other worthwhile effects. Or it may be that, given the laws about the deductibility of corporate charitable contributions, the stockholders can contribute more to charities they favor by having the corporation make the gift than by doing it themselves, since they can in that way contribute an amount that would otherwise have been paid as corporate taxes. 4

In each of these and many similar cases, there is a strong temptation to rationalize these actions as an exercise of social responsibility. In the present climate of opinion, with its widespread aversion to capitalism, profits, and soulless corporation and so on, this is one way for a corporation to generate goodwill as a by-product of expenditures that are entirely justified in its own self-interest. It would be inconsistent of me to call on corporate executives to refrain from this hypocritical window-dressing because it harms the foundations of a free society. That would be to call on them to exercise a social responsibility! If our institutions, and the attitudes of the public make it in their self-interest to cloak their actions in this way, I cannot summon much indignation to denounce them. At the same time, I can express admiration for those individual proprietors or owners of closely held corporations or stockholders of more broadly held corporations who disdain such tactics as approaching fraud. Whether blameworthy or not, the use of the cloak of social responsibility, and the nonsense spoken in its name by influential and prestigious businessmen, does clearly harm the foundations of a free society. I have been impressed time and again by the schizophrenic character of many businessmen. They are capable of being extremely far-sighted and clearheaded in matters that are internal to their businesses. They are incredibly short-sighted and muddle-headed in matters that are outside their businesses but affect the possible survival of business in general. This shortsightedness is strikingly exemplified in the calls from many businessmen for wage and price guidelines or controls or income policies. There is nothing that could do more in a brief period to destroy a market system and replace it by a centrally controlled system than effective governmental control of prices and wages. The short-sightedness is also exemplified in speeches by businessmen on social responsibility. This may gain them kudos in the short run. But it helps to strengthen the already too prevalent view that the pursuit of profits is wicked and immoral and must be curbed and controlled by external forces. Once this view is adopted, the external forces that curb the market will not be the social consciences, however highly developed, of the pontificating executives; it will be the iron fist of Government bureaucrats. Here, as with price and wage controls, businessmen seem to me to reveal a suicidal impulse. The political principle that underlies the market mechanism is unanimity. In an ideal free market resting on private property, no individual can coerce any other, all cooperation is voluntary, all parties to such cooperation benefit or they need not participate. There are no values, no social responsibilities in any sense other than the shared values and responsibilities of individuals. Society is a collection of individuals and of the various groups they voluntarily form. The political principle that underlies the political mechanism is conformity. The individual must serve a more general social interest whether that be determined by a church or a dictator or a majority. The individual may have a vote and say in what is to be done, but if he is overruled, he must conform. It is appropriate for some to require others to contribute to a general social purpose whether they wish to or not. 5

Unfortunately, unanimity is not always feasible. There are some respects in which conformity appears unavoidable, so I do not see how one can avoid the use of the political mechanism altogether. But the doctrine of social responsibility taken seriously would extend the scope of the political mechanism to every human activity. It does not differ in philosophy from the most explicitly collectivist doctrine. It differs only by professing to believe that collectivist ends can be attained without collectivist means. That is why, in my book Capitalism and Freedom, I have called it a fundamentally subversive doctrine in a free society, and I have said that in such a society, there is one and only one social responsibility of business to use its resources and engage in activities designed to increase its profits so long as it stays within the rules of the game, which is to say, engages in open and free competition without deception or fraud. Reprinted in: (1) Milton Friedman, An Economist s Protest: Columns on Political Economy, pp. 177-184. Glen Ridge, New Jersey: Thomas Horton & Daughters, 1972. (2) Kurt R. Leube, editor, The Essence of Friedman, pp. 36-42. Stanford, California: Hoover Institution Press, 1987. 10/3/12 6