Multiculturalism and liberal democracy

Similar documents
Multiculturalism Sarah Song Encyclopedia of Political Theory, ed. Mark Bevir (Sage Publications, 2010)

In his account of justice as fairness, Rawls argues that treating the members of a

In his theory of justice, Rawls argues that treating the members of a society as. free and equal achieving fair cooperation among persons thus

Bringing the Debate to the Classroom. World on Trial: French Headscarf Law

Citizenship, Nationality and Immigration in Germany

OVERVIEW OF A RECOGNITION AND IMPLEMENTATION OF INDIGENOUS RIGHTS FRAMEWORK

Phil 232: Philosophy and Multiculturalism spring 14 Charles Taylor, The Politics of Recognition (sections I and II)

AMY GUTMANN: THE CONSTRUCTIVE POTENTIAL OF COMMUNITARIAN VALUES DOES GUTMANN SUCCEED IN SHOWING THE CONSTRUCTIVE POTENTIAL OF COMMUNITARIAN VALUES?

What is multiculturalism?

The Politics of reconciliation in multicultural societies 1, Will Kymlicka and Bashir Bashir

Religion-Based Alternative Dispute Resolution: A Challenge to Multiculturalism

Battlefield: Islamic Headscarves. Doutje Lettinga & Sawitri Saharso VU Amsterdam/University of Twente Enschede, The Netherlands

Political Obligation 4

Definition: Institution public system of rules which defines offices and positions with their rights and duties, powers and immunities p.

Multiculturalism and Contextualism: How is Context Relevant for Political Theory?

Comments on Justin Weinberg s Is Government Supererogation Possible? Public Reason Political Philosophy Symposium Friday October 17, 2008

The Role of Sport in Fostering Open and Inclusive Societies

Definition: Property rights in oneself comparable to property rights in inanimate things

THE SIGNIFICANCE OF A PHILOSOPHICAL APPROACH IN CONSTITUTIONAL ADJUDICATION WITH REFERENCE TO THE PRINCE CASE ISSN VOLUME 6 No 2

Hijab: la lutte continue

Global Justice and Two Kinds of Liberalism

Rawls versus the Anarchist: Justice and Legitimacy

Forming a Republican citizenry

The Hardware and Software of Pluralism

Comments by Nazanin Shahrokni on Erik Olin Wright s lecture, Emancipatory Social Sciences, Oct. 23 rd, 2007, with initial responses by Erik Wright

Introduction 478 U.S. 186 (1986) U.S. 558 (2003). 3

MULTICULTURALISM THREE DEVELOPMENT PHASES:

The author of this important volume

EU Citizenship Should Speak Both to the Mobile and the Non-Mobile European

Con WEB. Webpapers on Constitutionalism & Governance beyond the State. Year 2001 No 1

Do we have a strong case for open borders?

Stereotyping of black, immigrant and refugee women

University of Alberta

Diversity and Democratization in Bolivia:

In Nations and Nationalism, Ernest Gellner says that nationalism is a theory of

The Public and Private Spheres, Sociopolitical Integration and the Demands of Difference: the Responses of Multiculturalism *

Relational Group Autonomy: Ensuring Agency and Accountability in the Group Rights Paradigm. Fiona MacDonald,

Chantal Mouffe On the Political

The Constitution in One Sentence: Understanding the Tenth Amendment

Multiculturalism or Civic Integration Policies: Which One Is Better for the Immigrant Women?

Liberalism and the Politics of Legalizing Unauthorized Migrants

WHY NOT BASE FREE SPEECH ON AUTONOMY OR DEMOCRACY?

David A. Reidy, J.D., Ph.D. University of Tennessee

Is Rawls s Difference Principle Preferable to Luck Egalitarianism?

Political and Social Transition in Egypt. Magued Osman

A conception of human rights is meant to play a certain role in global political

Constitution-Talk and Justice-Talk

Why Did India Choose Pluralism?

Economic philosophy of Amartya Sen Social choice as public reasoning and the capability approach. Reiko Gotoh

Pluralism and Peace Processes in a Fragmenting World

POSC 6100 Political Philosophy

PHIL 28 Ethics & Society II

Pearson Edexcel GCE in Government & Politics (6GP04/4B) Paper 4B: Ideological Traditions

The political problem of economic inequality and the perils of redistribution.

RESPONSE TO JAMES GORDLEY'S "GOOD FAITH IN CONTRACT LAW: The Problem of Profit Maximization"

The. Third Way and beyond. Criticisms, futures and alternatives EDITED BY SARAH HALE WILL LEGGETT AND LUKE MARTELL

Phil 115, June 20, 2007 Justice as fairness as a political conception: the fact of reasonable pluralism and recasting the ideas of Theory

Comments on Schnapper and Banting & Kymlicka

Liberalism and Culture

Political equality, wealth and democracy

Liberals, Communitarians, Republicans and the Intervention of the State in the Private Sphere

POLITICAL AUTHORITY AND PERFECTIONISM: A RESPONSE TO QUONG

RECONSIDERING CONTESTED SECESSIONS: UNFEASIBILITY AND INDETERMINACY

Future Directions for Multiculturalism

FEDERAL COURT OF AUSTRALIA

Phil 115, May 24, 2007 The threat of utilitarianism

25th IVR World Congress LAW SCIENCE AND TECHNOLOGY. Frankfurt am Main August Paper Series. No. 055 / 2012 Series D

SOCIAL STUDIES 20-2: Understandings of Nationalism

Constructing a Socially Just System of Social Welfare in a Multicultural Society: The U.S. Experience

To cite this article: Anna Stilz (2011): ON THE RELATION BETWEEN DEMOCRACY AND RIGHTS, Representation, 47:1, 9-17

South Slave Divisional Education Council. Social Studies Title: Understandings of Nationalism Curriculum Package

If you wish to understand it further, please consult my more detailed and articulated analysis.

COPYRIGHTED MATERIAL. Introduction CHAPTER. Thomas Christiano and John Christman

IMMIGRATION POLICY AND IDENTIFICATION ACROSS BORDERS. Matthew Lindauer

Globalization and food sovereignty: Global and local change in the new politics of food

119 Book Reviews/Comptes Rendus

A Defence of Equality among Societal Cultures.

John Rawls's Difference Principle and The Strains of Commitment: A Diagrammatic Exposition

John Rawls, Socialist?

Re: CSC review Panel Consultation

A COMMENTARY TO MONTSERRAT GUIBERNAU NATIONS WITHOUT STATES: POLITICAL COMMUNITIES IN THE GLOBAL AGE

THE SOCIAL CHARACTER OF FREEDOM OF EXPRESSION

SOCIAL JUSTICE AND THE MORAL JUSTIFICATION OF A MARKET SOCIETY

Law and Philosophy (2015) 34: Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2015 DOI /s ARIE ROSEN BOOK REVIEW

Are Decent Non-Liberal Societies Really Non-Liberal?

Poverty Knowledge, Coercion, and Social Rights: A Discourse Ethical Contribution to Social Epistemology

REFLECTIONS FROM THE CHIEF JUSTICE

UvA-DARE (Digital Academic Repository) Religious Freedom and the Threat of Jurisdictional Pluralism Rummens, S.; Pierik, R.H.M.

S.L. Hurley, Justice, Luck and Knowledge, (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2003), 341 pages. ISBN: (hbk.).

Criminal Justice Without Moral Responsibility: Addressing Problems with Consequentialism Dane Shade Hannum

Justice as fairness The social contract

The Challenge of Multiculturalism: Beyond Liberalism and Communitarianism

Themes and Scope of this Book

Social welfare activism in Jordan: democratisation in disguise?

2 POLITICAL THEORY / month 2004

E-LOGOS. Rawls two principles of justice: their adoption by rational self-interested individuals. University of Economics Prague

Is there room in liberal theory for Aboriginal rights as understood by Aboriginal peoples?

Immigration and freedom of movement

HUMAN RIGHTS AND DELIBERATIVE DEMOCRACY

Participatory parity and self-realisation

Transcription:

Will Kymlicka, Filimon Peonidis Multiculturalism and liberal democracy Published 25 July 2008 Original in English First published in Cogito (Greece) 7 (2008) (Greek version) Downloaded from eurozine.com (http://www.eurozine.com/multiculturalism-and-liberal-democracy-2/) Cogito (Greece) Eurozine Liberal values can be twisted to justify limiting civil rights, warns Will Kymlicka in interview. Nevertheless, religious law may not replace the civil code. "The same forces that support ethnic politics within liberal democracy also operate over time to channel it in peaceful and democratic ways." Filimon Peonidis: You were the first person who showed to us the significance of minority protection, cultural membership, and multiculturalism for mainstream Anglo-Saxon political philosophy. In the past all these were regarded as political, sociological or legal issues. A long period separates the publication of your first book on this topic, Liberalism, Community and Culture (1989), and your latest one, Multicultural Odysseys (2007). Have your views on liberal multiculturalism undergone any significant change during all these years? Will Kymlicka: I m still very interested in the general question of how the claims of ethno-cultural minorities relate to the basic principles of liberaldemocratic theory, but my motivation for addressing this question has evolved over the years. Originally, I chose this topic as a test case for exploring the liberal-communitarian debate that dominated Anglo- American political philosophy in the 1980s. In the 1970s, liberals like John Rawls and Ronald Dworkin had developed new theories of liberal egalitarian justice that I personally found very attractive. In the 1980s, however, communitarians like Charles Taylor criticized these theories for being too individualistic and atomistic, and his main proof for this critique was the example of ethnic minorities. According to Taylor, a Rawlsian or Dworkinian theory of liberal justice could not defend the sorts of group-specific rights that minorities need to protect themselves from assimilation. And he Page 1/6

concluded that this made liberalism particularly inappropriate for my own country Canada where a range of minority rights for the indigenous Aboriginal peoples, for the Quebecois, and for immigrant groups are wellestablished, widely-accepted, and indeed are vital to the survival of the country. This argument really worried me, because I wasn t willing to abandon support for Canada s minority rights, but nor was I willing to shift from liberalism to communitarianism to defend them, since I think that communitarianism has a dangerous tendency to limit the freedom of individuals to question and revise traditional ways of life. So my original motivation was to show that a Rawlsian theory has the resources to defend minority rights. More specifically, I wanted to show that (a) liberalism has its own reasons, related to its core values of individual freedom, for recognizing that people have legitimate interests in their culture and community; (b) that these values deserve protection through various group-specific rights, such as language rights or self-government rights; and (c) that these groupspecific rights can be implemented without jeopardizing the basic civil and political rights of individuals. More recently, my motivations have shifted. I m still interested in defending minority rights, but not so much in the context of communitarian critiques of liberal individualism. Rather, I m interested in how minority rights fit into broader issues in liberal-democratic theory. Many people worry that even if minority rights can be shown to be consistent with liberal ideas of individual autonomy, they threaten other basic liberal-democratic values, such as values of solidarity, or democratic participation, or simply peace and stability. We could phrase these as issues about the nature of multicultural citizenship. Once a country embraces multiculturalism, what are the bonds of citizenship that unite people from different ethnic groups, what is the source of solidarity, how do people engage in democratic deliberation, and so on? That has been the main focus of my work for the past ten to fifteen years. One reason why I have shifted in this direction is that, in many newly democratizing countries, the worries about multiculturalism are less to do with individual autonomy and more to do with how to create sustainable democratic forms of citizenship. FP: In your writings you insist that there are certain limits to the various concessions a liberal democratic state can make to distinct cultural groups. As you say, it is clear that multiculturalism in Canada is firmly embedded Page 2/6

within the framework of liberal democratic constitutionalism and human rights jurisprudence. Minorities are obligated to abide by this framework. However, a critic may object that sometimes minority groups are prohibited in the name of liberalism from engaging in the very activities that constitute their cultural identity. For instance, in some Western democracies Muslim populations are denied access to their own religious tribunals and female Muslim students are not allowed to wear headscarves in school. Should we consider the possibility that liberal multiculturalism just pays lip service to the idea of respecting non-western and non-christian collective identities? WK: There is undoubtedly a trend in recent years towards what Christian Joppke calls repressive liberalism, particularly in relation to immigrants in Europe. According to Joppke, when western European states seek to justify anti-immigrant policies, they no longer invoke nationally-distinctive myths, identities or narratives, but rather invoke universal liberal values, and argue that immigrants are a threat to these universal values. This is the basis on which France forbids Muslim girls from the wearing the hijab in school, and the basis on which Denmark limits the freedom of immigrants to marry spouses from foreign countries. I agree this is a worrying trend. But we need to distinguish different cases. In some cases, liberal values are being twisted to justify limiting people s fundamental civil rights as in the hijab and foreign marriage cases. In my view, this is simply illegitimate. If we are worried that some girls are being coerced by family members to wear the hijab or to marry foreign husbands, we need to find ways to stop the coercion, rather than limiting the rights of all people to wear religious dress or to marry non-citizens. These blanket bans really are repressive. But in other cases, minorities are seeking not simply to exercise their civil liberties, but also to exercise state power for example, asking the state to legally enforce the decisions of religious family law tribunals. People have a basic civil right to consult with their own religious authorities on issues of marriage and divorce, but those religious authorities do not have an inherent right to have their judgements be given legal effect and be enforced by state officials. In my view, it is perfectly appropriate for a liberal state to say that religious tribunals will only be legally recognized if they meet certain standards such as informed consent, due process, professional training, non-discrimination, the best interests of the child, and so on. These standards may conflict with the historic traditions of certain Page 3/6

minority groups, but of course they conflicted with the historic traditions of the majority as well. To insist that these standards be respected is not evidence of hypocrisy or insincerity in the application of liberal values. It simply re-affirms core liberal beliefs about the legitimate bases and goals of state power, beliefs that have been invoked to challenge both majority and minority traditions. FP: You are in favour of ascribing group rights to minorities that would protect them from dangers coming from the larger society ( external protections as you call them). Some liberals do not seem to agree with this suggestion. They claim that human rights are meant to protect only individuals from certain enduring threats to their life, liberty and property and that it is better to speak of group privileges that will be taken back when the cultural group in question ceases to be regarded as disadvantaged. What would you reply to this objection? WK: Moral philosophy typically works with a much narrower notion of rights than political or legal theory. For many moral philosophers, a claim only qualifies as a right if it can be deduced solely from premises about the inherent interests of individuals abstracted from any historical or sociological contingencies. Defined this way, it is indeed difficult to say that minority claims are rights, since we can certainly imagine circumstances that would make the claims unnecessary. For example, if borders were redrawn around the world, so that some current minorities became numerical majorities within these new boundaries, some of the rights they currently claim such as affirmative action or guaranteed political representation might be entirely unnecessary, and even illegitimate. A moral philosopher might conclude that such claims can therefore only be contingent privileges not inherent rights. But for the purposes of legal and political philosophy, I don t think this strict and narrow definition of rights is helpful. These forms of philosophy inevitably need to take certain institutional contexts for granted. We cannot theorize about citizenship rights, for example, without presupposing certain facts about how the world is divided into territorially-defined political communities. That is a contingent fact, and it may someday change if we lived in a world with a single global state, there would no longer be a distinction between citizens and non-citizens, and hence no need for a theory of citizenship rights. But in our world, we do very much need such a theory. And we cannot theorize about citizenship rights without first Page 4/6

specifying the institutional context. For contemporary Anglo-American political philosophy, that institutional context is the nation-state. So our political theories of citizenship rights are theories about the sorts of rights that are appropriate in the context of Westphalian nation-states. And in that context, I would argue that minority rights are just as deserving of being viewed as rights as many other social, civil, and political rights. Just as nation-states raise certain enduring threats to the life, liberty, and property of all individuals, regardless of cultural membership, so too they raise enduring threats to those individuals who belong to minority groups. So long as we live in a world of nation-states, we will need minority rights to protect against those enduring threats. FP: It is obvious that the highly successful Canadian model of multiculturalism and minority protection cannot be applied as it is to Balkan states for a variety of historical and geopolitical reasons. However, do you believe that there are any ideas or assumptions underlying this model that would help democratic governments in this region deal in a principled way with minority issues? WK: I don t think that specific models of multiculturalism can be transported directly from one country to another, particularly not the Canadian model, which is a product of a very unique history. So I would hesitate to offer any advice about immediate policy debates. But I do think there are longer-term lessons from the various Western experiences with multiculturalism and minority rights. The first is simply that ethnic politics must be seen as an enduring feature of a free and democratic society. Too many countries still cling to the hope that once societies democratize, modernize, and develop economically, then ethnic politics will disappear. So far as I can tell, there is no evidence for believing this, and much evidence to the contrary. Some of the deepest values of liberal democracy including foundational commitments to individual freedom, political equality and human rights operate to support and sustain ethnic politics. We need to acknowledge this and to prepare for it when thinking about the sort of democratic society we wish to build. On the other hand, the Western experience also shows that ethnic politics can be peacefully managed within a larger, stable liberal-democratic order. The same forces that support ethnic politics within liberal democracy also operate over time to channel it in peaceful and democratic ways, and thereby pacify and domesticate ethnic politics. So if ethnic politics are an Page 5/6

Powered by TCPDF (www.tcpdf.org) enduring part of democratic life, it can nonetheless become a normal part of day-to-day democratic politics, not a uniquely explosive or destabilizing issue. The long-term goal, therefore, shouldn t be to extinguish or to solve ethnic politics once and for all, but rather to normalize it. Page 6/6