The Concept of Law in Transnational Arbitral Legal Orders and some of its Consequences

Similar documents
POSITION PAPER THE NEW WORLD ORDER OF ECONOMIC RELATIONS. Alfredo De Jesús O., and José Ricardo Feris IN THE LIGHT OF ARBITRAL JURISPRUDENCE

Legal Reasoning, the Rule of Law, and Legal Theory: Comments on Gerald Postema, Positivism and the Separation of the Realists from their Skepticism

942 EJIL 20 (2009),

TOPIC: - THE PLACE OF KELSONS PURE THEORY OF LAW IN

Last time we discussed a stylized version of the realist view of global society.

RESPONSE TO JAMES GORDLEY'S "GOOD FAITH IN CONTRACT LAW: The Problem of Profit Maximization"

E-LOGOS. Rawls two principles of justice: their adoption by rational self-interested individuals. University of Economics Prague

Law as a form of justice

Politics between Philosophy and Democracy

Two Pictures of the Global-justice Debate: A Reply to Tan*

In 1978, Congress established the Foreign Intelligence Surveillance Court, which reviews warrants related to national security investigations.

Book Review: The Hart-Fuller Debate in the Twenty-First Century, by Peter Cane (ed)

Law and Philosophy (2015) 34: Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2015 DOI /s ARIE ROSEN BOOK REVIEW

On Human Rights by James Griffin, Oxford University Press, 2008, 339 pp.

A few years ago, Olivier De Schutter, UN Special Rapporteur on the Right to. Food, wrote how the dissemination of the European Social Charter (ESC)

The Identity of Legal Systems

A NORMATIVE POSITIVISM: LINKING STRUCTURAL AND PROCEDURAL PRINCIPLES TO CONCEPTIONS OF AUTHORITY USING HART S RULE OF RECOGNITION

How to approach legitimacy

THE IRAQ WAR OF 2003: A RESPONSE TO GABRIEL PALMER-FERNANDEZ

Proceduralism and Epistemic Value of Democracy

Legal normativity: Requirements, aims and limits. A view from legal philosophy. Elena Pariotti University of Padova

REFUSING RECOGNITION AND ENFORCEMENT ON GROUNDS OF PUBLIC POLICY AND NON-ARBITRABILITY IN KUWAIT S. Badah 1

CORRUPTION IN INTERNATIONAL TRADE AND COMMERCIAL ARBITRATION

ANDREAS ZIMMERMANN & RAINER HOFMANN, ED., UNITY AND DIVERSITY IN INTERNATIONAL LAW (BERLIN: DUNCKER & HUMBLOT, 2006) By Mario Prost

Introduction 478 U.S. 186 (1986) U.S. 558 (2003). 3

Opening of the Judicial Year. Seminar

Rawls versus the Anarchist: Justice and Legitimacy

Sociological Marxism Volume I: Analytical Foundations. Table of Contents & Outline of topics/arguments/themes

Book Review: Lessons of Everyday Law/Le Droit du Quotidien, by Roderick A. Macdonald

Aconsideration of the sources of law in a legal

Humanity as the A and Ω of Sovereignty: A Rejoinder to Emily Kidd White, Catherine E. Sweetser, Emma Dunlop and Amrita Kapur

Comment on Baker's Autonomy and Free Speech

Mehrdad Payandeh, Internationales Gemeinschaftsrecht Summary

Justice As Fairness: Political, Not Metaphysical (Excerpts)

Follow this and additional works at:

Reading Finnis Natural Law Theory in the Shadow of Hart

REVIEW. Statutory Interpretation in Australia

For a Universal Declaration of Democracy

POLITICAL AUTHORITY AND PERFECTIONISM: A RESPONSE TO QUONG

For a Universal Declaration of Democracy. A. Rationale

SOUTH DAKOTA BOARD OF REGENTS. Policy Manual

SOME PROBLEMS IN THE USE OF LANGUAGE IN ECONOMICS Warren J. Samuels

Identification of customary international law Statement of the Chair of the Drafting Committee Mr. Charles Chernor Jalloh.

Jus in Bello through the Lens of Individual Moral Responsibility: McMahan on Killing in War

Introduction[1] The obstacle

BOOK REVIEW: WHY LA W MA TTERS BY ALON HAREL

FILARTIGA v. PENA-IRALA: A CONTRIBUTION TO THE DEVELOPMENT OF CUSTOMARY INTERNATIONAL LAW BY A DOMESTIC COURT

We the Stakeholders: The Power of Representation beyond Borders? Clara Brandi

ITUC OBSERVATIONS TO THE ILO COMMITTEE OF EXPERTS ON CONVENTION 87 AND THE RIGHT TO STRIKE

Civil Disobedience and the Duty to Obey the Law: A Critical Assessment of Lefkowitz's View

Commentary on Idil Boran, The Problem of Exogeneity in Debates on Global Justice

Human Rights and their Limitations: The Role of Proportionality. Aharon Barak

The Rights and Wrongs of Taking Rights Seriously

Cover Page. The handle holds various files of this Leiden University dissertation.

LEGAL THEORY/ JURISPRUDENCE SUMMARY

CONSTANZE SCHULTE, COMPLIANCE WITH DECISIONS OF THE INTERNATIONAL COURT OF JUSTICE (OXFORD: OXFORD UNIVERSITY PRESS, 2004) Par Sébastien Jodoin*

The Public Conscience of the Law *

Ekaterina Bogdanov January 18, 2012

Multiculturalism Sarah Song Encyclopedia of Political Theory, ed. Mark Bevir (Sage Publications, 2010)

The Justification of Justice as Fairness: A Two Stage Process

VERBATIM PROCEEDINGS YALE LAW SCHOOL CONFERENCE FIRST AMENDMENT -- IN THE SHADOW OF PUBLIC HEALTH

IS STARE DECISIS A CONSTRAINT OR A CLOAK?

Democracy and Common Valuations

DECLARATION OF JUDICIAL TRAINING PRINCIPLES

Louisiana Law Review. H. Alston Johnson III. Volume 34 Number 5 Special Issue Repository Citation

Party Autonomy A New Paradigm without a Foundation? Ralf Michaels, Duke University School of Law

S.L. Hurley, Justice, Luck and Knowledge, (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2003), 341 pages. ISBN: (hbk.).

The Injustice of Affirmative Action: A. Dworkian Perspective

International Law s Relative Authority

JURISPRUDENCE: a brief story by. Alexander B R Ö S T L. Košice 2010

Comments on Schnapper and Banting & Kymlicka

ABSTRACT. Electronic copy available at:

Book Reviews. Julian Culp, Global Justice and Development, Palgrave Macmillan, Basingstoke, UK, 2014, Pp. xi+215, ISBN:

A MONOGRAPHIC APPROACH TO THE LEGAL PROTECTION OF CONSUMERS

IV. GENERAL RECOMMENDATIONS ADOPTED BY THE COMMITTEE ON THE ELIMINATION OF DISCRIMINATION AGAINST WOMEN. Thirtieth session (2004)

TOWARDS A NEW EUROPEAN LEGAL FRAMEWORK: THE PROPOSAL FOR A REGULATION ON A COMMON EUROPEAN SALES LAW

Summary. Pariah States in International Law?

25th IVR World Congress LAW SCIENCE AND TECHNOLOGY. Frankfurt am Main August Paper Series. No. 055 / 2012 Series D

Regional Autonomies and Federalism in the Context of Internal Self-Determination

The Determinacy of Republican Policy: A Reply to McMahon

JURISPRUDENCE: PHILOSOPHY ABOUT STUDY OF LAW

Political Obligation 3

Business Law - Complete Notes

Cultural Diversity and Social Media III: Theories of Multiculturalism Eugenia Siapera

Law Beyond the State: A Reply to Liam Murphy

C-Fam Analysis. Follow-Up and Review of the Post-2015 Development Agenda. Introduction. Center for Family and Human Rights May 12, 2015

Research Note: Toward an Integrated Model of Concept Formation

Philosophy 34 Spring Philosophy of Law. What is law?

Discourse Theory and International Law: An Interview with Jürgen Habermas *

Book Review: Kai Ambos, Treatise on International Criminal Law (vol I)

Recognition and secessionist in the complex environment of world politics

John Rawls's Difference Principle and The Strains of Commitment: A Diagrammatic Exposition

Law and Politics Book Review Sponsored by the Law and Courts Section of the American Political Science Association.

THE POSSIBILITY OF A FAIR PLAY ACCOUNT OF LEGITIMACY. Justin Tosi

From the veil of ignorance to the overlapping consensus: John Rawls as a theorist of communication

Programme Specification

1 From a historical point of view, the breaking point is related to L. Robbins s critics on the value judgments

Law Beyond the State: A Reply to Liam Murphy

Disagreement, Error and Two Senses of Incompatibility The Relational Function of Discursive Updating

The character of public reason in Rawls s theory of justice

Transcription:

Journal of International Dispute Settlement, Vol. 2, No. 1 (2011), pp. 59 85 doi:10.1093/jnlids/idq019 Published Advance Access January 2, 2011 The Concept of Law in Transnational Arbitral Legal Orders and some of its Consequences THOMAS SCHULTZ* If an arbitration system, hypothetically disconnected from states, were to seek to replicate the rule of law beyond the state, in its own transnational order, what would it look like? This question, which seems current given the proliferation of international dispute resolution mechanisms and the continuing rise of international arbitration, formed an implicit theme of the scholarship known as the School of Dijon. Some 30 years ago, the School of Dijon asserted the existence of non-national legal systems revolving around arbitration mechanisms, such as the lex mercatoria. Over the years, their claim developed into the argument that these systems own legality forms a basis for claims of autonomy from the state, the presence of law dispensing from the need for control by another legal order. This article argues, first, that this line of arguments is an enthymeme, as the concept of law has been the object of a near wholesale eschewal of definitional attention by the School of Dijon and its kindred theories. The article then maintains that any concept of law used for the aforementioned rhetorical and political purposes ought to include the fundamental principles of the rule of law. It then examines the guise that the rule of law takes when applied to transnational adjudicative normative orders instead of national legal systems. 1. Introduction A meaningful and relatively recent development in law on the international plane is the transformation of the landscape of international dispute settlement. 1 These last decades have been marked by a radical increase in the * Swiss National Science Foundation Ambizione Fellow, Graduate Institute of International and Development Studies; Senior Lecturer (Maître d enseignement et de recherche), University of Geneva Law Faculty; Executive Director, Geneva Master in International Dispute Settlement (MIDS); Editorial Director, Journal of International Dispute Settlement. E-mail: thomas.schultz@graduateinstitute.ch. Research supported by the Swiss National Science Foundation. 1 See eg G Abi-Saab, Fragmentation or Unification: Some Concluding Remarks (1999) 31 N Y U J Intl L Pol 919; M Koskenniemi and P Leino, Fragmentation of International Law? Postmodern Anxieties (2002) 15 Leiden J Intl L 553. ß The Author 2011. Published by Oxford University Press. All rights reserved. For permissions, please e-mail: journals.permissions@oup.com

60 Journal of International Dispute Settlement number of dispute resolution mechanisms in the international arena 2 and by a general liberalization of national arbitration laws, 3 leading to a decreasing control of national courts and national laws over arbitral procedures and awards, in what William Park views as a paradigm shift to laissez-faire judicial review. 4 These movements were accompanied by a creeping expansion of private justice systems into new territories, such as foreign investment, sports, competition matters, Internet-related disputes and, to some extent, consumer disputes. Private justice mechanisms, and in particular arbitral systems, which this article focuses on, have become more numerous and more autonomous, and have extended their realm. They have acquired a growing normative power, furthering the development of their own spheres of normativity, which in certain cases may be referred to as transnational arbitral regimes. 5 This development has triggered a political debate between the proponents of, on the one hand, economic efficacy and, on the other hand, state sovereignty a debate where one of the main questions posed concerns the advisability and extent of state intervention. 6 One of the most germane parts of an answer to this question, which nevertheless has remained largely unaddressed so far, would appear to be the regulative quality of such transnational arbitral regimes. That is, we ought to ask ourselves how just the normativity is that is produced by arbitration. This is one of the principal questions that must receive further elucidation before we can unobjectionably proceed with more ideological debates. The current article is conceived as an introductory reflection on this question. As such, it essentially offers a view for the theorist who wishes to contemplate the basic contours of this question, as well as its jurisprudential and political momentousness. When referring to transnational arbitral regimes, a proper starting point for the discussion always seems to be found in the visions, purposes and fate of the School of Dijon the school of thought that was at the vanguard of a movement that laboured hard to bring down legal statism, or classical legal positivism, first in the field of international commerce and later in other disciplines, such as sports. Accordingly, in Section 1 we will shortly review the central tenets of the School of Dijon. We will find that their identification of non-state arbitral legal systems, and the connected loosening of the bonds between law and government, actually opened an important path that could lead far beyond the mere battle on semantics that took place for which the 2 See eg T Buergenthal, The Proliferation of International Courts and Tribunals: Is It Good or Bad? (2001) 14 Leiden J Intl L 267; JS Martinez, Towards an International Judicial System (2003) 56 Stan L Rev 429, 437 9 and W Ben Hamida, L arbitrage transnational face à un désordre procédural: la concurrence des procédures et les conflits de juridictions in F Horchani (ed), Où va le droit de l investissement? Désordre normatif et recherche d équilibre (Pedone, Paris 2006). 3 See eg WW Park, Arbitration of International Business Disputes (OUP, Oxford 2006) 5 6. 4 Ibid 11ff ( Under this paradigm, courts intervene only to monitor arbitration s basic procedural integrity ). 5 See, for instance, K Lynch, The Forces of Economic Globalization (Kluwer, The Hague 2003) 81ff. 6 This is the underlying opposition of forces on which Emmanuel Gaillard builds his theoretical framework: E Gaillard, Legal Theory of International Arbitration (Martinus Nijhof, Leiden 2010).

Concept of Law in Transnational Arbitral Legal Orders 61 School of Dijon sometimes has been spurned. It is a path that, through the philosophical cruxes that the School of Dijon should not have eschewed, leads into the territories of the justice of systems of rules and the respect of the fundamental principles of the rule of law, which is the heart of our matter. In Section 2, we will seek to follow this path, and pause at the first main fork in the road, in order to explore different connections between law and justice. In Section 3, we will set on towards the erection of a tentative framework for the assessment of the justice of arbitral regimes, a framework based on the principles of a certain conception of the rule of law. 2. The School of Dijon s Enthymeme During the second half of the last century, the University of Dijon boasted a particularly strong faculty in the field of international arbitration. Scholars such as Berthold Goldman, Philippe Kahn, Philippe Fouchard and Eric Loquin, who all were or are based in Dijon, launched some of the most effective missiles in the intellectual battles that shaped the French tradition in international arbitration, which itself remains marked by a few illuminating idiosyncrasies and a great multitude of academic virtuosities. Among the many contributions of the scholarship crafted in Dijon, the most lasting and characteristic, which forms the substance of the strand of thought that is designated by the School of Dijon, is the idea that there are transnational legal systems that cannot be reduced to any one public national legal system. 7 These transnational systems of legal rules, in the scholarship of the School of Dijon and its followers and kindred thinkers, typically manifest themselves in, and are partly produced by, international arbitration procedures. 8 It is the Latin formulation of the rebirth of the lex mercatoria, which we primarily owe to Berthold Goldman, that best captured and conveyed (and helped market) the central idea of these reflections. More recently, further successful Latin terminology was introduced, most notably the lex sportiva, 9 again in order to refer to the existence as law (that is, the legality) of non-state normative systems. The School of Dijon and its kindred theories have come under criticism from a variety of fronts. The most massive onslaught came from the various heirs of Kelsenian and Austinian thinking. Not ready for a paradigm shift, many scholars exhibited various forms of fierce dogmatic determination to suppress 7 For a lively account of the development of the School of Dijon, see P Kahn s comments made during the Paris 2001 colloquium, in H Ghérari and S Szurek (eds) L émergence de la société civile internationale (Pedone, Paris 2003) 266 8. 8 See generally P Fouchard, P Kahn and A Lyon-Caen (ed), Le droit des relations économiques internationales. Études offertes à Berthold Goldman (Litec, Paris 1989); A Kassis, Théorie générale des usages du commerce (LGDJ, Paris 1984); F Osman, Les principes généraux de la Lex mercatoria (LGDJ, Paris 1992); F Marrella, La nuova lex mercatoria (CEDAM, Padova 2003); KP Berger, The Creeping Codification of the Lex Mercatoria (2nd edn, Kluwer, Alphen aan den Rijn 2010); P Deumier, Le droit spontané (Economica, Paris 2002). 9 See eg F Latty, La lex sportiva (Martinus Nijhoff, Leiden 2007).

62 Journal of International Dispute Settlement any academic representation of non-state normativity. Such authors cling to the classical conception of legal positivism, which identifies law with the command of a sovereign, and thus ignores all manifestations of legality that are unconnected to the notion of government: it is the idea that there is no law outside of state law. We should be aware that such an understanding of legal positivism has, outside the field of international commerce and arbitration, largely been abandoned in English-reading academic circles 10 since H.L.A. Hart s 1958 article in the Harvard Law Review, which started the famous Hart Fuller debate. 11 Hart s main point in this regard was to assert the undue restrictiveness and analytical unworkable character of Austin s proposal that we should understand law as a command backed up by the threat of a sanction, where the commander is someone in receipt of habitual obedience from most of the society but [who] pays no such obedience to others, in other words, a society s sovereign. 12 But another, more important albeit unscientific argument remains in favour of the detractors of the School of Dijon: in making the case for classical legal positivism, or legal statism, Duguit and Kelsen wrote that they believe to have serious reasons to be convinced that the only means to satisfy [their] aspiration for justice and equity is the resigned confidence that there is no other justice than the justice to be found in the positive law of states. 13 Hence, they concluded, there is no law outside of state law, or rather we ought not to recognize law outside of state law, as such normative systems presumably (they believed ) fail to satisfy our aspirations for justice. 14 This is a very meaningful argument to make, and it will actually inform the greatest part of the balance of this article (though I precisely will eschew Duguit and Kelsen s resigned confidence that non-state rule systems cannot live up to our standards of justice). Another fierce attack against the scholarship that originated in Dijon came from across the Channel. The English pragmatic approach to law spurned the entire doctrinal debate that, in effect, centred on the word lex in lex mercatoria for its lack of practical relevance. Surely, the pragmatists contended, all that matters is the question whether arbitral tribunals are allowed to apply the principles that the concept of lex mercatoria awkwardly seeks to designate, regardless of the latter s quality as a legal system. 15 And so this strand of thinking about arbitration and law beyond the state, after a relatively 10 It may be noted, en passant, that in order to get rid of the shackles of legal statism, the French world of arbitration needed to wait for the translation in French, which occurred in 1975, of S Romano s, L ordre juridique (Dalloz, Paris 1975). Hart s article in the Harvard Law Review, referred to in n 11, was never translated in French. 11 HLA Hart, Positivism and Separation of Law and Morals (1958) 71 Harv L Rev 593. 12 Ibid 602 3. 13 L Duguit and H Kelsen, Foreword (1926 27) 1 Revue internationale de la théoriedu droit 1, 3. 14 See also B de Sousa Santos, Toward a New Legal Common Sense: Law, Globalization, and Emancipation (2 nd edn Butterworths, London 2002) 90: the reduction of law to state law was, more than anything else, the result of a political fiat. 15 See eg T Schultz, Some Critical Comments on the Juridicity of the Lex Mercatoria (2008) 10 YB Priv Intl L 667.

Concept of Law in Transnational Arbitral Legal Orders 63 short-lived success as the terrain for fashionable intellectual jousts, became a topic that led to pulses abruptly ceas[ing] to race and laments about [yet] another published exposé of the New lex mercatoria. 16 The question of the autarkic legality of non-state rule-sets was thus brushed aside on the grounds that scholars indulging in such studies merely were fiddling with verbal distinctions while dramatic practical situations were urgently calling for legal solutions. As one author puts it in a more general discussion of legal pluralism, It is... not clear what is gained, either analytically or instrumentally, by appending the label law to [the intended normative manifestations]. 17 Fair enough. Law professors should refrain from the intellectual joys of battling with concepts, and get back to real work, should they not? The charge of inconsequentiality certainly is not entirely devoid of justification. But it is levelled too broadly: it is not the question that is inconsequential, but the way in which it is posed. Herein lies the issue: as long as the concept of law is not firmly anchored to some expressed and loaded tenor, one that carries clear consequences, settling the semantics over the nature of the systems of rules that the School of Dijon identified has little analytical import indeed. Truth be told, none or extremely few of the scholars of the School of Dijon and its followers ever put more than scant reflective effort into the elucidation of the major premise, which ought to say what law is before arguing that the lex mercatoria is an instance of this category of normative systems. Whether this is testimony of simple academic oversight or rather is the mark of a purposeful enthymeme (that is, a syllogism in which part of the argument is presented as so obvious that it is not worth including, making the argument difficult to challenge because questioning the obvious is a confession of ignorance) may be left open for question even though the mere reference by certain authors to the traditional concept of law, with no further explication, would tempt us to conclude in favour of the latter. 18 In any event, this relatively unscientific practice led to the whole debate about the lex mercatoria being stigmatized as woolly and unfocused. 19 Some of the detractors of the School s ideas, however, had it better, and did read a meaning into the concept of law that gave the question some obvious relevance. But these detractors pertain to another class of critics, which will be introduced in the following paragraphs. Other critics did indeed dimly sense a further and more important issue than inconsequentiality in the doctrine of the School of Dijon. As Stephen J. Toope 16 M Mustill, Lex Mercatoria and Arbitration (A Discussion of the New Law Merchant) (1992) 8 Arb Intl 215. 17 BZ Tamanaha, A Non-Essentialist Version of Legal Pluralism (2000) 27 J Law Socy 296, 304. 18 E Gaillard and J Savage (eds), Fouchard Gaillard Goldman on International Commercial Arbitration (Kluwer, The Hague 1999) para 1450: the criteria which traditionally defined the existence of a legal order (emphasis added). See similarly, G Goldman, Lex Mercatoria (1983) 3 Forum Internationale 19, arguing that it is manifest that the lex mercatoria has the status of law. 19 Mustill (n 16) 215.

64 Journal of International Dispute Settlement puts it, though somewhat bluntly: It would appear that the so-called lex mercatoria is largely an effort to legitimise as law the economic interests of Western corporations. 20 We should pause to think about these words: an effort to legitimize as law. While Toope s statement appears to be the result of a rather immediate gut reaction, it nevertheless points to an important aspect of the rhetoric of non-state legal systems: the pre-emptive character of legality. Brutally simplifying, the pre-emptive character of legality is the idea that when law already rules a given social context, then there is no further need for law, and in particular there is no reason for state law to intervene. 21 This is a social mechanism sometimes referred to, though with certain important nuances, as the emancipatory potential of law, which is the idea that the legal character of non-state normative systems is in and of itself an enabling rhetorical factor in the opposition to state interference. 22 This potential follows from the fact that the jural character of a rule system confers it some legitimacy, and thus some pre-emptive power: what is jural in nature is recognized or at least presumed to be partaking of the regulative quality that is associated with justice. Hart, for example, despite his strict insistence on the separability of law and morality, evokes the normally fulfilled assumption that a legal system aims at some form of justice[, which] colours the whole way in which we interpret specific rules in particular cases. 23 There is, he goes on, in the very notion of law consisting of general rules, something which prevents us from treating it as if morally it is utterly neutral, without any necessary contact with moral principles. 24 Law does indeed partake of the symbolism of justice, and vice versa. Legality is instrumental to the fulfilment of aspirations for justice. The cyclical revival of the terminology of natural law is testimony to this fundamental bond between law and justice, Hart further remarked. 25 Another manifestation of this connection is the compelling evidence that adherence to the rule of law is an accepted measure worldwide of government legitimacy, 26 making the rule of law the pre-eminent legitimating political ideal. 27 The rule of law frequently is understood as being good for everyone, 28 an unqualified human good. 29 20 SJ Toope, Mixed International Arbitration (CUP, Cambridge 1990) 96. 21 See Tamanaha (n 17) 304, who argues that one has much greater rhetorical authority when invoking the legitimacy of one s conduct on the basis of its accord with a body of law than when one invokes the mere fact that other people in the same situation happen to adopt the same course of action (social norms). This rhetorical effect, he suggests, does not change depending on the nature of the body of law (state or non-state). 22 See S Santos (n 14) 90 5 and, more generally, chapter 9 entitled Can Law Be Emancipatory? See further A di Robilant, Genealogies of Soft Law (2006) 54 Am J Comp Law 499, 545 (in her reference to Gurvitch s concept of social law and legal pluralism): social law and legal pluralism as critical instruments of emancipation. 23 Hart (n 11) 622. 24 Ibid 624. 25 Ibid 595: the elements of the Rechtsstaat and all the principles for the defence of which the terminology of natural law has in our day been revived. 26 Tamanaha, On the Rule of Law (CUP, Cambridge 2004) 3. 27 Ibid 4. 28 Ibid 1. 29 EP Thompson, Whigs and Hunter (Pantheon, New York 1975) 266.

Concept of Law in Transnational Arbitral Legal Orders 65 Surely then, legality is inseparable from the pursuit and presumed achievement of a certain ideal of justice at least with regard to the common-sense notion of law (as opposed to its jurisprudential understanding), which is the relevant notion for the understanding of the rhetorics of a doctrine since analytical legal philosophers are not typically consulted when the question is pondered whether state regulation should extend to or be reinforced in a given social context. 30 In the light of this connection in the collective conscience between the legality of a rules system and its regulative legitimacy as an ideal of justice, it becomes apparent that legality (in the sense of the characterization as law of a normative system) has a political dimension. 31 Hence Paul Lagarde s mention of the suspicion [that the lex mercatoria may constitute the vehicle for] a take-over of the transnational legal space by private economic powers. 32 Likewise, Lord Mustill s argument that [e]ssentially, the lex mercatoria is a doctrine of laissez-faire clearly expresses the political argument that is made by the apparently innocuous statement that the lex mercatoria deserves the first part of its name. 33 He points indeed to the idea that proponents of arbitration and other forms of private dispute resolution sometimes express a will of independence from the states and argue in favour of laissez-faire on the basis, among other factors, that certain transnational arbitration regimes form non-state legal systems. 34 Such regimes, as one authors puts it, are normative orders claiming legal dignity. 35 The question of the legality of non-state normative systems is much less an innocent pastime for law professors than most people assume. 36 The use of the word law in the qualification of a normative order has in ordinary language strong normative valence: law is, in the words of the historian E.P. Thompson, a cultural achievement of universal significance 37 ; in short, it is a desirable institution that evokes representations of justice. Now, if this connection between law and justice cannot go, if law represents a certain ideal of justice and therefore has rhetorical force on the political plane, then we are less than candid if we shun making this connection meaningful: the attribution of legality to a certain system of rules must be 30 On the limits and contours of the normative valence of attributing the label of law in such a positivistic guise, see eg J Waldron, Normative (or Ethical) Positivism in J Coleman (ed), Hart s Postscript (OUP, Oxford 2001) 411, 428ff; Tamanaha, Rule of Law (n 26) 137 41. 31 See S Santos (n 14) 90, referring to the complex intertwining of analytical and political claims in the definition of law. 32 P Lagarde, Approche critique de la lex mercatoria in P Fouchard, P Kahn, and A Lyon-Caen (eds), Le droit des relations économiques internationales Etudes offertes à Berthold Goldman 125 6 (Litec, Paris 1982) (emphasis added). 33 M Mustill, The New Lex Mercatoria: The First Twenty-Five Years (1988) 4 Arb Intl 86, 117. 34 This is, for instance, an implicit argument in Gaillard (n 6). 35 A di Robilant, Genealogies of Soft Law (2006) 54 Am J Comp Law 499, 542 (in her reference to Santi Romano s concept of legal pluralism). 36 See further P Zumbansen, Piercing the Legal Veil: Commercial Arbitration and Transnational Law (2002) 8 ELJ 400, 418ff, under the heading The Political Underpinnings of Lex Mercatoria. 37 Thompson (n 29) 265.

66 Journal of International Dispute Settlement subjected to certain expressed criteria of justice. 38 The idea is thus to reintroduce in the debate about the autonomy of arbitral regimes an understanding of law that focuses on what matters in the debate: the regulative quality of the normative system in question. Echoing Simon Roberts, we ought to offer a concept of law that helps introduce, understand and justify processes of private norm-making centred on dispute resolution mechanisms. 39 This is something that the School of Dijon shied away from, focusing instead on various aspects of effectiveness and normative autarky vis-à-vis the state. Thereby will the label of law, when attached to arbitral systems of rules, acquire much greater use value. The delineation of such criteria will form the task for the balance of this article. 3. Concepts of Justice We have seen, in the preceding section, that legality ought to be anchored to precepts of political morality constituting a valuable yardstick for gauging the qualities of a dispute resolution mechanism and, pro tanto, for assessing in which respect and to what extent claims for autonomy should be condoned. This raises the question of how to fill the concept of legality with criteria of justice that allow an assessment that is as objective as possible of the regulative quality of arbitral regimes. The question requires the selection of an appropriate ideal of justice to which legality may be anchored. Hence, the following will make a quite laconically selective survey of the main concepts of justice that offer themselves for the task. The three main concepts of justice that a priori appear relevant for the purposes of the current study are justice qua conformity to law, giving to each his own and formal legality. The following paragraphs seek to explain why only the third of these concepts appears to be workable for the purposes of assessing the regulative quality of arbitral regimes. The understanding of justice in the sense of conformity to law (Gerechtigkeit als Rechtsmässigkeit) may be the dominant mode among lawyers in dealing with questions of justice. This approach is based on the tenet that justice (Gerechtigkeit) can only be found in conformity to law (Rechtsmässigkeit); it conceives of justice qua justice according to law, where law stands for the utterances of the sovereign the law of the state. 40 By force of circumstances, 38 A dark parallel may be drawn here with the rhetorical use of the claim to adhere to the Rule of Law for the purposes of legitimizing an iniquitous political regime, which forms an argument that appears to have at least some political weight in a government s opposition to diplomatic interference by other states. The political operations of this argument are sometimes decried because of the emptiness of the regulative principles that are implied by a reference to the Rule of Law: see, for instance, J Paulsson, Enclaves of Justice (2007) 4 Transnatl Disp Mgmt 5, who calls these political operations the Fraudulent Consensus on the Rule of Law. 39 S Roberts, After Government? On Representing Law without the State (2005) 68 MLR 1, 4. 40 J Bell, Justice and the Law in KS Scherer (ed), Justice: Interdisciplinary Perspectives (CUP, Cambridge 1992) 114, 117.

Concept of Law in Transnational Arbitral Legal Orders 67 lawyers are occupied primarily with the achievement of practical justice, which is undertaken by focusing on the way in which legal decisions are rendered. 41 They typically may safely remain agnostic to fundamental, transcendental the values according to which legal rules are created: in the somewhat elliptical words of Pound, lawyers are not required to conduct a sit-down strike until philosophers agree in order to achieve practical justice. 42 Lawyers are usually neither required nor inclined to reflect on some transcendental ideal that may imbue their understanding of law and legal norms, 43 and essentially rely, to achieve justice, on interpretative proficiency and the science of legislation, rather than on reflections pertaining to the science of law. 44 With regard to gauging the justice or regulative quality of arbitral regimes, with the already mentioned rhetorical consequences that attach to that sort of assessment, following such an approach would lead to one of two analytical frameworks for the assessment of the justice of arbitral regimes. The first would focus on the applicable national laws and international conventions to determine the regulative quality of such regimes: the necessary and sufficient condition of justice would be the compliance by the regimes with the requirements that these legal instruments set for the validity of arbitration agreements and awards. Such an approach would only achieve a total trivialization of the whole question, as all important international arbitration systems globally satisfy such requirements arbitral awards would systematically be set aside were it not the case. To say that they all deserve, on the plane of justice, the autonomy that they have been granted by states is an entirely uninformative conclusion. To say that, because of this assessment of justice in the light of Rechtsmässigkeit, those systems deserve greater (or lesser) autonomy than they currently are granted because they ought to be recognized as independent legal systems would do violence to logic. Complying with current conditions of autonomy cannot be the grounds, through the artifices of legality as a revealing factor of regulative quality, for a claim that these conditions should be lowered or heightened. The second analytical framework that such a conception of justice may lead to would be built on the foundations of court decisions: if court decisions qualify or treat given non-state normative orders as legal systems, then these systems ought to be considered just and worthy of the label of law. 45 The advantage of this analytical framework over the preceding one is that here the 41 See generally N Luhmann, Gerechtigkeit in den Rechtssystemen der modernen Gesellschaft (1973) 4 Rechtstheorie 131. 42 R Pound, Justice According to the Law (Yale University Press, New Haven 1951) 129. 43 R Marcic, Rechtsphilosophie (Rombach, Freiburg 1969). 44 W Friedmann, Legal Theory (3 rd edn Stevens & Sons, London 1953) 154, 294 5. 45 It is a frequent argument among private international lawyers that the recognition by courts of the jural character of non-state rule systems ought to be the one decisive criterion for our scholarly determination on the nature of these systems. See, for instance, T Clay, L arbitre (Dalloz, Paris 2001) 217; JM Jacquet, M Delebecque and S Corneloup, Droit du commerce international (2nd edn, Dalloz, Paris 2010) 59 61.

68 Journal of International Dispute Settlement attribution of legality to the external normative system follows directly from a purposeful decision made by the recognizing legal system in this regard. The carriage of expectable rhetorical consequences of legality (using this attributed legality to claim further autonomy on the basis of the rhetoric discussed above) is then simply attached to this decision. It is no longer thrust upon a system that did not mean and barely could expect to open the door to claims of opposition to its intervention. But this advantage at the same time calls for the demise of this analytical framework as a scientific one: because of the distinction between relative legality (the internal point of view of one specific legal system regarding the legality of another rule system) and absolute legality (the external point of view of the analyst studying the question whether a given system of rules instantiates the characteristic features of law), the decision of a court cannot prejudge any scholarly determination in the assessment of the nature of a normative system. Whether we wish to scientifically endorse a given non-state normative system as law or not (which is the question here), with the rhetorical and political consequences that follow from such intellectual backing, is unrelated to what certain national legal systems provide. The reverse would run into the logical quagmire that manifests itself when one national legal system grants a non-state set of rules the label of law while another denies it. In the third century AD, the revered Roman lawyer Ulpian, whom we recall most often for his legal and philosophical one-liners, wrote that justice is the constant and perpetual will to give to each his own ( iustitia est constans et perpetua voluntas ius suum cuique tribuere ). 46 This definition of justice appears to have represented the most widely shared understanding of justice throughout history. According to John Bell, [t]his notion of giving to each his own brings forward the central elements of equal treatment and concern for how resources are allocated. 47 The difference with the previously examined notion of justice as conformity to law is that the latter is merely concerned with treating all according to their legal entitlements, 48 whereas Ulpian s notion takes up the question how the law ought to allocate entitlements in the first place. 49 Suum cuique tribuere thus represents the most basic understanding of substantive justice (as opposed to procedural justice). The analytical framework that such a notion of justice would offer has certain advantages over the justice-according-to-law perspective. First, it would have greater analytical purchase, by allowing to draw consequences from the analysis that are truly meaningful as it would break the dogmatic frame that unavoidably is reflect in arbitration legislation. Second, it would steer clear of the logical meanders and 46 Digest, 1.1.10; Inst 1.1. 47 Bell (n 40) 115. 48 Ibid. 49 Ibid.

Concept of Law in Transnational Arbitral Legal Orders 69 inconsistencies that the Rechtsmässigkeit approach raises when applied to the question of non-state normative systems, which I have just sketched. Incidentally, this suum cuique tribuere analytical framework is the one relied on, most of the time implicitly, by what one may loosely (and in reductionist fashion) identify as the emerging anti-arbitration and re-nationalization movement, meaning those who argue that arbitration overprotects investors in investment arbitration, businesses in consumer arbitration, employers in employment arbitration, sports federations in sports arbitration and so on. But on any scientific argument drawn from a purported misallocation of resources and, thus, on any battle led under the banner of substantive justice, Alf Ross, in a moment of polemical hyperbole, said this: to invoke justice [in such a substantive sense] is the same thing as banging on the table: an emotional expression which turns one s demand into an absolute postulate. 50 Hans Kelsen expressed the same idea more inconspicuously: The problem of values is in the first place the problem of conflicts of values, and this problem cannot be solved by means of rational cognition. The answer to these questions is a judgment of value, determined by emotional factors, and, therefore, subjective in character valid only for the judging subject, and therefore relative only. 51 The issue is this: in the absence of ascertainable and agreed higher standards against which to judge the correct allocation of resources effected by a system of norms, any reference to justice in a discussion on the virtues and vices of a rule system necessarily would amount to a scientifically unsupportable expression of individual or collective preferences. 52 And the condition just exposed appears almost impossible to fulfil given the fact of moral pluralism. 53 In short, it would be a purely subjective choice. Formal legality provides a less ambitious analytical framework, but one with greater use value. 54 It is a conception of the rule of law that subjects the attribution of the label of law 55 to conditions of justice pertaining, for instance, to the way in which norms are promulgated, their clarity and their temporal dimension (prospectivity vs retroactivity, for instance.) 56 It is hence a formal concept of justice, one that is agnostic to the actual contents of the set of rules it qualifies. 57 As such, it would consider as law an iniquitous regime, one that under a substantive approach to justice would be flagged as bad law, and 50 A Ross, On Law and Justice (Stevens, London, 1958) 274. 51 H Kelsen, What is Justice? [1957] in H Kelsen (ed), What Is Justice: Justice, Law, and Politics in the Mirror of Science: Collected Essays (University of California Press, Berkeley 1957) 4. 52 Bell (n 40) 116 7; Tamanaha, Rule of Law (n 26) 99 100. 53 Tamanaha (n 26) 100. 54 On formal legality, see generally ibid 91 101. 55 The rule of law is understood here as the fundamental conditions that have to be satisfied for the existence of any legal system : MH Kramer, Objectivity and the Rule of Law (CUP, Cambridge 2007) 102. 56 See eg P Craig, Formal and Substantive Conceptions of the Rule of Law (1997) PL 467. 57 See eg RS Summers, A Formal Theory of the Rule of Law (1993) 6 Ratio Juris 127, 135.

70 Journal of International Dispute Settlement would not discriminate it from a benign regime, provided both satisfy the applicable procedural conditions. 58 This is the reason why it is less ambitious than an analytical framework based on a substantive version of justice. It should nevertheless be pointed out that bad law complying with the relevant procedural requirements is more estimable than bad law which does not. As Robert George puts it, respect for the requirements of the rule of law is not a morally neutral matter despite the fact that the elements of the rule of law are themselves procedural. 59 This is so, he states, because a normative order conforming to the principles of the rule of law applies fairly whatever standards of conduct and of judgment it applies. This has real value, and independent value, even where the substance of what is done falls short of any relevant ideal of substantive justice. 60 Or, to use Mathew Kramer s words, when the rule of law is operative in a benign regime, and we seem safely entitled to assume that arbitral regimes are benign rather than evil, it is a morally cherishable expression of commitments to the dignity and equality of individuals. 61 Indeed, under the rule of law in such a procedural guise, law consists of an array of requirements and opportunities with which [the addressees] can become familiar and about which they can make effectual choices. As Brian Tamanaha observes: [f]ormal legality enhances the dignity of citizens by allowing them to predict and plan, no doubt a moral positive. 62 The greater use value of formal legality follows from the fact that the amplitude of reasonable disagreements is incomparably smaller over ways in which to implement procedural justice than over the proper allocation of entitlements. This is what led Jürgen Habermas to consider that only genesis, not a priori principles to which the content of norms would have to correspond, provides [a norm] with its justice and, hence, the legitimacy of positive law is conceived as procedural rationality. 63 The inherent variegatedness of conceptions of substantive justice requires that we dispense with arguments relating to the regulative quality of an arbitral regime on the basis of the contents of its rules or the way in which it redistributes resources and limit ourselves to procedural aspects of such a rules system. The question then simply is whether such a regime truly allows to predict and plan. 58 Kramer (n 55) 102: As a set of conditions that obtain whenever any legal system exists and operates, the rule of law is per se a morally neutral state of affairs. Especially in a sizable society, the rule of law is indispensable for the preservation of public order and the coordination of people s activities and the securing of individuals liberties; but it is likewise indispensable for a government s effective perpetration of large-scale projects of evil over lengthy periods. 59 RP George, Reason, Freedom, and the Rule of Law (2002) 15 Regent Univ L Rev 187, 190. 60 Ibid. 61 Kramer (n 55) 102. 62 Tamanaha (n 26) 96. 63 J Habermas, Beyond Facts and Norms (MIT Press, Boston 1996) 449, 453 (emphasis added). It may be pointed out that Habermas believes that the genesis of norms has to be democratic in order to fulfil the requirements of the rule of law, an aspect that I will not address in this article for reasons of space.

Concept of Law in Transnational Arbitral Legal Orders 71 Among the least objectionable yardsticks of procedural justice, precisely because it is based on deliberate efforts to expunge all elements of provincialism, 64 appears to be Lon Fuller s account of the rule of law, which he calls the inner morality of law. 65 Hence, in the third and last main section of this article, I maintain that this understanding of the concept of law is a device for expressing the necessary though not always sufficient conditions of regulative quality that every arbitral regime must follow in order to be considered procedurally just, and thus to deserve the label of law, with all its attendant rhetorical consequences. The fulfilment of the criteria that can be drawn from these precepts for the procedural setup of dispute resolution systems are instrumental in gauging the justice of private systems of justice, and thus for deciding in which respect and to what extent claims for autonomy should be condoned. 4. The Rule of Law in Outcome-Centred Rules Systems In a nutshell, the foregoing sections recount what appears as an important shortcoming in the rhetorical construction of the School of Dijon, namely that the concept of law used to identify non-state arbitral normative systems as legal systems ought to be made explicit and, if such identification is used for the political purposes of establishing or reinforcing autonomy from the state, it ought to be used as an expressing device for requirements of procedural justice. I have then evoked Lon Fuller s conception of the rule of law (the inner morality of law ) as a fitting concept of law for such purposes. These arguments will now be supplemented with an exposition of the regulatory desiderata for private justice regimes that may be inferred from Lon Fuller s concept of law. The following paragraphs will thus expound the sundry bearings that seven of the eight cognate principles delineated by Fuller, which he called the principles of legality, have on procedural questions in dispute resolution and, hence, on regulation through patterns of individual rule application and creation. Fuller s most basic contention is that law s essential function, the one that a norms system must fulfil in order to deserve the label of law, is to subject[...] people s conduct to the guidance of general rules by which they may themselves orient their behaviour. 66 Following this premise, he identified eight procedural principles that a system of rules must comply with in order to 64 Kramer (n 55) 185. 65 L fuller, The Morality of Law (rev edn Yale University Press, New Haven 1969) 33 41. 66 LL Fuller, A Reply to Professors Cohen and Dworkin (1965) 10 Vill L Rev 655, 657.

72 Journal of International Dispute Settlement perform law s essential function and thus to count as law. 67 These eight constitutive elements of legality are, using Matthew Kramer s terminology: 68 P1: governance by general norms, that is the generality of expression and application of the rules that are part of the system; P2: public ascertainability, or the public promulgation of the rules of the system; P3: prospectivity, meaning the non-retroactivity of the rules of the systems; P4: perspicuity, that is the formulation of the mandates provided by the legal system in lucid language; P5: non-contradictoriness and non-conflictingness, in other words the normative coherence of legal system; P6: compliability, that is the near absence of unsatisfiable behests; P7: steadiness over time, which calls for limits in the pace and scale of the transformations of the sundry norms in a legal system 69 P8: congruence between formulation and implementation, in other words that the publicly promulgated rules are actually applied and are applied impartially. As mentioned above, only seven of these eight principles will enter the following discussion. The one that will not be dealt with is compliability. This principle, which more precisely prohibits the presence of too many mandates requiring the impossible from the system s addressees, is not strictly speaking a formal condition of legality, but a substantial one, as it relates to both the precise contents of the rules and the concrete abilities of their addressees. The fulfilment of this condition does not depend on procedural qualities of a regulatory system and hence it has no direct bearing on the matter at issue here and does not translate into a principle that fittingly partakes of the setup of a dispute resolution system. Four of Fuller s principles are cognate in their challenge of arbitral regimes as rules systems with a tenable claim to legality. Governance by general norms (P1), public ascertainability (P2), prospectivity (P3) and steadiness over time (P7) all are principles that are not straightforwardly fulfilled by an outcome-centred mode of regulation. If arbitral awards are to collectively satisfy these principles, one element in the procedural setup of arbitral systems becomes crucial: the precedential force of the awards. The following paragraphs propound these connections, starting with a terse presentation of the aspects of these principles that may raise an issue. Fuller presented his principle of governance by general norms in negative terms as he did for all his principles of legality. He wrote that if every issue [is] decided on an ad hoc basis, then this constitutes an unwanted property of a normative system that would prevent it from being jural. 70 Matthew Kramer 67 Fuller (n 65) 38 9. 68 Kramer (n 55) 103 86. 69 Ibid 132. 70 Fuller (n 65) 38.

Concept of Law in Transnational Arbitral Legal Orders 73 presents this requirement in more sophisticated and nuanced terms: situation-specific directives [must not be] the... principal means of regulating people s conduct. 71 The rationale for this requirement is that the generality of application and address of a system s rules is necessary for the subjects to gain a reliable sense of what other people are required and permitted and empowered to do. 72 Law s inherent primary function is to provide dependable guideposts for self-directed action, 73 which is a purpose that cannot be fulfilled in the absence of a predominance of general norms. 74 Hence, a normative system not primarily composed of general rules would not be functional as law and would not deserve the label of law, neither for jurisprudential purposes nor, I maintain, for the rhetorical and political purposes of claims for a laisser-faire policy on the part of states. The principle of public ascertainability formed the object of a rather elliptical though accurate evocation by Fuller: it [is] very unpleasant to have one s case decided by rules when there [is] no way of knowing what those rules [are]. 75 Law, he contended, must be promulgated in order to count as law. Here again, Matthew Kramer puts flesh to the bones: a rules system whose mandates and other norms are not ascertainable by their addressees would fail to make any difference for their reasoning about their courses of conduct; it would be thoroughly inefficacious in channelling people s behaviour and would thus fail as law. 76 In sum, the purpose of this requirement is identical to the rationale of the principle of governance by general norms: allowing the appraisal by the addressees of the general norms under which the legal consequences of their conduct are assessed, 77 in other words to provide dependable guideposts. The consequences of a failure to meet this requirement is identical to any other failure of the Fullerian principles of legality: a rules system whose norms are not typically ascertainable by their addressees ought not to be considered law, neither for jurisprudential purposes nor for the reasoning that partakes of the School of Dijon. The principle of prospectivity requires that an overwhelming proportion of rules in a system is not retrospective, but prospective, meaning that they are created before the events occur to which they pertain. In and of itself, it is, of course, a brutal absurdity of commanding a man today to do something yesterday, 78 but in practice the exact threshold above which a normative system no longer qualifies as a legal system because of its overabundance of 71 Kramer (n 55) 110. 72 Ibid 112. 73 Fuller (n 65) 229. 74 HLA Hart, Lon L. Fuller: The Morality of Law in HLA Hart (ed.), Essays in Jurisprudence and Philosophy (Clarendon, Oxford 1983) 350 1, 357. 75 Fuller (n 65) 35. 76 Kramer (n 55) 113. 77 Ibid 114. 78 Fuller (n 65) 59.

74 Journal of International Dispute Settlement retrospective laws remains undefinable. What is germane is that a total absence of retroactive norms is neither required nor possible, as there always will be indeterminacies in a normative system, cases for which there are no determinately correct answers to be found in the body of the rules existing at the time when its addressees contemplate alternative courses of action. 79 Similarly, a legal system composed only of retrospective norms is, as Kramer puts it, forbiddingly incoherent. 80 In an echo of the raison d être ascribed to the two principles discussed earlier, the need for a rules system to be based on a great majority of prospective commands in order to be jural is that such prospectivity is necessary to impinge in any significant fashion on the choices and behaviour of the people who are subject to its sway. 81 The principle of steadiness through time requires limits on the pace and scale of the transformations of the sundry norms that pertain to a system of rules. 82 These speed limits must be set so as to avoid such frequent changes in the rules that the subject cannot orient his action by them. 83 This principle is based on the recognition that the erection of effective guideposts for self-directed action requires a degree of internalisation on the part of the addressees. 84 It appears psychologically evident that the absorption of a rule into one s practical reasoning requires granting the rule a certain authoritative character, which barely is possible if the rule merely befuddles its addressees as an ephemeral and unreliable transitory event in the normative landscape. 85 The slowness required by the principle of steadiness through time does obviously never amount to full normative stagnancy over long periods of time (and thus obsolescence). It merely alerts us to the indispensable character of a balance between constancy and adaptability, the forging of a via media between destructive dislocation and preposterous ossification. 86 As it is the case with the other Fullerian principles we have discussed heretofore, the purpose of the principle of steadiness is to enable the realization of the law s chief function, which is to forge its addressees actions qua responses to the [rules system] rather than qua patterns of conduct that occur independently of the [rules system]. 87 The requirements mandated by the principles adumbrated in the preceding paragraphs governance by general norms, public ascertainability, prospectivity 79 Kramer (n 55) 119 20; Fuller (n 65) 53 4, 56 7. 80 Kramer (n 55) 118. 81 Ibid. 82 Ibid 132. 83 Fuller (n 65) 39. 84 See, for instance, F Ost and M van de Kerchove, De la pyramide au réseau? (FUSL Publ, Brussels 2002) 334 5 (referring to the vis directiva of canon law); P Bourdieu, Les rites comme actes d institution (1982) 43 Actes de recherche en sciences sociales 59 and M Weber, Wirtschaft und Gesellschaft: Grundriß der Verstehenden Soziologie (Mohr Siebeck, Tübingen 1980) in pt II, ch VI s1 (on his concept of Einverständnishandeln). 85 Kramer (n 55) 171. 86 Ibid 170. 87 Ibid 171.