UC Berkeley Berkeley Planning Journal

Similar documents
Learning Through Conflict at Oxford

UNDERSTANDING AND WORKING WITH POWER. Effective Advising in Statebuilding and Peacebuilding Contexts How 2015, Geneva- Interpeace

Theories of Conflict and Conflict Resolution

We the Stakeholders: The Power of Representation beyond Borders? Clara Brandi

Controversy Liberalism, Democracy and the Ethics of Votingponl_

POLI 359 Public Policy Making

Testimony of Michael A. Vatis Partner, Steptoe & Johnson LLP

Power: Interpersonal, Organizational, and Global Dimensions Wednesday, 14 September 2005

Lecture (9) Critical Discourse Analysis

THE RICH HAVE MORE MONEY

The above definition may be amplified at national and/or regional levels.

POL 343 Democratic Theory and Globalization February 11, "The history of democratic theory II" Introduction

Chapter Ten Concluding Remarks on the Future of Natural Resource Management in Borneo

Qualities of Effective Leadership and Its impact on Good Governance

Max Weber. SOCL/ANTH 302: Social Theory. Monday, March 26, by Ronald Keith Bolender

ABSTRACT. Electronic copy available at:

From the veil of ignorance to the overlapping consensus: John Rawls as a theorist of communication

Comments by Nazanin Shahrokni on Erik Olin Wright s lecture, Emancipatory Social Sciences, Oct. 23 rd, 2007, with initial responses by Erik Wright

INTRODUCTION to SOCIOLOGY COURSE OBJECTIVES REQUIRED TEXTS COURSE WORK and EVALUATION OUTLINE: 8 September - 14 September

How to approach legitimacy

9. What can development partners do?

Where does Confucian Virtuous Leadership Stand? A Critique of Daniel Bell s Beyond Liberal Democracy

David Adams UNESCO. From the International Year to a Decade for a Culture of Peace and Non-violence

F A C U L T Y STUDY PROGRAMME FOR POSTGRADUATE STUDIES

Sociological Marxism Volume I: Analytical Foundations. Table of Contents & Outline of topics/arguments/themes

References and further reading

Universal Human Rights in Progressive Thought and Politics

Programme Specification

EMPOWERMENT OF THE WEAKER SECTIONS IN INDIA: CONSTITUTIONAL PROVISIONS AND SAFEGUARDS

JOB DESCRIPTION AMNESTY INTERNATIONAL INTERNATIONAL SECRETARIAT

Nancy Holman Book review: The collaborating planner? Practitioners in the neoliberal age

Action Theory. Collective Conscience. Critical Theory. Determinism. Description

SAMPLE CHAPTERS UNESCO EOLSS POWER AND THE STATE. John Scott Department of Sociology, University of Plymouth, UK

Social Theory and the City. Session 1: Introduction to the Class. Instructor Background:

PEACEBUILDING: APPROACHES TO SOCIAL

1. Introduction. Jonathan Verschuuren

Ideology COLIN J. BECK

LJMU Research Online

Status and the Challenge of Rising Powers by Steven Ward

Whose Rights Are They? Social Justice, HRE Discourse, and the Politics of Knowledge

Notes from discussion in Erik Olin Wright Lecture #2: Diagnosis & Critique Middle East Technical University Tuesday, November 13, 2007

1100 Ethics July 2016

Power and Organizations

Ina Schmidt: Book Review: Alina Polyakova The Dark Side of European Integration.

25th IVR World Congress LAW SCIENCE AND TECHNOLOGY. Frankfurt am Main August Paper Series. No. 055 / 2012 Series D

Aalborg Universitet. Line Nyhagen-Predelle og Beatrice Halsaa Siim, Birte. Published in: Tidsskrift for kjønnsforskning. Publication date: 2014

Professor of Political Theory and Public Policy, School of Public Policy, UCL, UK.

Review of Prudential Public Leadership: Promoting Ethics in Public Policy and Administration. By John Uhr. New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2015.

USING SOCIAL JUSTICE, PUBLIC HEALTH, AND HUMAN RIGHTS TO PREVENT VIOLENCE IN SOUTH AFRICA. Garth Stevens

TOWARDS A JUST ECONOMIC ORDER

Herman, Gabriel Morality and Behaviour in Democratic Athens: A Social History

POLI 111: INTRODUCTION TO THE STUDY OF POLITICAL SCIENCE

Sociology. Sociology 1

22. POLITICAL SCIENCE (Code No. 028)

The Concept of Governance and Public Governance Theories

Review of Christian List and Philip Pettit s Group agency: the possibility, design, and status of corporate agents

The UN Peace Operation and Protection of Human Security: The Case of Afghanistan

Economic philosophy of Amartya Sen Social choice as public reasoning and the capability approach. Reiko Gotoh

Personal, Social and Institutional Dimensions PNE 336, ext Sociology 217 Office hours: T, 2-4;

Lecturer: Dr. Dan-Bright S. Dzorgbo, UG Contact Information:

Participatory Democracy as Philosophy of Science Orientation for Action Research. Erik Lindhult, Mälardalen University, Sweden

Definition: Institution public system of rules which defines offices and positions with their rights and duties, powers and immunities p.

Chapter 1 Sociological Theory Chapter Summary

AMY GUTMANN: THE CONSTRUCTIVE POTENTIAL OF COMMUNITARIAN VALUES DOES GUTMANN SUCCEED IN SHOWING THE CONSTRUCTIVE POTENTIAL OF COMMUNITARIAN VALUES?

Who will speak, and who will listen? Comments on Burawoy and public sociology 1

Ideas for an intelligent and progressive integration discourse

Diplomacy in the 21st Century (2)

Philosophy and Real Politics, by Raymond Geuss. Princeton: Princeton University Press, ix pp. $19.95 (cloth).

Sociology is the study of societies and the way that they shape people s behaviour, beliefs,

Mehrdad Payandeh, Internationales Gemeinschaftsrecht Summary

3. Framing information to influence what we hear

Western Philosophy of Social Science

Detailed Contents. The European Roots of Sociological Theory 1

POLI 111: INTRODUCTION TO THE STUDY OF POLITICAL SCIENCE

TRANSCEND: Person, Network, and Method. By Rebecca Joy Norlander. December 27, 2007

Unit 1: Foundational Concepts of Politics. 1a: Situate the academic discipline of political science within the broader field of social science.

Market, State, and Community

Book Review. Evidence for Hope: Making Human Rights Work in the 21 st Century. Matheus de Carvalho Hernandez*

The key building blocks of a successful implementation of the Sustainable Development Goals

Can the Future of Work become its past?

An Inconvenient Truth. Politics, Economics, and Ethics

enforce people s contribution to the general good, as everyone naturally wants to do productive work, if they can find something they enjoy.

South East European University Tetovo, Republic of Macedonia 2 ND CYCLE PROGRAM IN PUBLIC ADMINISTRATION. Master studies - Academic Diplomacy

The Global State of Democracy

Governors State University GSU Chicago, Illinois Federal University of Minas Gerais, Belo Horizonte, MG and

UNDERGRADUATE PROGRAMME IN POLITICAL SCIENCE. Semester: 5 Paper No: Public administration: theory and practice

Rethinking Migration Decision Making in Contemporary Migration Theories

The Paradoxes of Terrorism

Business Ethics Journal Review

How Zambian Newspapers

The strategic role of the mass media in strengthening the discourse of moderation and rationality

Last time we discussed a stylized version of the realist view of global society.

WIKIPEDIA IS NOT A GOOD ENOUGH SOURCE FOR AN ACADEMIC ASSIGNMENT

Defining Accountability

Representation of Minority under Deliberative Democracy and the Proportional Representation System in the Republic of Korea*

Summary. A deliberative ritual Mediating between the criminal justice system and the lifeworld. 1 Criminal justice under pressure

Funded by the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council Strategic Research

Prentice Hall. Sociology: A Down-to-Earth Approach, 9th Edition (Henslin) High School. Indiana Academic Standards - Social Studies Sociology

International Relations. Policy Analysis

Lecture 17. Sociology 621. The State and Accumulation: functionality & contradiction

Transcription:

UC Berkeley Berkeley Planning Journal Title Planning in the Face of Power by John Forester Permalink https://escholarship.org/uc/item/6299b40d Journal Berkeley Planning Journal, 4(1) ISSN 1047-5192 Author Fischler, Raphael Publication Date 1989-01-01 Peer reviewed escholarship.org Powered by the California Digital Library University of California

TOWARD AN ETHICAL AND POLITICALLY CRITICAL PlANNING THEORY AND PRACTICE Raphael Fischler Review of: john Forester's Planning in the Face of Power (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1989; 283 pp.) The propertyless masses especially are not served by a formal "equality before the law" and a "calculable" adjudication and administration, as demanded by "bourgeois" interests. Naturally, in their eyes justice and administration should serve to compensate for their economic and social life opportunities in the fa ce of propertied classes. justice and administration can fulfil this function only if they assume an informal character to a far-reaching extent. It must be informal because it is substantively "ethical. Max Weber1 john Forester's new book pursues several objectives: to apply critical social theory to the study of planning, to make sense of the microprocesses that constitute planning practice, and to help planners be progressive practitioners. Forester brings together, in a single volume, essays which have appeared in various journals since 1980 and which have been reworked as chapters for this publication. The key conceptual development in this work consists of redefining planning in terms of communicative action and of refining advocacy planning with "the practical recognition of systematic sources of misinformation" (p. 46). For Forester, planning involves not only technical analysis, but primarily a clash of arguments and social identities. Progressive planning therefore requires arguing and organizing, as well as an emancipation from oppressive structures. His is an important, valuable, praiseworthy work. As a planning theorist, Forester follows the precepts which he sets for the planner: h raises public awareness, defines problems, and sets agendas. He draws our attention to the ethical and political dimensions of planning, arguing that "progressive planning... is at once a democratizing and a practical organizing process" (p. 47). He defines the problem facing planners as the domination of citizens by "concentrations of economic power" (p. xi). This domination is played out and maintained, in a society where the use of private force is illegal, by means of distorted communication. Some people are able to exert power, Forester writes, because "they very selectively inform and misinform citizens" (p. 45) and thereby manage their beliefs and knowledge, their consent, their trust, and their understanding or definition of problems. They do so in three ways: (1) they "inform or misinform citizens effectively by virtue of their ability to prevail in formal decision-making situations;" 125

Berkeley Planning Journal (2) they exert power in the setting of agendas, by "controlling which citizens find out what and when, about which projects, which options, and what they might be able to do as a result;" and (3) they "shape the self-conceptions, the sense of legitimate expectations, and finally the needs of the citizens" (p. 44). Here, Forester could have added that domination in urban development also shapes "the self-conceptions [and] the sense of legitimate expectations," the role-frames of planners themselves. (We will come back to that issue below.) Finally, the author sets the agenda for planning research and education by arguing that planning has an "anticipatory character." Researchers and educators should develop planners' ability to anticipate problems as well as make them aware of the relationship of micro-processes of communication to macro-processes of both domination and emancipation from such domination. Planning practice, then, "consists of the elements of envisioning a problem situation, managing arguments concerning it, and negotiating strategically to intervene" (p. 207; italics in original). With his "critical-communicative account of planning" (p. 11), Forester presents a very compelling and fertile model. His source of inspiration is critical social theory, in particular Juergen Habermas's theory of universal pragmatics and of communicative action. Forester does recognize the limitations of the work of the German philosopher-cum-socialscientist 2 and works to compensate for them, particularly in terms of empirical application. Yet he follows Habermas, in some chapters at least, in putting more weight on abstract systems of ideal types than on systematic analyses of social reality. In that sense, Planning in the Face of Power presents not so much an empirical analysis of planning practice as a conceptual framework for further analysis. 3 Such future analysis should, in turn, make up for the lack of political-economic, historic, and psychological dimensions in this book, a shortcoming which Forester himself recognizes. It is important to understand that conceptual framework and to see how it differs from those that (used to) dominate planning thought. Forester's goal is to constitute a theory of planning practice - a theory that does not confuse planning with problem-solving or with urban development and that describes planning in different fields of governmental activity (land-use, economic development, health, etc.). The myth of Rationality makes room for a critique of speech acts; the political economy of the city is replaced, under the spotlight, by "political legitimacy; "procedural fairness and accountability; and "interpersonal ethics" (p. 161 ). Planning is thus about attention and arguments, but only marginally about plans and implementation; its context is a system of hegemony rather than one of urban development. The research agenda that Forester proposes (pp. 1 57-162) indicates that his analytic framework holds promise for a systematic understanding of how plan- 126

Ethical and Critical Planning Theory and Practice, Fischler ning works across various fields. Yet for this general theory to be refined into theories of land-use planning, health planning, and the like, substance has to be added to procedure, product to process, and the "political-economic dynamics" which this book "omits" (p. 162) have to be brought back into the picture. 4 One area that needs particular attention is, I believe, the organizational and political position of the planner. Planning practice, for instance that of urban planners, cannot be fully understood without a detailed analysis of planners' position in the "socio-spatial development process" 5 and their specific contribution to it. Although this book gives little explicit treatment to the position of the planner, its core ideas have important implications for the relationship of planners to the institutions in which they practice. By framing the task of planners in terms of communicative action and their responsibility in terms of distortions of communication, Forester redefines what gives planning its legitimacy and what constitutes a planner's professional discretion. The shift here is away from expertise and efficiency, and toward ethical commitment and equity. The emphasis is not on what planners know but on how they distribute their knowledge, not on their ability to solve problems but on opening up debate about them, not on public trust in planners' expertise but on individual trust in their integrity, 6 not on consent to planners drawing up plans but on consent to their mediating debate. To the extent that expertise does matter, political savvy now pushes technical skill into the background. The planner has become a midwife of new social identities, helping people to recognize their "real" situations and their "true" interests. Forester's professionals thus find legitimacy not so much in their educational certification and in their relationship to the Prince as in their contribution to democracy. They rely less on the authority of their social position than on the authority of the better (i.e. critical) argument. Their discretion lies more in their ability to engage in informal "organizing strategies" than in their mandate to make decisions according to their expert judgement. Forester's book thus creates an image of the planner not as a bureaucrat but as a social activist. Herein, of course, lies the problem: planners may be and probably should be activists, but they are and remain bureaucrats. Both aspects are inseparable: planning is, at best, "a 'critical' governmental activity'' (Beauregard 1988: 73). "Critical" means, for instance, that "the work of planners and public administrators might be directed specifically to social and labor movements working to attain structural changes in the present politicaleconomy" (p. 61). This type of "nonreformist reform" work makes sense only if one assumes that the government supports it and/or that planners can perform it despite their bureaucratic status and politicaleconomic position. These are precisely the assumptions that Forester 127

Berkeley Planning Journal makes, and he calls on two aspects of planning practice to support his case. First, he believes that "bureaucrats [can] appeal to the principles of formal equality and procedural democracy" (p. 60) to which government is formally committed. Planners who help give a voice to hitherto silent citizens are only doing their duty under the law. He argues, in addition, that "how much planners can do... depends not only on their formal responsibilities but also on their informal initiatives. [Thanks to the complexity and, hence, uncertainty of the planning process], planning staff can exercise substantial discretion and exert important influence as a result" (p. 84). It is probable, however, that Forester, having opted for agency and not for structure, over-estimates the freedom of planners in their job. More importantly, he does not explicitly apply to planners what he has highlighted in the case of citizens: domination involves the systematic distortion of people's identity, understanding, and action -- or in Foucault's words, the constitution of subjects. Forces of domination not only use power, they institutionalize it. Forester recognizes that the "organizational and political contexts of [planners'] practice [are] structures of selective attention, of systematically distorted communication" (p. 139) and he must know that, by definition as it were, "advocacy is incompatible with organizational [i.e. bureaucratic] perspectives." What he therefore implicitly expects, is that planners free themselves, in consciousness and in action, from the institutions, the agendas, and organizations, that frame their work. Hence the need for a critical planning education. Forester devotes a whole chapter to education, and he insists that it should help future practitioners anticipate problems and develop persuasive arguments. He could have carried his logic one step further. According to this logic, planning schools should also emancipate future planners from traditional planning ideology and empower them to become activists. That may not square very well with the views of those planners who currently grant, renew, or refuse school accreditation, but there is hope.... The issue of the social position of the planner is important in another way, namely with respect to the problem of power itself. I believe that the title to this book -- "Planning in the Face of Power" -- is not really representative of Forester's ideas and their implications. A more representative title, but perhaps less catchy, would have been: "Planning in the Face of Domination" or even "Planning in the Face of Hegemony." Forester differentiates between legitimate and illegitimate power, but he does not give full expression to the distinction. Power is legitimate when people freely consent to its exercise, if the relationship of dependency, deference, trust, and consideration between the rulers and the ruled results from rational agreement. Similarly, distortion of communication is acceptable if it follows from the "legitimate division of labor" (p. 34), itself grounded in rational agreement. This means two things. 128

Ethical and Critical Planning Theory and Practice, Fischler First, one need not stretch these ideas very far to come to the conclusion that planners do not enjoy a legitimacy of rational agreement and, hence, that they exercise illegitimate power. Which is why, as I mentioned above, they can seemingly gain legitimacy only through deserving actions, by contributing to freedom, justice, and democracy, to the "ideal speech situation." The danger is, of course, that some planners will be forced to choose between added legitimacy and their monthly paycheck. (Be progressive? Yes, but be cautious.) Secondly, power is clearly inevitable and not necessarily negative, destructive, and stifling. This is obvious in the case of legitimate power. But it is also true for power in general. Building physical and organizational structures in the city means making hard choices, choices doomed not to please everyone, whatever Habermas says about the "generalizability" of interests. If planning is to be more than defining problems and arguing about them, if it is to lead to concrete change in the city, it cannot do without power, nor can it do solely with power grounded in consensus. "The moral obli tion of the politician is to use power to improve the human condition." The same holds for the planner. Forester, of course, knows this all too well. The great irony of his theory is that while the behavior of planners (and others) in the planning process must be judged against the standards of communicative action (i.e. action aimed at reaching consensus), their success in the development process depends on strategic action (i.e., action aimed at furthering a specific agenda and particular interests). Forester's analysis makes clear not only that the distortion of communication is a major problem in planning but also that planners are, under the present circumstances, not served by complete transparency and openness. The dilemma is one between political legitimacy and political efficacy: while the former is rooted in formal agreements, the latter is nourished by informal action. In other words, while the authority of planners resides in their institutional position and in their technical expertise, their power stems from their informal initiatives and social-political skills. The duality of the planner's mandate "to press professionally... for substantive goals" and "to bring about a participatory process" (p. 1 00) is a source of tension: reaching "substantive goals" in the city takes more than planning and more than communicative action, even if the quality of the planning process partly determines the quality of the planning product. This "irony" does not signal a weakness in Forester's theory, but its realism: improving the planning process is important, but given the present circumstances, more than that is needed to improve the city itself. Planners who wish to be agents of change must at the same time rely on and transcend, if not transform, their official status. In this respect, Forester's insistence on agency "in the face of' structure must be commended. He is "structurally critical yet hardly fatalistic" (p. 47) 129

Berkeley Planning Journal and he calls for resistance and organization, for the creation and maintenance of urban social movements. Even if it renders his vision selective -- indeterminacy over determinacy, informality over formality - it is Forester's dedication to emancipation and empowerment that make his work so valuable. His conceptualization of planning as praxis has no equal in planning theory, and his recommendations to improve it - although not always new -- are unique for their practical and political value. This book, he writes, seeks... to show just what public-serving planning practitioners can do... not in theory but in practice, in an organizationally messy world of political inequality and economic exploitation, and in response to Paul Goodman's continually nagging practical question, "Now what?" (p. 13) Planners, answers Forester, can support citizens victimized by an unequal distribution of resources; they can help organize social movements and provide them much needed information and expertise; and they can share with people their understanding of structural factors in urban development. The primary tools of this progressive practice are "the practical anticipation of problem situations" (p. 164) and "the selective, communicative organizing or disorganizing of attention" (p. 11 ). In so conceptualizing planning, Forester will probably attract little sympathy from professionals who do not wish to confuse "reactive planning [with) real planning." 8 On the other hand, he will enable others to give legitimacy and cogency to their claims for non-technical and nonregulatory activities. Recent research, to which Forester refers, indicates that the road from paralyzing self-perceptions and powerlessness to emancipation and empowerment is long and arduous. 9 Those who do not choose this road may very well be left with a good deal of guilt, for the planning theorist has shown that they could, if they wanted, act on their moral responsibility -- despite the constraints and the threats. Although it does not make the road to progressive practice any shorter, Forester's book is a guide for the journey. 130

Ethical and Critical Planning Theory and Practice, Fischler NOTES The title of this review is borrowed from the book, p. 162. Many thanks to Michael Teitz for comments on an earlier draft. 1 From Gerth and Mills (1946: 221). 2 For example, in Forester (1986). 3 Forester has already engaged himself in more systematically empirical work, in structured applications of his analytic framework. 4 Chapter 6 of the book illustrates this point: as it focusses on a specific area of planning (land-use planning), it comes to rely more on institutional and political-economic factors in its analysis. sr he expression is Philip Cook's (1983), who precisely calls for theories that "reintegrate planning theory and development theory." 6.-r rust is an issue of yourintegrity in the planning process," remarks a planner interviewed by Forester; p. 93. 7 Ed Broadbent, fanner leader of the Canadian N DP, on National Public Radio, CBC broadcast on Sunday, March 5, 1989. 8 Solnit 1987: 41. 9 0n p. 67, Forester refers to Baum (1983) and to Howe and Kaufman (1979). See also Hoch (1988: 25-34). REFERENCES Baum, Howell. 1983. Planners and Public Expectations. Cambridge, Mass.: Schenkman. Beauregard, Robert A. 1988. "Bringing the City Back ln."' Paper presented at A.C.S.P. Conference, Buffalo, New York. Cook, Philip. 1983. Theories of Planning and Spatial Development. london: Hutchinson. Forester, john. 1986. "Critical Theory and Public life: Only Connect." In International journal of Urban and Regional Research, 10(2): 185-206. Gerth, H.H., and C. Wright Mills, eds. 1946. From Max Weber: Essays in Sociology. New York: Oxford University Press. Hoch, Charles. 1988. "Conflict at large: A National Survey of Planners and Political Conflict." journal of Planning Education and Research (Fall): Howe, Elizabeth, and jerome Kaufman. 1979. "The Ethics of Contemporary American Planners." journal of the American Planning Association, 45: 243-255. Lipsky, Michael. 1980. Street-Level Bureaucracy. New York: Russell Sage Foundation. Solnit, Albert. The job of the Planning Commissioner. 3rd edition, Washington, D.C.: APA Planners Press. Weber, Max. 1958. The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism. New York: Charles Scribner's Sons. 131