THE AUSTRALIAN NATIONAL UNIVERSITY

Similar documents
Further key insights from the Indigenous Community Governance Project, 2006

Politics between Philosophy and Democracy

Who will speak, and who will listen? Comments on Burawoy and public sociology 1

REVIEW. Statutory Interpretation in Australia

The Development of Classical Administrative Law and Modern Threats to it. Professor Christopher Forsyth University of Hong Kong 12 th April 2018

Book Review of The Justices of the United States Supreme Court

The Lobbying Code of Conduct: An Appraisal

Foreign bribery Views from the coal-face. March 2016 Publication No

Common law reasoning and institutions

Reflections on Citizens Juries: the case of the Citizens Jury on genetic testing for common disorders

Follow this and additional works at: Part of the Law Commons

Queensland Schools Constitutional Convention. Tuesday 2 March 2004, 9am Banco Court

Maureen Molloy and Wendy Larner

Submission on Theft, Fraud and Bribery and related offences in the Criminal Code

CONTEXTUALISM AND GLOBAL JUSTICE

Property Law Part IV. Tibisay Morgandi. Research Block Four

First Among Equals: The Supreme Court in American Life Kenneth W. Starr New York: Warner Books, 2002, 320 pp.

DISSENTING OPINIONS. Yale Law Journal. Volume 14 Issue 4 Yale Law Journal. Article 1

The University of Chicago Law Review

OVERVIEW OF A RECOGNITION AND IMPLEMENTATION OF INDIGENOUS RIGHTS FRAMEWORK

worthwhile to pose several basic questions regarding this notion. Should the Insular Cases be simply discarded? Can they be simply

The Mason Papers Leslie Zines. All rights reserved.

A Perspective on the Economy and Monetary Policy

Picture an almost irresistible force meeting an almost immovable. object. On the one hand, the United States was determined to force the

Knowledge about Conflict and Peace

558 March 28, 2019 No. 15 IN THE SUPREME COURT OF THE STATE OF OREGON

A SECOND CHANCE FOR THE HARM PRINCIPLE IN SECTION 7? GROSS DISPROPORTIONALITY POST-BEDFORD

Pleading Guilty in Lower Courts

RATIONALITY AND POLICY ANALYSIS

Conference on The Paradox of Judicial Independence Held at Institute of Government 22nd June 2015

INTRODUCTION TO READING & BRIEFING CASES AND OUTLINING

Fixed Fee Adjudication and Enforcement Service

The Provision of Public Goods, and the Matter of the Revelation of True Preferences: Two Views

Electoral Reform Proposal

The public vs. private value of health, and their relationship. (Review of Daniel Hausman s Valuing Health: Well-Being, Freedom, and Suffering)

Holmes and Hand. By Patrick Ward. Member of the Class of 2014 at Elon University School of Law

SUBMISSION OF THE SCOTTISH LAW COMMISSION ON THE CONTRACT (THIRD PARTY RIGHTS) (SCOTLAND) BILL

TECHNICAL ASPECTS OF IMPLEMENTATION OF THE 1996 HAGUE PROTECTION OF CHILDREN CONVENTION RESOLUTION S RESPONSE TO THE MINISTRY OF JUSTICE

Institutional engagement

The Advantages and Disadvantages of Permanent Intermediate Courts of Appeal

HUMAN SETTLEMENT DEVELOPMENT Vol. IV - Greening London: Sustainability, Politics and the Third Way - Anne Bartlett

Dorin Iulian Chiriţoiu

Future Directions for Multiculturalism

VERBATIM PROCEEDINGS YALE LAW SCHOOL CONFERENCE FIRST AMENDMENT -- IN THE SHADOW OF PUBLIC HEALTH

Discussion seminar: charitable initiatives for journalism and media summary

Charles I Plosser: A progress report on our monetary policy framework

FRAMEWORK OF THE AFRICAN GOVERNANCE ARCHITECTURE (AGA)

The Role of the Courts following Referral of Power - Some Brief Comments by Justice R P Austin Supreme Court of New South Wales

American Bar Association House of Delegates

Comparative and International Education Society. Awards: An Interim Report. Joel Samoff

A Study of the California Penalty Jury in First- Degree-Murder Cases

CHAPTER 1 PROLOGUE: VALUES AND PERSPECTIVES

CHAPTER 2: DISPUTE SETTLEMENT

Review of Prudential Public Leadership: Promoting Ethics in Public Policy and Administration. By John Uhr. New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2015.

The Role of the Police in Building Community Identity Among Young People 1

The Role of Legal Advisers in International Law

Lecture Notes Atkins v. Virginia, 536 U.S (2002) Keith Burgess-Jackson 29 April 2016

2015 HIGH SCHOOL MOOTING COMPETITION

On Democratic Reason Ira Katznelson [Hertie School, June 12, 2018]

REDEMPTION, FAITH AND THE POST-CIVIL WAR AMENDMENT PARADOX: THE TALK

JULIUS STONE AND THE STUDY OF LAW AND SOCIETY IN AUSTRALIA

Address Kees Sterk, President of the ENCJ Budapest, 10 July 2018 Meeting with OBT

Chapter 1 The Problem of Judicial Independence

Dialogues between International and Public Law. A conference organised by BIICL and Melbourne Law School Thursday 30 June Friday 1 July 2016, London

A TIME FOR CHANGE THE GARDA SÍOCHÁNA CORPORATE STRA CORPORA TEGY TE STRA

The Doctrine of Judicial Review and Natural Law

Introduction[1] The obstacle

REALIST LAWYERS AND REALISTIC LEGALISTS: A BRIEF REBUTTAL TO JUDGE POSNER

Analysis of legal issues and information tips on how to respond critically

To Say What the Law Is: Judicial Authority in a Political Context Keith E. Whittington PROSPECTUS THE ARGUMENT: The volume explores the political

February 24, 2009: DA Carney's Testimony to NYSBA Task Force on Wrongful Convictions

INTRODUCTION THE HONORABLE HELEN WILSON NIES*

Socio-Legal Course Descriptions

JUDGMENT. R v Sally Lane and John Letts (AB and CD) (Appellants)

TSR Interview with Dr. Richard Bush* July 3, 2014

Proceduralism and Epistemic Value of Democracy

RESPONDING TO CHALLENGERS Conflict, change and leadership

Jus in Bello through the Lens of Individual Moral Responsibility: McMahan on Killing in War

Judges, Parliament and the Government the new relationship Transcript of a lecture by Rt Hon Lord Woolf

Council for Security Cooperation in the Asia Pacific

The Dickson Poon School of Law. King s LLM. International Dispute Resolution module descriptions for prospective students

Proposed Amendments to the Bar s Open Meeting Rules

The Proper Metric of Justice in Justice as Fairness

Communicating a Systematic Monetary Policy

The Language of Law and More Probable Than Not : Some Brief Thoughts

The Japanese rule on cross-border insolvency had been severely criticized by many foreign lawyers 1, because it

The Federal Courts. Chapter 16

Last time we discussed a stylized version of the realist view of global society.

IMMIGRATION LAW PRACTITIONERS' ASSOCIATION

English Law, UK Courts and UK Legal Services after Brexit

Consultation Response

Advisory Committee on Enforcement

Volume 60, Issue 1 Page 241. Stanford. Cass R. Sunstein

PUBLIC CONTROL OF BUSINESS REVISITED

Impeachment: Advice and Dissent

Regional Autonomies and Federalism in the Context of Internal Self-Determination

Justice Andrea Hoch: It is my pleasure. Thank you for inviting me.

How Legal Pluralism Is and Is Not Distinct from Liberalism: A Response to Dennis Patterson and Alexis Galán

Judicial Review, Competence and the Rational Basis Theory

Consultation on TLAB Rules of Practice and Procedures and Related Documents

Transcription:

THE AUSTRALIAN NATIONAL UNIVERSITY ANU COLLEGE OF LAW Social Science Research Network Legal Scholarship Network ANU College of Law Research Paper No. 10-31 Michael Coper CONSTITUTIONAL ADJUDICATION AND DEMOCRACY: One Voice Or Many? http://ssrn.com/authorid=358025 http://ssrn.com/abstract=1633210

INTERNATIONAL ASSOCIATION OF LAW SCHOOLS (IALS) CONFERENCE ON CONSTITUTIONAL LAW American University Washington College of Law and Georgetown University Law Center Washington DC, USA, 11 12 September 2009 CONSTITUTIONAL ADJUDICATION AND DEMOCRACY: One Voice Or Many? Michael Coper 1 Charles Evans Hughes pithy remark in 1907 that the Constitution is what the judges say it is 2 sparked a vigorous, and probably never-ending, debate about the tension between the objective and subjective elements in judicial law-making. In contested cases of constitutional interpretation in a multi-member final appellate court, can there be one right view, produced by the objective application of an external standard, or is the prevailing view merely the accidental consequence of the aggregation of individual subjective opinion to form a view that happens to have majority support? 3 I am going to leave hanging this large jurisprudential perennial, and devote this short (IALS-mandated 3-5 page) paper to an intriguing subset of the question. Whether the judges are discovering an objective truth or whether the legal system merely deems it to be so by giving authoritative effect to the opinion of the officials charged with the task of resolving disputed questions, 4 should the judges speak with one voice or many? My focus here is not so much on the permissibility 5 or desirability 6 of dissent, but rather on the question of whether the view of the court, or a majority of the court, should be 1 Dean and Robert Garran Professor of Law, Australian National University College of Law, Canberra, Australia; Member, IALS Governing Board. 2 Addresses and Papers of Charles Evans Hughes (1908) 133, 139 (cited in Fred R Shapiro, The Oxford Dictionary of American Legal Quotations (1993) 216). Interestingly, Hughes, later a Chief Justice of the United States Supreme Court, became concerned that this remark was widely taken to be highly critical of the Court, when he purported merely to be referring to the Court's essential function: The Autobiographical Notes of Charles Evans Hughes (1973) 143-144 (also cited in Shapiro, op cit). 3 See Michael Coper, Encounters with the Australian Constitution (1987) 400-422; Tony Blackshield, 'Realism' in Tony Blackshield, Michael Coper and George Williams (eds), The Oxford Companion to the High Court of Australia (2001) 582-585. 4 United States Supreme Court Justice Robert Jackson captured this beautifully in his well-known aphorism that we are not final because we are infallible, but we are infallible only because we are final : Brown v Allen (1953) 344 US 443, 540. 5 The UK s Privy Council did not allow dissent until it bowed to pressure in 1966 from Australian Chief Justice Garfield Barwick: see Tony Blackshield, Michael Coper and Jack Goldring, 'Privy Council' in Tony Blackshield, Michael Coper and George Williams (eds), The Oxford Companion to the High Court of Australia (2001) 560.

2 expressed in a single consolidated opinion of the court, or rather in a multiplicity of individual opinions. 7 The very posing of this question may come as a surprise to my IALS colleagues at this conference. My impression though I stand willing to be corrected (the opportunity for which is a major benefit of IALS gatherings) is that most appellate courts around the world do not exhibit the latitude for individual self-expression that has been an enduring feature of the modus operandi of the High Court of Australia for over a century. 8 Yet the practice in Australia has, in some quarters, been a cause for concern. As a consequence, I am currently engaged with some ANU colleagues in an empirical study, commissioned by the National Judicial College of Australia, of what the consumers of judicial opinions 9 think of the relative merits of multiple opinions as against an opinion of the court, or at least of a majority of the court. The project was sparked by a concern that multiple opinions in support of a common outcome are a recipe for uncertainty and lack of clarity in the law, and come at a social and economic cost. Yet there are robust arguments on both sides, and I use this paper to sketch out those arguments in broad outline, concluding with some thoughts on where the issue sits in the context of the conference theme of constitutional adjudication and democracy. In favour of the collective opinion The arguments for a consolidated opinion of the court, or a majority of the court, are clear enough. Clarity, and consequently certainty, are best served, so it is argued, when the court speaks with one voice. Litigants know where they stand, lower courts know what they must follow, lawyers know how to advise their clients, students more easily know what the law is, and the community has a knowable framework of laws within which to go about its business. Moreover, cases can be disposed of more efficiently, and more cases can be dealt with in a given time frame. To state the same argument from the other side, a multitude of ways of stating the same conclusion leaves the law in a state of doubt, delivers a much more onerous task to those who have to master it, and slows down the whole process of case disposal. 6 The theory and practice of dissent has been comprehensively explored in Australia by Andrew Lynch: see, for example, 'The Intelligence of a Future Day: The Vindication of Constitutional Dissent in the High Court Australia 1981-2003' (2007) Sydney Law Review 195; 'Does The High Court Disagree More Often In Constitutional Cases? A Statistical Study Of Judgment Delivery 1981-2003' (2005) 33 Federal Law Review 485; 'Taking Delight in Being Contrary, Frightened of Being a Loner or Simply Indifferent - How Do Judges Really Feel About Dissent?: Cass Sunstein's Why Societies Need Dissent' (2004) 32 Federal Law Review 311; 'Is Judicial Dissent Constitutionally Protected?' (2004) 4 Macquarie Law Journal 81; 'Dissent: The Rewards and Risks of Judicial Disagreement in the High Court of Australia' (2003) 27 Melbourne University Law Review 724; 'Dissent: Towards a Methodology for Measuring Judicial Disagreement in the High Court of Australia' (2002) 24 Sydney Law Review 470. 7 See generally Michael Coper, 'Joint Judgments and Separate Judgments' in Tony Blackshield, Michael Coper and George Williams (eds), The Oxford Companion to the High Court of Australia (2001) 367-369; also 'Concurring Judgments', 129-130. 8 The High Court of Australia confusingly called the High Court rather than the Supreme Court of Australia, evidently to distinguish it from the Supreme Courts of the States within the Australian federation was established in 1903, and has unambiguously been Australia's final appellate court since the abolition of Privy Council appeals, a staged process that was completed in 1986. 9 Lower courts, legal advisers, academic lawyers, the media, litigants, and of course citizens at large.

3 In favour of multiple opinions On the other hand, there are powerful arguments in favour of each judge stating his or her view in a separate, individual opinion. First, the certainty claimed for a single consolidated opinion is often illusory. The achievement of agreement amongst powerful individual judicial minds may require a degree of compromise that glosses over issues perhaps peripheral to the instant case but of potential importance to the future development of the law. Experienced legal advisers sometimes prefer to know the nuance of individual opinion in order to better predict the course of future development, even if that necessitates a greater investment of time and effort. 10 Academic lawyers may similarly appreciate the richness of the raw material that comprises the basis of their scholarly analysis and speculation. (Trial judges, though, will most likely spurn subtlety and yearn for unvarnished clarity to inform their rulings and jury directions and thus render them less vulnerable on appeal.) Secondly, the giving of reasons by each individual judge is often seen as the best assurance that the judge has truly and conscientiously turned his or her mind to the question and provided a transparent and examinable justification for his or her decision. The judicial oath may even be invoked to demand such transparency. Collective opinions may be a cover for laziness or even undue influence; Thomas Jefferson certainly thought so in 1820 when he described the United States Supreme Court as huddled up in a conclave and characterized Chief Justice John Marshall as a crafty Chief Justice who, with the silent acquiescence of lazy or timid associates, sophisticates the law to his own mind by the turn of his own reasoning. 11 In other words, whatever the efficiency gains of collective decision-making, in the sphere of pronouncements by final appellate courts the practice may be seen to threaten the very integrity of the judicial process. 12 Thirdly, aficionados of constitutional interpretation well understand the endemic complexity and subtlety of the task, and the wide range of principles and values competing for attention, and will rarely be surprised at the diversity of opinion this produces. If these differences are subsumed into collective opinions, that may distort the world as it really is. We may need to accept the wisdom of Oliver Wendell Holmes that certainty generally is illusion, and repose is not the destiny of man. 13 10 Less defensibly, there is a consequent risk of greater cost to the client, unless advisers treat keeping up to date with the law as their general responsibility or defray the cost over their practice as a whole. 11 Thomas Jefferson, Letter to Thomas Ritchie, 25 December 1820, in Paul Ford (ed), Writings of Thomas Jefferson (1899) 10:171, cited in Shapiro, above n 2, 307. Similarly, Australian Chief Justice John Latham observed in 1950 that I am now finding it possible to adopt (the method of assigning one judge to write the judgment of the Court) more frequently, but it has to be watched in order to prevent a tendency which, I suggest, has at times been most odious in the Privy Council, to leave it to one judge to do all the work and really make up the mind of the Court : correspondence from The Papers of Sir John Latham, cited in Coper, above n 7, 368, and searchable at http://catalogue.nla.gov.au/record/3662490. 12 I am speaking here of domestic appellate courts, and of judicial independence in the sense of the independence of the judges from each other. It may be that, in relation to at least some international tribunals, the independence of those tribunals from external pressure (for example, from member states) is, by contrast, better protected by a collective view of the tribunal and non-disclosure of individual opinion. 13 Oliver Wendell Holmes, 'The Path of the Law' (1897) 10 Harvard Law Review 457, 465; Collected Legal Papers (1920) 181.

4 How important are reasons anyway? Of course, this debate makes a number of assumptions. First, it assumes that, in the tension between the competing demands of process and outcome, between the need for reasons and the imperative for decision, reasoning and justification have an important role to play. 14 Some societies especially those in the western common law tradition may value this more highly than others. Some may prioritise execution over deliberation. I will be interested to discover at this IALS conference to what extent this tension is culture-bound, and how it plays out across the range of decision-making processes, not just in the judicial sphere but also in legislative and administrative processes and in other facets of public and private governance. Variations even within a shared tradition Secondly, even within the common law tradition, there is a wide spectrum of ways in which the opinions of final appellate courts find expression. Despite Jefferson s angst about the dominance of Chief Justice Marshall, pressure of business long ago entrenched in the United States Supreme Court the practice of an opinion of the court moderated frequently by separate pluralities and occasionally by individual glosses, but with the attention of commentators grabbed mainly by the strong tradition of dissent while in Australia, despite an irregular pattern of joint judgments of two or more judges, a single opinion of the court, or of the majority, is by far the exception rather than the rule. In part, this is because there is no formal procedure in Australia analogous to the conferencing of the United States Supreme Court judges to allocate the opinion writing; 15 but does the practice drive the culture, or the culture drive the practice? Certainly, in the High Court of Australia there is a well-entrenched ethos of rugged individualism, and it will be interesting, when the results come in of our survey of the consumers of High Court judgments, 16 to see not only whether this ethos is seen to be sustainable, but also whether it is seen to be the product of what might be called the good justifications set out above, or rather of some less attractive personality traits such as arrogance, stubbornness, or self-indulgence. Balancing competing goals in our constitutional ecosystems In truth, the tension between collectivism and individualism in judicial decision-making in final appellate courts reflects our desire to achieve a range of competing goals simultaneously. We value collective opinions because they represent consensus, clarity, certainty, and stability, whereas we value individual opinions because we associate them with individual responsibility, fluidity, difference, diversity, and more easily detectable harbingers of change. I suppose that any constitutional ecosystem will seek to strike a 14 See Tony Blackshield, 'Judicial Reasoning' in Tony Blackshield, Michael Coper and George Williams (eds), The Oxford Companion to the High Court of Australia (2001) 373-376. 15 See Troy Simpson, 'Conferences' in Tony Blackshield, Michael Coper and George Williams (eds), The Oxford Companion to the High Court of Australia (2001) 130-133. More recently, there has been conferencing of a sort: see Michael Kirby, 'Ten Years in the High Court: Continuity and Change' (2005) 27 Australian Bar Review 4, 15-16. 16 The results of a pilot study, involving interviews with a random selection of lower court judges, senior practitioners and senior academic lawyers, are to be presented immediately after this IALS conference, at the Australian Legal Convention in Perth, Western Australia, on 19 September 2009.

5 balance between these goals, and will achieve a balance that both varies over time and differs from that achieved in other systems. 17 It is a balance we are all familiar with, though we tend to think about it more in the macro-context of our legal system and its panoply of institutions than in the microcontext of how our final appellate court finds its own style 18 and modus operandi. It is a balance between certainty and flexibility, between continuity and change, between consensus and diversity, between corporatism and individualism, between accountability and independence, between expedition and due deliberation, perhaps even between skepticism and faith. Understanding how we react to and evaluate that balance may need the insights of a range of other disciplines such as philosophy, sociology and psychology. One voice or many in the context of democratic theory Where, then, does this issue of whether a final appellate court should issue the product of its collective will or tolerate individual idiosyncrasy sit in the context of constitutional adjudication and democracy? 19 The most familiar, the most fundamental, and the most enduring debate about constitutional adjudication and democracy is of course the debate about the legitimacy of judicial review: what justifies the second-guessing, by unelected judges, of the legislative and executive actions of our elected officials? 20 As we know, the answer lies partly in the abstract notion of the law teased out by the high priests of ratiocination and given authoritative force by the state. In this kind of arrangement, there is, however, no room for mere judicial fiat; the pronouncements of the high priests must be persuasive. Which, then, is the more persuasive statement of the law: the fuzzy compromise of a judicial collective, or the elusive common ground embedded in individual variations? I dare say there is no single right answer to this question or any simple resolution of the dilemma. The mere fact of having a multi-member court, coupled with the expectation of (and arguably duty to give) reasons, may be seen as more significant to the justification of judicial review than the form in which those reasons are expressed. 21 Moreover, in the pragmatic spirit of the common law, gains can be made in incremental improvements to the ways in which our constitutional systems function, whether they lean towards the collective or the individual approach to judicial adjudication. To the extent, for example, 17 Interestingly, part of the balance lies in the very idea of having a multi-member appellate court rather than a single judge. Whether expressed in consolidated or fragmented form, the judgment of a multimember court already proffers a safeguard against individual subjectivity. 18 Michael Meehan, 'Judicial Style' in Tony Blackshield, Michael Coper and George Williams (eds), The Oxford Companion to the High Court of Australia (2001) 378-380. 19 For the broader context of the role of a constitutional court in a democracy, see Michael Coper, 'Democracy' in Tony Blackshield, Michael Coper and George Williams (eds), The Oxford Companion to the High Court of Australia (2001) 203-204. 20 Cf Michael Coper, 'Marbury v Madison' in Tony Blackshield, Michael Coper and George Williams (eds), The Oxford Companion to the High Court of Australia (2001) 453-455. 21 See n 17 above.

6 that the debate is about clarity in judicial reasoning, 22 there may be more important factors than those discussed in this paper: for example, the core judicial craft of good writing, the reservation of disagreement to points of major principle rather than of minor preference, the publication of court-sanctioned summaries of decisions, and so on. In the end, any system depends for its efficacy on the capacity, skill, commitment, and integrity of the human beings who operate it, and the degree of trust that particular societies repose in their institutions and their traditions. I suspect that many countries, perhaps most, have successful or unsuccessful judicial systems despite, rather than because of, the detail of their particular institutional arrangements. Professor Michael Coper Dean and Robert Garran Professor of Law Australian National University College of Law Canberra, ACT 0200 AUSTRALIA 4 August 2009 22 Which I think is an important element of judicial accountability: see Michael Coper, 'Accountability' in Tony Blackshield, Michael Coper and George Williams (eds), The Oxford Companion to the High Court of Australia (2001) 3-4.