Research Note: Toward an Integrated Model of Concept Formation

Similar documents
CHAPTER 5. CONTROL. Comparability: The Limits of Comparison

Migrants and external voting

Beyond Authoritarianism: The Conceptualization of Hybrid Regimes

Guidelines for Performance Auditing

RESEARCH METHODOLOGY IN POLITICAL SCIENCE STUDY NOTES CHAPTER ONE

Democratization Conceptualisation and measurement

Comparing the Data Sets

Bridging the Qualitative-Quantitative Divide: Best Practices in the Development of Historically Oriented Replication Databases

paoline terrill 00 fmt auto 10/15/13 6:35 AM Page i Police Culture

1 Introduction. Cambridge University Press International Institutions and National Policies Xinyuan Dai Excerpt More information

Introduction Why Don t Electoral Rules Have the Same Effects in All Countries?

Ina Schmidt: Book Review: Alina Polyakova The Dark Side of European Integration.

University of Notre Dame Department of Political Science Comprehensive Examination in Comparative Politics September 2013

DU PhD in Home Science

SOSC 5170 Qualitative Research Methodology

Whose Vote is it Anyway?

James M. Buchanan The Limits of Market Efficiency

OPINION OF ADVOCATE GENERAL Mengozzi delivered on 7 July 2011 (1) Case C-545/09

Governance and Good Governance: A New Framework for Political Analysis

Prof. Ljupco Kevereski, PhD. Faculty of Education, Bitola UDK: ISBN , 16 (2011), p Original scientific paper

Status and the Challenge of Rising Powers by Steven Ward

Constitutional Democracy and World Politics: A Response to Gartzke and Naoi

The historical sociology of the future

Part II. Research design

American Government /Civics

CHAPTER 1 PROLOGUE: VALUES AND PERSPECTIVES

Follow links for Class Use and other Permissions. For more information send to:

Political Science Graduate Program Class Schedule Spring 2014

Political Parties. The drama and pageantry of national political conventions are important elements of presidential election

IS STARE DECISIS A CONSTRAINT OR A CLOAK?

Summary. The Politics of Innovation in Public Transport Issues, Settings and Displacements

The Invention of Decolonization: The Algerian War and the Remaking of France. Todd Shepard.

Exploring the fast/slow thinking: implications for political analysis: Gerry Stoker, March 2016

Attest Engagements 1389

The Possible Incommensurability of Utilities and the Learning of Goals

Practice Guide for the application of the new Brussels II Regulation.

Jürgen Kohl March 2011

A COMPARISON BETWEEN TWO DATASETS

Testimony of Steven Aftergood Director, Project on Government Secrecy Federation of American Scientists

Agricultural Policy Analysis: Discussion

BOOK SUMMARY. Rivalry and Revenge. The Politics of Violence during Civil War. Laia Balcells Duke University

Can the number of veto players measure policy stability?

Key Issues in Recording Remittances in the Balance of Payments Statistics and Recent Improvements in Concepts and Definitions

Strategies for Combating Terrorism

Viktória Babicová 1. mail:

The Philosophy and Methods of Political Science. Keith Dowding

Chapter 1 Requirements for Description

INTERNATIONAL RECOMMENDATIONS ON REFUGEE STATISTICS (IRRS)

Introduction: The Challenge of Risk Communication in a Democratic Society

Conceptual Hierarchies in Comparative Research: The Case of Democracy

Principles of Democracy

Economic Crises and the Electoral Resilience of Dominant Parties: A Paired Comparison of Mexico and Malaysia. Marthe Vaagen

MA International Relations Module Catalogue (September 2017)

Using Typologies in Comparative Research Dr. Jody LaPorte DPIR & St Hilda s College

Abstract. Keywords. Kotaro Kageyama. Kageyama International Law & Patent Firm, Tokyo, Japan

Polimetrics. Lecture 2 The Comparative Manifesto Project

IV. GENERAL RECOMMENDATIONS ADOPTED BY THE COMMITTEE ON THE ELIMINATION OF DISCRIMINATION AGAINST WOMEN. Thirtieth session (2004)

Spring 2019 Course Descriptions

Cover Page. The handle holds various files of this Leiden University dissertation.

2. Good governance the concept

Comments on Schnapper and Banting & Kymlicka

Nicholas Capaldi. Legendre-Soule Distinguished Chair in Business Ethics. Loyola University New Orleans. New Orleans, LA, USA

Commentary on Idil Boran, The Problem of Exogeneity in Debates on Global Justice

Dietlind Stolle 2011 Marc Hooghe. Shifting Inequalities. Patterns of Exclusion and Inclusion in Emerging Forms of Political Participation.

Anti-immigration populism: Can local intercultural policies close the space? Discussion paper

Karen Bell, Achieving Environmental Justice: A Cross-National Analysis, Bristol: Policy Press, ISBN: (cloth)

Following the Leader: The Impact of Presidential Campaign Visits on Legislative Support for the President's Policy Preferences

Defining political participation: how to pinpoint an elusive target? 2014 Marc Hooghe

Sociological Marxism Volume I: Analytical Foundations. Table of Contents & Outline of topics/arguments/themes

1. Students access, synthesize, and evaluate information to communicate and apply Social Studies knowledge to Time, Continuity, and Change

CHAPTER 1 PROLOGUE: VALUES AND PERSPECTIVES

ANES Panel Study Proposal Voter Turnout and the Electoral College 1. Voter Turnout and Electoral College Attitudes. Gregory D.

On Conflict and Consensus

Comparative Case Study Research MA Mandatory Elective Course, Fall CEU credits, 4 ECTS

EPRDF: The Change in Leadership

Journals in the Discipline: A Report on a New Survey of American Political Scientists

Article II. Most Favoured-Nation Treatment

Empirical Modalities: Lessons for the Future of International Investment

2018 Visiting Day. Law School 101 Room 1E, 1 st Floor Gambrell Hall. Robert A. Schapiro Asa Griggs Candler Professor of Law

Running Head: POLICY MAKING PROCESS. The Policy Making Process: A Critical Review Mary B. Pennock PAPA 6214 Final Paper

Rise and Decline of Nations. Olson s Implications

Revising NATO s nuclear deterrence posture: prospects for change

Walter Lippmann and John Dewey

Collective Action for Equitable Natural Resource Management in Eastern African Highlands

SOCI 423: THEORIES OF SOCIAL DEVELOPMENT

2. Realism is important to study because it continues to guide much thought regarding international relations.

Magruder s American Government C H A P T E R 1 Principles of Government S E C T I O N 1 Government and the State What Is Government?

The Possibility Principle: choosing negative cases in comparative research

GENDER SENSITIVE DEMOCRACY AND THE QUALITY OF GOVERNMENT

British Election Leaflet Project - Data overview

STATE UNIVERSITY OF NEW YORK AT ALBANY Rockefeller College of Public Affairs and Policy Department of Political Science

VIRGINIA SELF-REPRESENTED LITIGANT STUDY:

THE PROVINCIAL AUDITOR AND THE ADMINISTRATIVE JUSTICE SYSTEM

Colorado 2014: Comparisons of Predicted and Actual Turnout

Chapter 6 Online Appendix. general these issues do not cause significant problems for our analysis in this chapter. One

Analysis of the Draft Defence Strategy of the Slovak Republic 2017

The Global State of Democracy

Discovering Migrant Types Through Cluster Analysis: Changes in the Mexico-U.S. Streams from 1970 to 2000

why we need a theory of federalism

Methodological note on the CIVICUS Civil Society Enabling Environment Index (EE Index)

Transcription:

Kristen A. Harkness Princeton University February 2, 2011 Research Note: Toward an Integrated Model of Concept Formation The process of thinking inevitably begins with a qualitative (natural) language, no matter at which shore we shall subsequently land. -Giovanni Sartori 1 I. Introduction Conceptual confusion has devastating consequences for scientific inference be it descriptive or causal, qualitative or quantitative. For example, case study comparisons often rely on matching techniques based in shared conceptual categories to overcome the problems of indeterminancy (too many plausible independent variables given the number of cases). If those conceptual categories have been stretched beyond recognition such that they can, in fact, accommodate broadly dissimilar cases, then analytical leverage is lost. Most statistical models, on the other hand, are grounded explicitly in assumptions of basic unit heterogeneity. Violating those assumptions, which can occur when concepts lose meaning or are applied inappropriately and unthinkingly, severely compromises the validity of results. Indeed, measurement itself takes as its antecedent the formation of concepts: before measurement can occur, we must have some notion of what is to be measured. Poorly developed concepts thus translate directly into measurement error which can bias quantitative studies in unknown directions. Precision and clarity in concept development are thus critical to drawing reliable inferences from empirical research. Giovanni Sartori warned the political science community about the inherent dangers of conceptual stretching long ago and proposed a framework, the ladder of abstraction, for maintaining unit homogeneity and thus the basis for comparison. Recent scholarship, however, has found this framework unsatisfactory in several important ways. Collier and Levitsky, in analyzing work on 1 Sartori 1970, 1038. 1

the third wave of democratization, argue that Sartori s framework cannot cope adequately with what they term diminished subtypes cases that appear to fit the mold of a concept well except that they are missing a single defining attribute. Gary Goertz, on the other hand, argues for a different scheme of conceptualization that moves away from Sartori s proclivity for dichotomizing and instead proposes a continuum of gradations from the positive, ideal-type of a concept to its negation. While these scholars point out important shortcomings of Sartori s concept ladder, their solutions fall prey to the original problem that he sought to overcome conceptual stretching and its inherent threat to inference. As a solution, this research note proposes an integrated model of concept formation: one that defines concepts along a clear ladder of abstraction while at the same time ordering related concepts from a positive to a negative poll and accounting for the relevant absence of one or more attributes of a concept. Thus, the analytical benefits of Collier and Levitsky s and Goertz s frameworks are retained without sacrificing conceptual clarity and precision. II. Sartori s Concept Ladder In 1970, Giovanni Sartori entreated the political science community to pay greater attention to concept formation. Examining the research of his day, Sartori identified a pervasive problem in the field s tendency toward what he termed conceptual stretching: the misapplication of western political concepts to an increasingly broad and diverse array of countries. This extension of traditional concepts had led, in his view, to the routine inclusion of inappropriate cases into conceptual categories (especially in the burgeoning quantitative literature) as well as to the extreme watering-down of the concepts themselves such that they no longer retained any real defining characteristics and ceased to reveal useful information about political and social realities. 2 In response, Sartori advocated careful concept construction according to a hierarchical, taxonomic model based in principles of appropriate classification: the now famous ladder of abstrac- 2 Ibid, 1034-1035. 2

tion. What is oft forgotten, however, is that this model was structured according to Sartori s fundamental concern with the logic of appropriate comparison; of establishing what is homogeneous and therefore comparable with what is heterogenous and therefore non-comparable. 3 It is out of this fundamental concern that the either-or, mutually-exclusive nature of his classificatory system grew: Classes are required to be mutually exclusive, i.e., class concepts represent characteristics which the object under consideration must either have or lack. Two items being compared must belong first to the same class, and either have or not have an attribute; and only if they have it, the two items can be matched in terms of which has it more or less [emphasis original] 4 Hence, only once it is established that two objects are indeed comparable that they possess the same attributes, and therefore belong to the same category do questions of gradation, of more or less, come into play. Homogeneity matters most, and homogeneity is established through careful concept construction. With these underlying principles in mind, we can now review the tenets of Sartori s ladder of abstraction. Here, related concepts are situated vertically with their relative position determined by their number of well-defined constitutive attributes: the more abstract the concept (the fewer definitional attributes it possesses), the higher up the ladder it goes. Thus, the highest concept on any given ladder would logically have very few attributes, such as electoral regime, wherein a country need only hold elections to qualify. As one moves down the ladder, each concept is considered a subtype of those that preceded it, possessing all of their attributes plus one or more additional characteristics. For example, we would consider democracy a subtype of electoral regime since democracies too hold elections and yet they must also possess additional qualities such as free and fair contestation and civil liberties. In turn, we would consider Presidential as a subtype of both electoral regime and democracy (see Figure 1). Thus, to add 3 Ibid, 1036. 4 Ibid, 1038. 3

an additional attribute to an existing concept forms a new, sub-type concept that is lower on the ladder of abstraction yet still visually connected to its parent concept, mirroring the constructions of classical taxonomy. Figure 1: An Example of Sartori s Concept Ladder Electoral (E) (E, C, L) Presidential (E, C, L, I) E= elections, C= free and fair contestation, L= civil liberties, and I= independence of executive and legislative power As many have noted, Sartori s concept ladder was particularly insightful as it highlighted the inverse relationship, or the trade-off, between definitional thickness and traveling capacity. The fewer attributes required of a concept, the greater its abstraction, and the more cases to which it could conceivably apply. Likewise, the more attributes necessary to define a concept, the lower its abstraction, and the fewer cases it could possibly encompass. Sartori s concept ladder thus provided social scientists a powerful tool that at once enforces clarity and precision in concept building, develops a means of relating concepts to one another, and establishes scope conditions around the applicability of those concepts. Yet, recent criticisms have challenged Sartori s model, arguing that in some instances it cannot provide sufficient levels of conceptual differentiation and that certain types of concepts, just as essential to social-scientific inquiry, cannot be captured within his strict taxonomic structure. The 4

following two sections will discuss two particularly incisive critiques and their suggestions for modified or alternative models of concept formation: diminished subtypes and family resemblance types. III. Diminished Subtypes In their 1997 World Politics Research Note, Collier and Levitsky argue that the post-cold War wave of democratization led to a proliferation of new regimes that shared many characteristics of established democracies but nonetheless differed in profound ways from them. For scholars seeking to analytically cope with this diversification of so-called democratic forms, Sartori s classic concept scheme proved inadequate. The problem was that these new democracies failed to meet (usually) one of the traditional defining standards of democracy (and yet were otherwise reasonably democratic): they had less than full suffrage, partially restricted civil liberties, or biased rules of contestation, among other such defects. 5 In an effort to classify these systems in a meaningful way, and with an eye to avoiding conceptual stretching, many scholars attempted to adapt Sartori s ladder through the practice of defining diminished subtypes or employing democracy with adjectives. Thus, we have restricted democracies, illiberal democracies, and oligarchical democracies ; all of which are defined according to the one democratic attribute they lack (see Figure 2). Indeed, Collier and Levitsky defend this strategy as a way to differentiate cases without falling prey to conceptual stretching because it specifies the missing attribute while still identifying the attributes that are present. 6 I contend, however, that while diminished subtypes do indeed provide much needed analytical differentiation, they do not avoid Sartori s notion of conceptual stretching. And, more importantly, their use violates the fundamental either-or logic of classification that Sartori himself insisted was necessary to properly establish unit homogeneity and thus our very ability to meaningfully compare. 5 Collier and Levitsky, 1997, p.430. 6 Ibid, p.438. 5

Figure 2: An Example of Collier & Levitsky s Diminished Subtypes: Electoral (E) (E, C, L, S) Diminished Subtypes Parliamentary (E, C, L, S, I) Restricted (E, C, L, S) Illiberal (E, C, L, S) Oligarchical (E, C, L, S) E= elections, C= free and fair contestation, L= civil liberties, I= independence of executive and legislative power, S= full suffrage, and = absence of attribute Diminished subtypes are not true subtypes, in a formal sense, as all of their attributes are not shared by the parent concept. This misapplication of logical subtypes has great consequence: it not only undermines unit homogeneity, and thus comparability, but also drains the initial concept, here democracy, of any substantial meaning. Let me demonstrate this by mapping out the logical space inhabited by only some of the diminished subtypes of democracy identified by Collier and Levitsky (again, see Figure 2). Let us first define democracy as a regime type with regular elections, full suffrage, free and fair contestation, and civil liberties. A diminished subtype of democracy has been expounded for the absence of any of these attributes except regular elections: illiberal democracy lacks civil liberties, restricted democracy lacks free and fair contestation, and oligarchical democracy lacks full suffrage. This leaves regular elections as the only universal characteristic of all democracies. Thus democracy becomes equated with electoral regime. From here, the violation of unit homogeneity is relatively simple to understand: if the expanded set of democracies 6

do not qualitatively share an underlying set of definitional attributes then by comparing them we do not learn anything meaningful about democracy. This is not to say that no comparison can be made, but that the results of such a comparison would rather tell us something about a more abstract category such as electoral regimes. IV. Theorizing the Continuum Between Negative and Positive Poles In his book, Social Science Concepts, Gary Goertz directly takes issue with Sartori s either-or logic of classification (as well as Collier and Levitsky s modifications to it). Instead, he argues that one should treat all concepts as continuous for, often, to dichotomize is to introduce measurement error. 7 Out of this re-orientation in basic categorical logic, Goertz entreats scholars to think in terms of conceptual continuums for if you are thinking in terms of ladders all you can do is go up or down... my metaphorical universe also runs from left to right, from negative to positive pole... 8 We should thus first explicitly theorize the positive, ideal-type of the concept as well as its true negation, what he refers to as the positive and negative poles. Then we must theorize the grey zone in between the poles, or the various intermediary conceptual forms that might lie along that continuum. 9 I believe Goertz s insight here to be quite important and yet perhaps misguided. We certainly should be able to think laterally to place concepts in relation to one another along a continuum between what we consider to be important opposites, such as autocracy and democracy. Yet, throwing away the most basic elements of Sartori s classificatory system the either-or logic underlying unit homogeneity and thus comparability seems a monumental and perhaps unnecessary sacrifice. A closer examination of Goertz s model, as it is used in practice, will illuminate its possible reconciliation with Sartori s framework. Figure 3 presents Goertz s conceptualization of democracy (without placing it in relation to more abstract concepts). 10 As becomes quickly apparent, what 7 Goertz, 2006, p.34. 8 Ibid, p.82 9 Ibid, p.34. 10 Ibid, p.82. 7

Goertz considers a continuum within a concept is more readily understood as a continuum of distinct concepts (all regime-oriented) set in relation to one another. Moreover, the presence or absence of dichotomous attributes still defines membership within those concepts. We have not defined democracy along a true continuous scale of, say, the degree to which citizens can freely and fairly contest elections. Rather, concepts are arrayed according to how many of the core attributes of democracy they possess. Unlike other possible interpretations of Goertz s recommendations, this continuum does not contradict Sartori s logic. It is therefore at least theoretically possible to combine some of Goetz s insights into the ladder of abstraction framework. Figure 3: An Example of Goertz s Concept Continuum: Pole + Pole Authoritarianism ( E, C, L) Illiberal, Controlled (E, C, L) (other forms possible) Illiberal (E, C, L) (E, C, L) (missing ALL attributes) (missing NO attributes) E= elections, C= free and fair contestation, L= civil liberties, and = absence of attribute V. Toward an Integrated Model of Concept Formation Both Goertz and Collier and Levitsky identify significant shortcomings in Sartori s recommendations for concept formation respectively, the ladder of abstraction s inability to array concepts from negative to positive poles and its restricted capacity for analytical differentiation in the face 8

of complex concepts. Yet, the suggested corrections fall prey to the fundamental problem that Sartori originally set out to overcome: conceptual stretching which undermines unit homogeneity and hence the very basis of useful comparison. Is there a way, then, to combine the three tasks of the authors at hand? To clearly define concepts along a concept ladder, thereby preventing conceptual ambiguity and stretching, to take into consideration the relevant absence of a particular attribute, and to order a concept from a positive to a negative poll? I believe so, and indeed in the combination of the three concerns may lie the strongest model of concept mapping and formation. Figure 4 presents an initial attempt at an integrated model of concept formation. Here, the concept map combines a vertical ordering of abstraction with an horizontal ordering between poles. Following Sartori, the addition or subtraction of attributes understood as either a positive quality or its absence moves subtypes up or down the ladder. Following Goertz, the proportion of missing attributes (negations of positively defined attributes), on the other hand, moves the concept laterally from the positive to the negative pole. The positive pole is thus defined as a concept possessing all of the specified positive attributes for that level of abstraction while the negative pole is defined as a concept embodying its complete negation. This mapping technique gains analytical differentiation and the ability to use conceptual continuums without sacrificing the crucial advantages of Sartori s either-or taxonomy we still know in exactly which ways units are homogeneous and thus comparable. Within a single concept, such as liberal democracy, we can then turn to a logic of degrees and, for example, measure how the relative competitiveness of elections affects outcomes of interest such as post-electoral ethnic violence. Or we can compare across specified heterogeneous subtypes and use the precision gained by this model of concept formation to isolate the effect of a specified attribute (this parallels the logic behind indicator variables in regression analysis). For example, if we wanted to understand how free and fair contestation impacts the quality of public goods provision (such as health care), we would compare the set of liberal restricted electoral regimes to the set of liberal democracies in Figure 4 since they only differ according to the attribute of interest. 9

Figure 4: An Integrated Model of Concept Formation: Least Attributes Non-Electoral ( E, C) Authoritarian ( E, C, L) Non-Electoral ( E) [ E, C = logically impossible] Liberal Non-Electoral ( E, C, L) Illiberal Restricted Electoral (E, C, L) Restricted Electoral (E, C) Electoral (E) (E, C) Illiberal Liberal (E, C, L) (E, C, L) Liberal Restricted Electoral (E, C, L) Most Attributes Pole + Pole E= elections, C= free and fair contestation, L= civil liberties, and = absence of attribute 10

VI. Conclusion In their work on concept development, Collier and Levitsky and Goertz identify legitimate shortcomings of Sartori s ladder of abstraction. We should be able to accommodate a proliferation of diminished subtypes when contemplating important concepts like democracy. We should also be able to integrate missing attributes into our conceptual frameworks and order concepts on a gradation from positive to negative ideal types. These two aims, however, ought not to be accomplished via conceptual stretching the critical threat to inference that Sartori originally sought to remedy. Rather, an integrated model of concept formation is necessary one that captures the comparative strengths of all three models without entailing sacrifices in clarity and precision. It is my hope that the model proposed here, an attempt at such integration, stands up to careful scrutiny that it achieves increased analytical flexibility while maintaining the careful construction of unit homogeneity central to reliable inference. References Collier, David, and Steven Levitsky. 1997. with Adjectives: Conceptual Innovation in Comparative Research. World Politics 49, no.3 (April): 430-451. Goertz, Gary. 2006. Social Science Concepts: A User s Guide. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Sartori, Giovanni. 1970. Concept Misformation in Comparative Politics. American Political Science Review 64, no.4 (December): 1033-1053. 11