Terrorism and Just War Theory

Similar documents
All is Fair in War? Just War Theory and American Applications. Chris Sabolcik GSW Area II

Foreword to Killing by Remote Control (edited by Bradley Jay Strawser, Oxford University Press, 2012) Jeff McMahan

Jus in Bello through the Lens of Individual Moral Responsibility: McMahan on Killing in War

On the Ethics of War. Iceal Averroes E. Estrella. Article. Introduction

War and Violence: The Use of Nuclear Warfare in World War II

Course Description Course Goals and Objectives Required Texts and Readings

Historic Approaches to War: Just War Tradition: A Reference Guide A resource from the United States Army Chaplain Center & School

Chapter 37. Just War

Oxford Handbooks Online

War and intervention

Department of Philosophy Phone: Philosophy 118/ War and Morality

Redefining Legitimate Authority: Just War in the Era of Terrorism

DRONES VERSUS SECURITY OR DRONES FOR SECURITY?

According to the Just War tradition a war can only be just if two sets of principles

Proportionality and Necessity in Jus in Bello

PROPORTIONATE DEFENSE

INTERNATIONAL LAW AND INSTITUTIONS International Law Regarding the Conduct of War - Mark A. Drumbl INTERNATIONAL LAW REGARDING THE CONDUCT OF WAR

Proportionate Defense

United States defense strategic guidance issued

Just War Theory, Legitimate Authority, and Irregular Belligerency

THE IRAQ WAR OF 2003: A RESPONSE TO GABRIEL PALMER-FERNANDEZ

A Necessary Discussion About International Law

The first affirmation of the Center s Guideline ( on

Moral Dilemmas of Modern War

LEBOHANG MATSOSO TOPIC: BOOK REVIEW OF LAW AND WAR

PROPORTIONALITY AND NECESSITY. Just war theory, the traditional theory of the morality of war, is not a consequentialist

War (VIOLENCE) Education. Dr Katerina Standish National Centre for Peace and Conflict Studies University of Otago

Dear students: This presentation is a text version of the presentation that was given in lecture # 1, since presentations with certain animations

WAR AND CONFLICT STUDIES (1POL543)

President Bush s 2002 National Security Strategy (NSS) addressed many. of the Nation s new security challenges in a post 9/11 world.

Combatants, non-combatants and opportunistic killings. Helen Frowe Stockholm University

FACT SHEET STOPPING THE USE OF RAPE AS A TACTIC OF

The University of Chicago Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Ethics.

JUST WAR THEORY AND ITS SEVEN COMPONENTS

Varieties of Contingent Pacifism in War

JUST WAR THEORY. Laurens van Apeldoorn. Introduction

The Internet in Bello: Cyber War Law, Ethics & Policy Seminar held 18 November 2011, Berkeley Law

Review. Michael Walzer s Arguing about War New Haven: Yale University Press, 2004

Legitimate Authority and the Ethics of War: A Map of the Terrain

Proportionality in Self-Defense and War Jeff McMahan

Week # 2 Targeting Principles & Human Shields

SPECIAL ISSUE ON TRANSITIONAL JUSTICE

Wanted Dead or Alive: Ethical Concern in UAV Warfare. Abstract. First draft please do not cite without permission of the author

Terrorism and just War. Tamar MEISELS

Is the War on Terror Just? 1. Alex J. Bellamy, University of Queensland, Australia

CONTEMPORARY TERRORIST ORGANIZATIONS AND THE THREAT TO MICHAEL WALZER S DEFENSE OF A SUPREME EMERGENCY EXEMPTION FROM JUS IN BELLO.

JUST WAR THEORY AND THE CHALLENGES IMPOSED BY TRANSNATIONAL TERRORIST NETWORKS

The responsibility to protect doctrine Coherent after all: A reply to Friberg-Fernros and Brommesson

Companion to Applied Philosophy (Wiley-Blackwell, 2016)

Global Justice. Wednesdays (314) :00 4:00 pm Office Hours: Seigle 282 Tuesdays, 9:30 11:30 am

RESOLVING THE ETHICAL CHALLENGES OF IRREGULAR WAR

Michael Walzer, arguably the

Wars Waged by the USA and by Canada: Just, Unjust and Everything Inbetween

Rawls and Feminism. Hannah Hanshaw. Philosophy. Faculty Advisor: Dr. Jacob Held

The Permissibility of Aiding and Abetting Unjust Wars

PREVENTION, PREEMPTION, AND THE BUSH DOCTRINE

Please do not cite; it s drafty in here.

In 1978, Congress established the Foreign Intelligence Surveillance Court, which reviews warrants related to national security investigations.

International Humanitarian Law

MORAL responsibility for an unjust threat, or a threat of wrongful harm, is,

WASHINGTON STATE MODEL UNITED NATIONS

WikiLeaks Document Release

Chapter 8: The Use of Force

INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF RESEARCH AND ANALYSIS VOLUME 4 ISSUE 2 ISSN

FIGHTING JUSTLY IN AN UNJUST WAR: A CRITICAL ANALYSIS OF JUS AD BELLUM AS A NECESSARY CONDITION FOR JUS IN BELLO MICHAEL KEWLEY (Philosophy)

Objectives To explore the meanings of conflict and war. To make deductions and practise reasoning skills.

Conventional Deterrence: An Interview with John J. Mearsheimer

The Permissibility of Aiding and Abetting Unjust Wars

PIPA-Knowledge Networks Poll: Americans on Iraq & the UN Inspections II. Questionnaire

Criminal Justice Without Moral Responsibility: Addressing Problems with Consequentialism Dane Shade Hannum

Responsible Victims and (Partly) Justified Offenders

Counterterrorism strategies from an international law. and policy perspective

Chemical Weapons and Just War Theory Are New Threats Bound By Old Rules?

International Security Problems and Solutions by Patrick M. Morgan (Washington, D.C.: CQ Press, 2006)

NUCLEAR DISARMAMENT: AN OVERVIEW OF CUSTOMARY INTERNATIONAL LAW

PO/IR 265 TERRORISM: STRATEGIES OF DESTRUCTION IES Abroad Rome

1/13/ What is Terrorism? The Globalization of Terrorism. What is Terrorism? Geography of Terrorism. Global Patterns of Terrorism

Forthcoming in Lazar and Frowe (eds.) Oxford Handbook of Ethics of War (New York: OUP) The Just War Framework 1

10/15/2013. The Globalization of Terrorism. What is Terrorism? What is Terrorism?

The Paradox of Riskless Warfare

The Taken Country of Narcos by Rodrigo Ventura

Nuremberg Tribunal. London Charter. Article 6

Example 8.2 The Economics of Terrorism: Externalities and Strategic Interaction

Humanitarian Intervention, the Responsibility to Protect and jus in bello *

Resolved: United Nations peacekeepers should have the power to engage in offensive operations.

A discussion with Michael Walzer

RESPONSE TO JAMES GORDLEY'S "GOOD FAITH IN CONTRACT LAW: The Problem of Profit Maximization"

PDFlib PLOP: PDF Linearization, Optimization, Protection. Page inserted by evaluation version

The Legitimacy of Humanitarian Intervention in International Society of The 21 st Century

POLITICAL TERRORISM AND THE RULES OF JUST WAR

Just War, As It Was and Is James Turner Johnson January 2005

RUSSIA & UKRAINE: INTERNATIONAL LAW AND SELF DETERMINATION. Patrick McGuiness

The Ethics of Harm: Violence and Just War

Do we have a strong case for open borders?

PROBLEMS OF CREDIBLE STRATEGIC CONDITIONALITY IN DETERRENCE by Roger B. Myerson July 26, 2018

Preemptive Strikes: A New Security Policy Reality

Serious Crime Bill (HL) Part I Briefing for House of Lords Second Reading

Art. 61. Troops that give no quarter have no right to kill enemies already disabled on the ground, or prisoners captured by other troops.

Global Justice. Mondays Office Hours: Seigle 282 2:00 5:00 pm Mondays and Wednesdays

JUST AND LAWFUL CONDUCT IN WAR: REFLECTIONS ON MICHAEL WALZER

Transcription:

Scott C. Lowe Perspectives on Evil and Human Wickedness Vol. 1 No. 2 Page 46 Terrorism and Just War Theory Scott C. Lowe Department of Philosophy/Assistant Dean of Liberal Arts, Bloomsburg University, Bloomsburg, Pennsylvania (USA) In this paper I wish to critique the view that some acts of terrorism can be justified by classic just war theory, a claim defended by political theorist, Andrew Valls, among others. His argument turns on two elements. First, Valls offers a broad interpretation of what terrorism is, reducing it to violence by non-state actors for political purposes. I believe that there are problems with this definition of terrorism, and suggest a narrower alternative. Second, Valls focuses heavily on his disagreement with the requirement of just war theory that only those with legitimate political authority, i.e., nation states, may use political violence. He may well be right in saying that legitimate political authority does not reside only in the form of politically recognized states. However, the conclusion that Valls draws from his analysis is that, granted the justice, proportionality, etc. of the act of political violence, some acts by terrorist organizations could satisfy the criteria of just war theory. His is a striking conclusion. The just war theory tradition is the basis of a long held view in the West that there can be legitimate uses of war, while also setting moral boundaries on the waging of war. If acts of terrorism can satisfy the conditions of just war theory, then they would have a moral legitimacy that runs deeply contrary to our normal understanding of terrorism. I believe that the proper response to Valls is to focus on how narrow his conclusion really is. In de-emphasizing the importance of terrorizing in acts of terrorism, Valls may have brought some acts of terrorism under the umbrella of just war theory, but only relatively few. I argue that these cases are too few to justify the weight Valls puts on them. Rather, the examples of terrorism that experience has shown are far more common and involve far more carnage are precisely those whose purpose it is to threaten a population and their way of life. These acts of terrorism target the safety of innocent citizens, of non-combatants, and it is an analysis of the status of non-combatants that shows that terrorism, as we commonly understand it, is not compatible with just war theory. Just War Theory Since before the time of Aquinas, appeals to justice and morality have been used to explain and justify the moral legitimacy of war. Aquinas was among the earliest writers to develop a view that stands in what we might now call a just war theory tradition, though he is in turn clearly indebted to Augustine, whom he cites frequently. In Summa Theologica 1, Aquinas lays out three conditions for justly entering into war, and also discusses legitimate ways of conducting war, specifically, the morality of ambushing one s enemy (it s permissible, though, 1 Aquinas, Summa Theologica, Second Part, Part II, question 40 - Of War.

Scott C. Lowe Perspectives on Evil and Human Wickedness Vol. 1 No. 2 Page 47 interestingly, lying to the enemy is not.) Aquinas s discussion foreshadows the basic structure of this tradition as it continues down to this day. 2 That is, he distinguishes between the conditions for justly resorting to war (jus ad bellum) and the conditions for justly waging war (jus in bello). 3 Central to the justice of resorting to war according to this tradition are the three criteria Aquinas discusses: that hostilities be used in support of a just cause, that support of that just cause in fact be the reason for going to war, and that the war be waged under the legitimate authority of the state. Waging war in support of a just cause in this context means doing so because, as Aquinas puts it, those attacked deserve it on account of some fault. He follows with an illuminating quotation from Augustine: A just war is usually described as one that avenges wrongs, when a nation or state has to be punished, for refusing to make amends for the wrongs inflicted by its subjects, or to restore what it has seized unjustly. In modern terminology, a just war is usually waged in self-defense or in defense of another, or is waged as punishment to avenge some wrong done by another nation. Note that this condition does not preclude a nation s engaging in offensive warfare; with sufficient provocation, a nation could justly strike first in self-defense or in defense of an innocent third party. Further, the second condition under jus ad bellum requires that such a just cause in fact be the reason for engaging in hostilities. It is not enough that the just cause (even if legitimate) simply be window dressing for some other, morally dubious, motive. A just war must be pursued with right intention. Additionally, Aquinas argues that a just war can only be waged under the authority of the sovereign. That is, just wars can only be waged by a state; all non-state groups act unjustly if they engage in warfare or political violence. Aquinas gives two reasons for this condition. First, private individuals do not need to resort to political violence or warfare because they have the sovereign to appeal to in support of their rights and to protect their interests. And, second, it is the job of the sovereign, not private citizens, to look after the public good; as the care of the common weal is committed to those who are in authority, it is their business to watch over the common weal of the city, kingdom or province subject to them. And since it is the sovereign who has the authority to use the material sword in defense of the state from both external and internal foes, private citizens are not to use violence in war, as punishment, nor, certainly, in insurrection. Finally, the tradition, as it has developed, usually includes three further conditions under jus ad bellum: that war not be started except as a last resort, that war not be started except when there is a reasonable probability that it will accomplish its goal, and that the good gained by engaging in warfare is proportional to the likely pain, suffering and evils that result from doing so. These three conditions all direct our attention to the disadvantages of warfare, and demand that we weigh carefully in deciding whether going to war is worth the costs that are likely to come with it. I will not be concerned with these conditions in what follows, and will simply assume that such conditions hold and can be met. Additionally, it is worthwhile to touch briefly on the conditions of jus in bello because of their bearing on the discussion that follows. Under this heading there is also a demand for 2 I am greatly indebted to Brian Orend s discussion of just war theory in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 3 The tradition also includes a third category, jus post bellum, the conditions for justly ending war, though these will not concern us here.

Scott C. Lowe Perspectives on Evil and Human Wickedness Vol. 1 No. 2 Page 48 proportionality, though here it functions at a more tactical level, requiring that soldiers not use force out of proportion to the particular (presumably legitimate) military end they seek. Second, in the conduct of war, soldiers must not make use of certain wholly illegitimate tactics or weapons such as chemical or biological warfare, mass rape, genocide or torture. Finally, and most importantly for our purposes, to conduct war justly, soldiers must discriminate between legitimate military targets which may be attacked and those non-combatants who, though potentially victims of collateral damage, may not be intentionally targeted. This distinction between legitimate military, industrial or political targets that may be the object of attack, and non-combatants, innocents in some sense of the word, who may not be intentionally targeted, will play an important role in much of what follows. So, in sum, according to the just war tradition, warfare is not always an illegitimate political tool. If a sovereign intends a sufficiently important and just end, and if that end has a reasonably good chance of being brought about, then hostilities may be initiated as a last resort to accomplish that end. Further, if, in the conduct of that war, the military uses no morally unacceptable means, nor acceptable means out of proportion to their tactical end, and if noncombatants are not intentionally targeted, then one can be said to wage war justly. Terrorism and Just War The just war tradition we have been discussing carries a lot of weight. It is the primary moral and religious context in which the legitimacy of war has been discussed for nearly a millennium. It is for this reason that Andrew Valls asks the question, Can Terrorism Be Justified?, and defends a qualified affirmative answer within the just war tradition; just war theory, despite its ambiguities, provides a rich framework with which to assess the morality of war, 4 and, he wants to add, other forms of political violence such as terrorism, as well. Valls s strategy is to show that certain forms of terrorism can meet every defensible qualification under just war theory, so he canvasses each of the nine criteria under jus ad bellum and jus in bello. I will not review all that he has to say here, but rather will focus on two pieces: the demand for legitimate authority (jus ad bellum) and for discrimination (jus in bello). A central issue for Valls s position is to discredit the requirement of just war theory that only those with legitimate political authority may make use of political violence. Obviously, if non-state organizations are precluded from the use of political violence, then all of the cases of terrorism we are interested in here would be ruled out. 5 So why think that non-state organizations may not use violence? Recall Aquinas s two reasons mentioned above: that private individuals do not need to resort to political violence because they have the sovereign to protect their rights and interests; and, that it is the responsibility of the sovereign alone to look after the public good. Clearly Aquinas is wrong on both counts, for neither of these reasons will support the claim that political violence is never justified by non-state organizations. First, it is simply false to claim that governments always act fairly and support the rights of all citizens. Being the legitimate, recognized government of a nation does not guarantee that that government is concerned with protecting the rights of the ethnic, religious or racial minorities within its borders, as the history of even the North American and European democracies make clear. And, if that ill treatment is sufficiently malicious and intractable, then we cannot rule out violence, in principle, as an unacceptable 4 Valls, Andrew, Can Terrorism Be Justified?, in Valls (ed.) Ethics in International Affairs: Theories and Cases, Rowman & Littlefield, Lanham, MD, 2000, pp.65-79. 5 Nothing I say here rules out the possibility that some political violence by states is illegitimate and amounts to state terrorism, though I do not take up that topic.

Scott C. Lowe Perspectives on Evil and Human Wickedness Vol. 1 No. 2 Page 49 means of ending injustice. Similarly, experience also shows that it is not only sovereign governments that can function as the true representatives of the interests of a people. Examples as familiar as the PLO or IRA illustrate our willingness to accept organizations well short of sovereign states as the real protectors of the interests and rights of their people, sometimes even against the legitimate, recognized government in power. So, let us grant that non-state organizations can represent the interests of a people, in a manner analogous to a state, such that they may legitimately use political violence. Next, let us turn to the discussion of discriminating between military or other acceptable targets and non-combatants, who may not be targeted. The central issue here, unfortunately, is to take on the difficult task of determining who counts as a non-combatant. Traditionally, soldiers were to avoid the intentional harming of innocent civilians. Yet, with some exceptions such as children, few of us are so void of responsibility for the actions or policies of our governments as to count as fully innocent; trying to figure out what innocence is and who qualifies is a thorny matter, indeed. Valls offers some help clarifying this issue by first noting that we should avoid the attempt to draw any firm lines between combatants and non-combatants. Rather, following the work of Robert Holmes, he suggests it would be better to conceive of combatancy/noncombatancy as a continuum along which we could place persons of different degrees of culpability: At one end he would place political leaders who undertake the aggression, followed by soldiers, contributors to the war, supporters, and finally, at the other end of the spectrum, noncontributors and nonsupporters. 6 So, if non-combatancy status is a matter of degree, then the discrimination that soldiers must exercise in whom they target also comes in degrees. Being more discriminate means being careful to target folks who are more clearly combatants; being less discriminate means being indiscriminate or even intending to target those more at the other end of the scale. Similarly, the terrorist, if his or her action is to be judged by the standards of the just war tradition, must make every effort to be more, rather than less, discriminate in deciding who is targeted for attack. Thus, from what has been said so far, we can see the point of Valls conclusion. Namely, if it is legitimate for non-state actors to use political violence, as I have conceded it is, and if that political violence meets all the other criteria of just war theory, especially the demands for justice and discrimination, then some acts of what has traditionally been called terrorism are permissible and just. 7 Defining Terrorism You have noticed, no doubt, that I have not yet offered a definition of the key term in this whole discussion - terrorism. Trying to define this concept is both interesting and challenging; by examining different views on terrorism I hope to highlight my differences with Valls s view. He starts his discussion by suggesting boundaries within which a definition of terrorism should fall. 8 First, we should be careful not to define terrorism in such a way that we build the immorality into it. To start with a definition like the intentional, indiscriminate killing of the innocent is to assume the immorality of terrorism, and would end any discussion of its morality or immorality before we start. Such a discussion would be as pointless as trying to decide whether murder is wrong; of course it is, pointing out its wrongfulness is what you are doing when you call an act a murder. So, on the one hand, we need to craft a definition of terrorism 6 Valls, p.76, paraphrasing Holmes, On War and Morality, p.187. 7 Valls, pp.77-9. 8 Valls, pp.66-8. See also Corlett, pp.164-68.

Scott C. Lowe Perspectives on Evil and Human Wickedness Vol. 1 No. 2 Page 50 using morally neutral language that allows us to decide on the basis of the merits of the case whether the action is moral or immoral. On the other hand, terrorism is a word with an established (albeit wide) pattern of use, and we cannot ignore its meaning in ordinary language. A use of the term would be ruled out if it shifted too far away from everyday usage. For instance, it accords with its use in ordinary language to label al-qaeda a terrorist organization, but that does not mean that all actions carried out in its name are terrorist acts, contemporary rhetoric notwithstanding. So, it would push ordinary meaning too far to describe transferring money from one al-qaeda cell to another as a terrorist act; it might by prior to a terrorist act and it might be preparatory to a terrorist act, but it is not itself a terrorist act. In light of these boundaries, the definition of terrorism that Valls settles on leans decidedly toward avoiding morally loaded language, and ends up being very broad because of it. He states that he regards terrorism as violence committed by nonstate actors against persons or property for political purposes, and that this definition leave[s] open the normative issues involved while being reasonably consistent with ordinary language. 9 It is worth noting two implications of holding such a broad definition. First, while you can get to Valls s conclusion without adopting his definition of terrorism, his definition certainly makes it easier to get there. To call a definition broad is simply to say that it includes more examples under it than does a narrower definition. In this case it means that more actions count as terrorism, or at least more clearly count as such, than would be included under a narrower definition of terrorism with more restrictive criteria attached to it. For instance, fewer types of actions would count as terrorism if we include in our definition the idea that terrorist acts are those which tend to induce terror in a population; (I will elaborate on this definition of terrorism below.) What are the important examples that are included under this broader definition of terrorism? While carving out a category of permissible terrorism, Valls gives no examples of terrorist acts that would fit this category. Interestingly, the only examples he does use come in the context of defending the claim that terrorist acts can at least be carefully discriminate. He cites the kidnapping and murder of Aldo Moro by the Red Brigades, the murder of an American diplomat in Uruguay by an anti-government group, and the bombing of the American Marine barracks in Beirut as examples. Focusing on the level of discrimination of acts of terrorism is appropriate, for discrimination seems to be the key criterion for separating broader from narrower definitions of terrorism. Broad definitions readily allow cases of highly discriminate acts of political violence, such as the cases of political assassination mentioned above, while more narrow definitions push us back toward emphasizing more indiscriminate acts of political violence, ones that harm or terrorize people independent of their level of responsibility. If any examples of terrorism are going to be justified, they will have to be examples of just, proportionate, etc., highly discriminate political violence (tyrannicide, perhaps?), and it will be easier to accommodate them under a broad definition of terrorism. A second point to recognize about Valls s broad definition of terrorism is that it gets perilously close to violating the requirement that we stay within the bounds of ordinary language. One way of violating this proviso is to apply a term to circumstances in which it clearly does not fit, i.e., to circumstances in which we would want to apply another term, not terrorism. Consider the following example. A gang of teenage boys ride their skateboards by the mayor s house and rip her mailbox off its post and smash it. Why? Because they are upset with her advocacy of town ordinances restricting the riding of skateboards on downtown streets. I offer this as an 9 Valls, p.68.

Scott C. Lowe Perspectives on Evil and Human Wickedness Vol. 1 No. 2 Page 51 example of "violence committed by nonstate actors against persons or property for political purposes" though it is clearly not an example of terrorism. Anyone who used the word terrorism in this context, I can only imagine as speaking euphemistically, for what we have here is an example of petty crime, of vandalism. So, my suspicions about a very broad definition of terrorism push me toward adopting a somewhat narrower definition. Let me suggest such a narrower definition, one that Valls rejects precisely because of the proviso that makes it narrower. 10 Virginia Held, in her article, Terrorism, Rights, and Political Goals, offers a definition of terrorism that varies only slightly from the one we have been discussing. She describes terrorism as a form of political violence to achieve political goals, where creating fear is usually high among the intended effects. (Italics mine.) 11 In other words, Held s definition re-introduces the terror back into terrorism. Valls objects to this addition because causing fear is nonessential to an act being terrorism; interestingly, Held agrees. But to focus on whether causing fear is a necessary part of defining terrorism is to miss the point. What Held s definition adds is not a necessary condition of terrorism, but a frequently experienced aspect of terrorism and one that brings us much closer to the core of ordinary usage. As I pointed out above, terrorism is a broad term. Trying to pin down its essential elements is a very difficult task, as many authors have pointed out. 12 But if we look at both our experience of terrorism as well as our most common use of the word terrorism, we will find that inducing fear in a population is a very important, though not essential, element of terrorism. Conclusion So, what is the upshot of this disagreement over the definition of terrorism? What I want to argue is not that Valls is wrong that there is a wide array of acts of terrorism and that some of them may be justified. Rather, I hope to have shown why examples of justified terrorism are isolated ones and why it is not so surprising that we might count them as permissible. From what has been suggested above it is clear that if there are examples of terrorism permitted under just war theory, they will have to meet a number of challenging requirements. They will have to be acts of political violence that are proportionate and effective, done in support of a just cause, and not immoral in themselves. Additionally, they will have to be more, perhaps very much more, discriminate rather than less discriminate or indiscriminate in who is targeted for attack. It is this last criterion that creates the greatest challenge to an act of political violence being an act of terrorism. Any act of political violence that meets all of these criteria will clearly be just and very precisely targeted. This fact shows why Valls s conclusion is not such a dramatic one after all; we would have little room for moral objection to a just and proportionate precisely targeted attack on someone who deserves it, even if carried out by a nonstate organization. Yet, such cases are a long way from the acts of terrorism that are currently the focus of so much concern. The terrorist attacks in the United States last fall, the ongoing and escalating violence in the Middle East, as well as past terrorist attacks in Ireland, Russia, Japan and elsewhere around the world are all highly indiscriminate acts of violence. They represent the violence that we fear. 10 Valls p.67. 11 Held, Virginia, Terrorism, Rights, and Political Goals, in Violence, Terrorism and Justice, R. G. Frey and Christopher Morris (eds.), Cambridge University Press, Cambridge and New York, 1991, p.64. 12 The difficulty of specifying the meaning of terrorism is a common theme in the literature. See Valls, Corlett or Held for long lists of authors who have struggled with the issue.

Scott C. Lowe Perspectives on Evil and Human Wickedness Vol. 1 No. 2 Page 52 Ending the resort to such violence, and the conditions that give rise to it, is one of the great challenges to the century before us. Bibliography Aquinas, Summa Theologica, Second Part, Part II, question 40 - Of War. Coady, C.A.J., Terrorism, Encyclopedia of Ethics, vol. II, Garland Publishing, Inc., New York, 1992. Coates, A. J., The Ethics of War, Manchester University Press, Manchester and New York, 1997. Corlett, J. Angelo, Can Terrorism Be Morally Justified?, Public Affairs Quarterly, vol. 10, #3, July 1996, pp.163-84. Held, Virginia, Terrorism, Rights, and Political Goals, in Violence, Terrorism and Justice, R. G. Frey and Christopher Morris (eds.), Cambridge University Press, Cambridge and New York, 1991. Holmes, Robert, On War and Morality, Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ, 1989. Orend, Brian, War: Just War Theory, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2001 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL= http://plato.stanford.edu/ archives/win2001/entries/war/#2 Wilkins, Burleigh, Terrorism and Collective Responsibility, Routledge, New York, 1992. Walzer, Michael, Just and Unjust Wars, 2nd ed. Basic Books, 1992.