Lecture 2: Normative theories of social and fiscal justice in historical perspective (check on line for updated versions)

Similar documents
Brahmin Left vs Merchant Right: Rising Inequality and the Changing Structure of Political Conflict Evidence from France & the US,

Economic philosophy of Amartya Sen Social choice as public reasoning and the capability approach. Reiko Gotoh

Lecture 8: The rise of the fiscal, social and capital state

Fairness and Well-Being

Rising Inequality and the Changing Structure of Political Conflict. Thomas Piketty EHESS and Paris School of Economics Hamburg, May

Problems with Group Decision Making

Rising Inequality and the Changing Structure of Political Conflict. Thomas Piketty Paris School of Economics PSE Summer School, June

Chapter 4: Voting and Social Choice.

VOTING ON INCOME REDISTRIBUTION: HOW A LITTLE BIT OF ALTRUISM CREATES TRANSITIVITY DONALD WITTMAN ECONOMICS DEPARTMENT UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA

On Equality, Social Choice Theory, and Normative Economics

Definition: Institution public system of rules which defines offices and positions with their rights and duties, powers and immunities p.

Rising Inequality and Globalisation. Thomas Piketty EHESS and Paris School of Economics Utrecht, May

Empirical Research on Economic Inequality Why study inequality?

The Restoration of Welfare Economics

Political Economics II Spring Lectures 4-5 Part II Partisan Politics and Political Agency. Torsten Persson, IIES

Working Paper No. 13/05. Personal responsibility and income distribution

Econ 551 Government Finance: Revenues Fall 2018

ECON 4270 Distributive Justice Lecture 4: Rawls and liberal equality

Problems with Group Decision Making

14.770: Introduction to Political Economy Lectures 4 and 5: Voting and Political Decisions in Practice

The determinants of the preferences for redistribution

Global Fairness and Aid

Nordic Journal of Political Economy

Empirical research on economic inequality Lecture notes on theories of justice (preliminary version) Maximilian Kasy

VALUING DISTRIBUTIVE EQUALITY CLAIRE ANITA BREMNER. A thesis submitted to the Department of Philosophy. in conformity with the requirements for

Social Choice Theory. Denis Bouyssou CNRS LAMSADE

2015/5. Optimal taxation theory and principles of fairness. Marc Fleurbaey and François Maniquet

The Political Economy of Trade Policy

Median voter theorem - continuous choice

2 Political-Economic Equilibrium Direct Democracy

Topics on the Border of Economics and Computation December 18, Lecture 8

3 Electoral Competition

Thinkwell s Homeschool Economics Course Lesson Plan: 36 weeks

John Stuart Mill ( )

(67686) Mathematical Foundations of AI June 18, Lecture 6

Remarks on the Political Economy of Inequality

History of Social Choice and Welfare Economics

14.770: Introduction to Political Economy Lectures 4 and 5: Voting and Political Decisions in Practice

Capital in the 21 st century A Middle East Perspective. Thomas Piketty Paris School of Economics Cairo, June

Extended Abstract: The Swing Voter s Curse in Social Networks

Some reflections on the role of moral reasoning in economics

2. Welfare economics and the rationale for public intervention 2.3. Equity: From Social Efficiency to Social Welfare

LECTURE 3. Theories of Social Justice, the State and Economic Inequality

2.2. From social efficiency to social welfare - Equity issues (Stiglitz ch.5, Gruber ch.2)

Principles of Distributive Justice

Social Welfare, Individual Well-being and Opportunity Sets

CSC304 Lecture 16. Voting 3: Axiomatic, Statistical, and Utilitarian Approaches to Voting. CSC304 - Nisarg Shah 1

S E N, A M A R T Y A K.

Princeton University Press

Political Economy of Institutions and Development. Lectures 11 and 12. Information, Beliefs and Politics

1 Electoral Competition under Certainty

Human Development and the current economic and social challenges

CS 886: Multiagent Systems. Fall 2016 Kate Larson

David Rosenblatt** Macroeconomic Policy, Credibility and Politics is meant to serve

Lecture 16: Voting systems

I assume familiarity with multivariate calculus and intermediate microeconomics.

Racism, xenophobia, and redistribution

Why Rawls's Domestic Theory of Justice is Implausible

CSC304 Lecture 14. Begin Computational Social Choice: Voting 1: Introduction, Axioms, Rules. CSC304 - Nisarg Shah 1

Voter Participation with Collusive Parties. David K. Levine and Andrea Mattozzi

The Social Choice Theory: Can it be considered a Complete Political Theory?

Economic Growth and the Interests of Future (and Past and Present) Generations: A Comment on Tyler Cowen

Voluntary Voting: Costs and Benefits

Tilburg University. Can a brain drain be good for growth? Mountford, A.W. Publication date: Link to publication

1 Aggregating Preferences

VI. Rawls and Equality

14.770: Introduction to Political Economy Lectures 8 and 9: Political Agency

COWLES FOUNDATION FOR RESEARCH IN ECONOMICS YALE UNIVERSITY

IMPARTIAL JUSTICE: CONDITIONS AND IMPLICATIONS

On Optimal Voting Rules under Homogeneous Preferences

Philosophy 285 Fall, 2007 Dick Arneson Overview of John Rawls, A Theory of Justice. Views of Rawls s achievement:

Market failures. If markets "work perfectly well", governments should just play their minimal role, which is to:

Social Choice & Mechanism Design

Normative Frameworks 1 / 35

Collective Decision with Costly Information: Theory and Experiments

ONLINE APPENDIX: Why Do Voters Dismantle Checks and Balances? Extensions and Robustness

Any non-welfarist method of policy assessment violates the Pareto principle: A comment

What makes people feel free: Subjective freedom in comparative perspective Progress Report

Pork Barrel as a Signaling Tool: The Case of US Environmental Policy

Immigration and Conflict in Democracies

Public Choice. Slide 1

POLITICAL EQUILIBRIUM SOCIAL SECURITY WITH MIGRATION

Poverty and inequality: Unequal challenges ahead

Tax Competition and Migration: The Race-to-the-Bottom Hypothesis Revisited

Social choice theory

Chapter 2 Positive vs Normative Analysis

Section 1: Microeconomics. 1.1 Competitive Markets: Demand and Supply. IB Econ Syllabus Outline. Markets Ø The Nature of Markets

Inequality and economic growth

CH 19. Name: Class: Date: Multiple Choice Identify the choice that best completes the statement or answers the question.

Olsen JA (2009): Principles in Health Economics and Policy, Oxford University Press, Oxford. Lecture 4: Equality & Fairness.

Political Economics Handout. The Political Economics of Redistributive Policies. Vincenzo Galasso

A Rawlsian Paradigm Case

Reflections on Inequality and Capital in the 21 st century. Thomas Piketty Paris School of Economics LSE, May

Do we have a strong case for open borders?

Reconciling Educational Adequacy and Equity Arguments Through a Rawlsian Lens

Do not turn over until you are told to do so by the Invigilator.

political budget cycles

THE CAPABILITY APPROACH AS A HUMAN DEVELOPMENT PARADIGM AND ITS CRITIQUES

Should Fiscal Policy be Set by Politicians?

Economic Perspective. Macroeconomics I ECON 309 S. Cunningham

Transcription:

Public Economics: Tax & Transfer Policies (Master PPD & APE, Paris School of Economics) Thomas Piketty Academic year 2016-2017 Lecture 2: Normative theories of social and fiscal justice in historical perspective (check on line for updated versions)

Roadmap of lecture 2 The notion of social objective function Utilitarianism, maximin, general SWF Non-welfarist social objectives Condorcet paradox & majority cycles Condorcet jury theorem & the constructive view of political institutions A simple model of inequality and beliefs

The notion of social objective function «Social objective function» (or «social welfare function», SWF) = complete description of the set of objectives and values (together with trade-offs and priorities between these objectives and values) that the social planner maximizes in order to determine the socially optimal policy Of course in the real world there exists no benevolent social planner. Different individuals and social groups may have contradictory objectives, preferences and values (as well as different beliefs systems about how the economy is working, elasticity parameters, etc.)

But the interesting point is that individuals are not selfish, or at least do not present their mostpreferred policy as determined by their self-interest: they usually refer to more universal objectives («if you cut my taxes, in the end this is also going to be good for the poor»). Even if they are not always entirely sincere (pb of self-serving beliefs), these statements illustrate need to refer to universal moral values and objectives This in itself is interesting, and it does put constraints on political discourses and outcomes. Therefore the discussion on the social objective function and about normative theories of justice is critical if we want to understand actual policies

Utilitarianism, maximin, general SWF Utilitarian objective: W = 1 i n U i = maximize the sum of individual utilities Pb = one needs to assume that interpersonal comparisons of utility levels make sense, and that one can sum them up. Not clear at all that it makes any sense. Maximin objective: W = Min 1 i n U i = maximize welfare of individuals with minimal welfare level One needs to be able to determine who has the lowest welfare level (the most disadvantaged social group). This is less challenging than summing up utilities. But still not easy.

General social welfare function: W = 1 i n V(U i ), with V(U i ) = concave transformation of individual utility If V(U) is linear (V(U)=U) back to utilitarianism If V(U) is infinitely concave back to maximin The concavity of the social welfare function V(.) determines the collective preference for redistribution, from utilitarianism to maximin (together with concavity of individual utility functions)

Exemple. U(c)=c (linear utility for consumption) V(c)=c 1-γ /(1-γ) (for all γ 0, γ 1) V(c)=log(c) (if γ=1) Marginal social welfare V (c)= c -γ (for all γ 0) As γ, V(c) becomes infinitely concave, i.e. individuals with higher consumption levels bring infinitely small marginal social welfare (as compared to individuals with lower consumption levels) stronger social preference for equality If there is no incentive cost to redistribution, then any γ>0 leads to full redistribution: Max 1 i n V(c i ) under budget constraint 1 i n c i C = Y (fixed) c i = C/n (full equality) With incentive costs (labor supply, etc.), full equality is generally not optimal; for given incentive costs, higher γ more redistribution

Other possible objective function: output maximization (SWF = Y = 1 i n c i ) (U(c)=c, γ=0) (GDP maximization) Output maximization is not seriously defended as a proper ethical objective by anyone: everybody seems to agree that it is better to have 100 individuals with 10 000 each rather than 99 individuals with 0 and 1 individual with 1 000 100, in spite of the fact that total income is higher in the second case But output maximization is sometime adopted by economists so as not to deal explicitely with distributive issues: «let s maximize output, and then it will be possible to distribute it so as to raise everybody s welfare, in a second stage» Ok, except that the second stage often never happens It is impossible to separate production & distribution; one needs to adress distributive issues explicitely from the beginning Output maximization raises not-so-simple intertemporal issues: OK let s Maximize Y=C+S, but what is optimal saving & capital accumulation, i.e. how much should we save for the next generations? See lecture 7

Non-welfarist social objectives Ralws, A Theory of Justice, 1971. Two principles of justice: (1) Each person is to have an equal right to the most extensive basic liberty compatible with a similar liberty for others (2) Social and economic inequalities are to be arranged so that they are to be of the greatest benefit to the leastadvantaged members of society ( maximin) Rawls is sometime summarized by economists by the maximin principle ( Rawlsian social welfare function ) However Rawls theory is more subtle: in his view, first principle (most extensive basic rights for all) has explicit and absolute priority over second principle (maximin) Non-welfarist approach: basic rights (opportunity sets) have value in themselves, independently from welfare or utility considerations; choice process is important in itself

The rights-based approach is most appropriate to account for the rise of the social and fiscal state. Modern redistribution is based upon a logic of access to substantial and concrete rights (access to free and compulsory education, access to free health care, etc.), not upon a logic of utilitarian or maximin monetary redistribution. Q.: Do basic rights only include formal right to own, move, speech, vote? What about rights to education, health, work, housing, culture, effective democracy? This is where the discussion becomes interesting Rawls approach is maybe too restrictive and abstract, and not sufficiently explicit: rights involve political conflicts; they are are grounded in history and must be studied as such; at an abstract level, many declarations of rights express principles that are not too different from Rawls (e.g. 1789, article 1)

Les hommes naissent et demeurent libres et égaux en droits. Les distinctions sociales ne peuvent être fondées que sur l utilité commune (Déclaration des droits de l homme et du citoyen, 1789, article 1) ( Men are born and remain free and equal in rights. Social distinctions can only be based upon common utility ) (sentence 2 can be interpreted as maximin) And yet it took a long time for effective rights to be extended (beyond formal equality) A. Sen develops a more concrete approach to rights and capabilities : Commodities and capabilities, OUP 1987; Development as Freedom, Anchor 1999; The Idea of Justice, HUP 2009; Development as Freedom: an Indian Perspective, IJIR 2006

Harsanyi ( Can the Maximin Principle Serve as a Basis for Morality? A Critique of John Rawls's Theory, APSR 1975): maximin makes no sense: it could require us to sacrifice everything we have, just to improve slightly the well being of a small group of handicapped or mentally retarded or incurable individuals; utilitarianism makes more sense Interesting, but: (1) Harsanyi ignores Rawls first principle (basic rights and opportunities), in spite of the fact that his exemples involve substantial rights and opportunities (handicap, health), rather than abstract monetary redistribution (2) Harsanyi does not tell us how we can agree about a concavity parameter for utilitarian social welfare function

Condorcet paradox & majority cycles Arrow, Social Choice and Individual Values, 1951 Impossibility theorem = if we rule out interpersonal comparisons of utilities, then there is no consistent collective rule to aggregate individual preferences and take collective decisions (i.e. we need minimal agreement about common values and goods) In particular, the majority rule does not work: in general, one can find policies A,B,C such that a majority prefers A to B, B to C, and C to A Condorcet paradox 1785: with multi-dimensional political conflicts, majority cycles are pervasive ( democracy needs to be organized, constitution design is important) Arrow 1951 = negative results about political institutions = equivalent of Debreu 1959 Theory of Value An axiomatic analysis of economic equilibrum = positive results about economic institutions (two welfare theorems)

Concrete exemples of multi-dimensional political conflict: attitudes vertical redistribution dimension (public sector, taxation) vs attitudes vs foreigners/migrants See Roemer-Lee-Van der Straeten, Racism, Xenophobia, and Distribution: Multi-Issue Politics in Advanced Democracies, HUP 2007; JEEA 2006; JE 2005 : the xenophobia dimension substantially reduces the equilibrium level of vertical redistribution (size of public sector, etc.) Next step: are majority cycles possible? I.e. Hollande beats Sarkozy, who beats Le Pen, who beats Hollande. Not there yet, but not impossible. Electoral system is important. Deliberation system is even more important. See also Kuziemko-Norton-Saez-Stantcheva, «How Elastic are Preferences for Redistribution?», AER 2015. Inequality dimension vs trust-in-government dimension.

Condorcet jury theorem and the constructive view of political institutions Condorcet jury theorem. Assume that everybody has the same objective function (same values and preferences), but has different beliefs and information about what policy is optimal (given these values and preferences). Further assume that we have to choose between two policies A and B, that everybody receives a signal providing information as to whether A or B is the optimal policy, and that everybody has the same probability p>0.5 to receive the right signal. Then with a large population, the probability that the majority rule leads to the right decision approaches 1. Nobody wants to be dictator, everybody prefers democracy.

With different signal qualities, more than 2 policies, etc. then one may prefer indirect democracy, etc.: constitution design matters See Condorcet 1785, Essai sur l application de l analyse à la probabilité des décisions rendues à la pluralité des voix ; and Condorcet s contribution to revolutionary debates on ideal constitution Condorcet jury theorem = basic positive result about democratic institutions (aggregation of information through voting). Equivalent to Arrow- Debreu positive result about economic institutions (aggregation of information through the markets) The jury theorem and the majority-cycle paradox should be viewed as complementary: democracy can work, but it needs to be organized

If political conflict is about different beliefs and information (and not simply about conflicting interests and preferences), then different electoral & political systems allow for different aggregation of information: see Piketty The Information-Aggregation Approach to Political Institutions, EER 1999 But even if politics is about information, communication is always limited (pb of credibility with different prior beiefs): see Spector, Rational Debate Leads to One-Dimensional Conflict, QJE 2000 Politics is also about conflicting interests and self-serving beliefs. So it is important to regulate political finance, access to the media, etc. See Bonica-Rosenthal, «Why Hasn t Democracy Slowed Rising Inequality», JEP 2013; T. Kuhner, Capitalism vs Democracy: Money in Politics and the Free Market Constitution, SUP 2014

A simple model of inequality and beliefs The aim of this simple model is to illustrate the discussion about values vs beliefs Two possible income levels: y 0 < y 1 y 0 = low-paid job; y 1 = high-paid job Probability (y i =y 1 ) = π 0 + θe i if parental income = y 0 Probability (y i =y 1 ) = π 1 + θe i if parental income = y 1 With e i = effort, θ = index of how much individual effort matters, Δπ =π 1 - π 0 = index of how much inequality in social origins matters (better access to education, connexions to find jobs, etc.)

Redistributive taxation: c 0 =(1-t)y 0 +ty, c 1 =(1-t)y 1 +ty, With t = income tax rate, y=(1-p)y 0 +py 1 = average pretax income, p = pop. fraction getting high income Per capita tax revenue ty used to pay lump-sum cash transfer (or to finance equal access to education or other public services) t=0% : no redistribution; t=100%: full redistribution Individual i has utility U i =c i -C(e i ), with C(e)=e 2 /2a: Max (1-p i )c 0 + p i c 1 C(e i ), with p i = π i + θe i FO condition: e i = aθ(1-t)(y 1 -y 0 ) more redistribution leads to less effort how much this matters depends on relative importance of θ vs Δπ

Assume everybody agrees about some form of maximin objective: Max (1-p)c 0 + pc 1 C(e), with p = π 0 + θe (i.e. expected welfare of individuals with low parental income) Then one can show that optimal t* is given by: t* = HΔπ/a(y 1 -y 0 )θ 2 (H = pop fraction of indiv. with high-income parents) I.e. optimal tax t* if Δπ or θ, i.e. if parental origins more important & role of effort less important But this does not mean that everybody agrees about t* : different beliefs about Δπ and θ can lead to different t* politics as a conflict over beliefs See Piketty, Social Mobility & Redistributive Politics, QJE 1995

Why different beliefs? Because it is difficult to learn about Δπ and θ Self-serving beliefs also play a role: high-income individuals have a clear incentive to pretend that θ matters more than Δπ, and to try to spread their views in the media & political parties But even if all individuals have fully sincere, and start with same initial beliefs, one can show that different families will end up with different beliefs: e.g. if you put a lot of effort experience an upward mobility experience, you will tend to believe that effort works and update your beliefs accordingly This can explain why mobility experience and not only current income determines political attitudes

In the long run, high-income individuals tend to be more right-wing on average than low-income individuals (they want less redistribution), even if they are not selfish at all (in effect, right-wing dynasties believe more in effort and end up with higher average incomes, whether their beliefs are right or wrong) Other, more sophisticated ways to learn about optimal t*: study the comparative history of inequality and taxation, read econometric estimates of elasticities: see Lectures 3-4 But there will always be a lot of uncertainty about the conclusions one can draw from historical or econometric evidence, so the political conflict will continue, and democratic institutions will do what they can to aggregate these different beliefs

This simple model also illustrates the difficulties to define the proper social objective Assume Δπ=0, i.e. family origins do not matter, everybody faces the same probability π + θe to have high income y 1 > y 0 With risk aversion (U i =V(c i )-C(e i ) and V(.) concave), one still wants redistributive taxation But with U i =c i -C(e i ), do we really want t*=0? If y 1 vs y 0 = long-term, lifetime inequality, then risk aversion might not be the relevant way to determine the socially desirable level of redistribution (with short-term risk, this is questionable as well: public unemployment insurance) Assume social objective = Max c 0 C(e)

Max c 0 C(e) = (1-t)y 0 +ty C(e) with e = aθ(1-t)(y 1 -y 0 ), y=(1-p)y 0 +py 1, p=π + θe Then one can show that t* = 2/3 + π/3a(y 1 -y 0 )θ 2 (formula to be checked; please do it for next time!) This leads to much more redistribution than with expected welfare maximization Discussion about objective function matters, together with the discussion about beliefs and elasticities