Postscript: Subjective Utilitarianism

Similar documents
Ethical Basis of Welfare Economics. Ethics typically deals with questions of how should we act?

Ethics Handout 18 Rawls, Classical Utilitarianism and Nagel, Equality

Efficiency, Utility, and Wealth Maximization

PubPol Values, Ethics, and Public Policy, Fall 2009

The Necessity for Constrained Deliberation

Afterword: Rational Choice Approach to Legal Rules

John Rawls THEORY OF JUSTICE

The Conflict between Notions of Fairness and the Pareto Principle

Interests, Interactions, and Institutions. Interests: Actors and Preferences. Interests: Actors and Preferences. Interests: Actors and Preferences

The Ethics of Wealth Maximization: Reply to Malloy

Economic philosophy of Amartya Sen Social choice as public reasoning and the capability approach. Reiko Gotoh

Kaplow, Louis, and Shavell, Steven. Fairness versus Welfare. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, Pp $50.00 (cloth).

Economic Analysis of Law and the Value of Efficiency

Comments on Justin Weinberg s Is Government Supererogation Possible? Public Reason Political Philosophy Symposium Friday October 17, 2008

Property, Wrongfulness and the Duty to Compensate

Law & Economics Lecture 1: Basic Notions & Concepts

Volume 60, Issue 1 Page 241. Stanford. Cass R. Sunstein

Notes toward a Theory of Customary International Law The Challenge of Non-State Actors: Standards and Norms in International Law

AN EGALITARIAN THEORY OF JUSTICE 1

George Mason University

Ehrenzweig on the Law of Conflict of Laws

-- To obtain permission to use this article beyond the scope of your HeinOnline license, please use:

Normative Frameworks 1 / 35

Rethinking the Theory of Legal Rights

Cambridge University Press The Cambridge Rawls Lexicon Edited by Jon Mandle and David A. Reidy Excerpt More information

On the Irrelevance of Formal General Equilibrium Analysis

Economic Growth and the Interests of Future (and Past and Present) Generations: A Comment on Tyler Cowen

Utilitarianism. Introduction and Historical Background. The Defining Characteristics of Utilitarianism

Compassion and Compulsion

FUNCTIONAL LAW AND ECONOMICS: THE SEARCH FOR VALUE-NEUTRAL PRINCIPLES OF LAWMAKING INTRODUCTION

Rawls versus the Anarchist: Justice and Legitimacy

Keywords: Pareto Efficiency, Wealth-Maximization, Sources of Law, Lawmaking Process, Unanimity, Product Liability.

An Outline of Takings

Prosecuting the Press for Publishing Classified Information

The Ethical and Political Basis of the Efficiency Norm in Common Law Adjudication

Regulatory Policy Program

This page intentionally left blank

The Veil of Ignorance in Rawlsian Theory

I. Identify and or Define. III. Diagrams, Games, and Puzzles. II. Matching exercise: link the following philosophers with their ideas.

RAWLS DIFFERENCE PRINCIPLE: ABSOLUTE vs. RELATIVE INEQUALITY

Jonathan Klick. Francesco Parisi * Abstract

ECONOMIC POLICIES AND SOCIO-ECONOMIC CLAUSES IN THE SOUTH AFRICAN BILL OF RIGHTS.

Robbins as Innovator: the Contribution of An Essay on the Nature and Significance of Economic Science

Handout 6: Utilitarianism

Reply to Arneson. Russel Keat. 1. The (Supposed) Non Sequitur

ECONOMICS AND INEQUALITY: BLINDNESS AND INSIGHT. Sanjay Reddy. I am extremely grateful to Bina Agarwal, IAFFE S President, and to IAFFE for its

Phil 115, June 20, 2007 Justice as fairness as a political conception: the fact of reasonable pluralism and recasting the ideas of Theory

Comments: Individual Versus Collective Responsibility

Comment on Baker's Autonomy and Free Speech

Authority versus Persuasion

Global Aspirations versus Local Plumbing: Comment: on Nussbaum. by Richard A. Epstein

"Efficient and Durable Decision Rules with Incomplete Information", by Bengt Holmström and Roger B. Myerson

that keeps judges' hands off the economic system.

The Efficiency and the Efficacy of Title VII

POLITICAL AUTHORITY AND PERFECTIONISM: A RESPONSE TO QUONG

Matthew Adler, a law professor at the Duke University, has written an amazing book in defense

Course: Economic Policy with an Emphasis on Tax Policy

Lecture 17 Consequentialism. John Stuart Mill Utilitarianism Mozi Impartial Caring

The Cartelization of Commerce

RECONCILING LIBERTY AND EQUALITY: JUSTICE AS FAIRNESS. John Rawls s A Theory of Justice presents a theory called justice as fairness.

The Two Faces of Federalism

Ethical Considerations on Quadratic Voting

Do not turn over until you are told to do so by the Invigilator.

Outline of a talk to the conference of the International Adam Smith Society Valparaiso, Chile January 2018

Unconstitutional Conditions and Bargaining Breakdown

ELIMINATING CORRECTIVE JUSTICE. Steven Walt *

Solving the "Tragedy of the Commons": An Alternative to Privatization*

Phil 116, April 5, 7, and 9 Nozick, Anarchy, State, and Utopia

An example of public goods

LOGROLLING. Nicholas R. Miller Department of Political Science University of Maryland Baltimore County Baltimore, Maryland

Running Head: The Consequentialism Debate 1. The Consequentialism Debate. Student s Name. Course Name. Course Title. Instructors name.

A Bargaining Theory Approach to Default and Disclosure Provisions in Contract Law

The Entitlement Theory 1 Robert Nozick

1 Justice as fairness, utilitarianism, and mixed conceptions

Human Development and the current economic and social challenges

World-Wide Ethics. Chapter Six. Social Contract Theory. of the social contract theory of morality.

Economic Perspective. Macroeconomics I ECON 309 S. Cunningham

Full file at

The Restoration of Welfare Economics

Criminal Justice Without Moral Responsibility: Addressing Problems with Consequentialism Dane Shade Hannum

PHI 1700: Global Ethics

The Rights and Wrongs of Taking Rights Seriously

MARKETS, METHODS, MORALS AND THE LAW

Elliston and Martin: Whistleblowing

ECONOMIC ANALYSIS AND DISTRIBUTIVE JUSTICE

Social Contract Theory

George Mason University SCHOOL of LAW

Do Voters Have a Duty to Promote the Common Good? A Comment on Brennan s The Ethics of Voting

Policy & precarity what are people able to do and be? Helen Taylor Cardiff Metropolitan

I assume familiarity with multivariate calculus and intermediate microeconomics.

I. Identify and or Define. III. Games and Puzzles

Playing Fair and Following the Rules

Phil 115, May 24, 2007 The threat of utilitarianism

Market Failure: Compared to What?

Phil 115, May 25, 2007 Justice as fairness as reconstruction of the social contract

Law and Economics Session 6

TRANSACTION COST AND THE ORGANIZATION OF OWNERSHIP AN INTRODUCTION

Reply: Legitimacy and Obedience

Implementing Cost-Benefit Analysis when Preferences are Distorted

Primitivist prioritarianism. Hilary Greaves (Oxford) Value of Equality workshop, Jerusalem, July 2016

Transcription:

University of Chicago Law School Chicago Unbound Journal Articles Faculty Scholarship 1989 Postscript: Subjective Utilitarianism Richard A. Epstein Follow this and additional works at: http://chicagounbound.uchicago.edu/journal_articles Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation Richard A. Epstein, "Postscript: Subjective Utilitarianism," 12 Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy 769 (1989). This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Faculty Scholarship at Chicago Unbound. It has been accepted for inclusion in Journal Articles by an authorized administrator of Chicago Unbound. For more information, please contact unbound@law.uchicago.edu.

POSTSCRIPT: SUBJECTIVE UTILITARIANISM RICHARD A. EPSTEIN* In accordance with the Marquis of Queensberry's rules as adapted to academic exchanges, I have not made any changes in my original piece' to take into account Eric Mack's reply. 2 Nonetheless I am so taken aback, not to say stunned, by much of what he has written, that I think a few words of clarification are needed on my position. The fault may lie with me, and if Professor Mack has so misread my orientation, so might others. I hope to correct the misimpressions before they become widespread. The key question is what it means to be a utilitarian. In Mack's view, which I take it has a long philosophical tradition, utilitarians are people who believe that there is an objective, disembodied, and impersonal good independent of persons, one that can be attached to given individuals and then summed in some arithmetic way. The world is thus viewed as one large organism of sorts where the pleasures of one person can be offset against the pains of another. Utility then is conceived as an impersonal value not attached to any single person. I should have thought that it was dear from my article (as in my comments on Dworkin's Derek and Amartya example) 3 that I did not use utilitarianism in this "impersonal" sense, but rather as a theory that measures the desirability of alternative legal rules by the consequences that they generate for the persons they govern. In taking this position I quite agree with Mack that value is in some ultimate sense subjective, so that interpersonal comparisions of utility cannot be made rigorously. In saying this I do not want to be taken as committing myself to a necessary philosophical truth, but only to a maxim of political behavior. I believe that we all make interpersonal comparisons of utility every day of our lives in our family, play and work settings. I think that the impulse to religious and charitable conduct is quite incomprehensible if these judgments were, at * James Parker Hall Distinguished Service Professor of Law, University of Chicago. 1. See Epstein, The Utilitarian Foundations of Natural Law, 12 HARV. J.L. & PUB. POL'Y 713 (1989). 2. See Mack, A Costly Road to Natural Law, 12 HARV. J.L. & PuB. PoL'Y 753 (1989). 3. See Epstein, supra note 1, at 745-49. HeinOnline -- 12 Harv. J. L. & Pub. Pol'y 769 1989

770 Harvard Journal of Law & Public Policy [Vol. 12 least in a rough way, foreclosed to us in our daily lives. Nonetheless as the numbers of individuals become larger, their affective senses are dulled, and the power to make these judgments weakens. The dangers of using interpersonal comparisons of utility as sources of coercive judgment strike me as exceedingly dangerous within a political system. I shall therefore assume that such judgments should not be part of any legal calculus, however important they are to the social fabric. The question is what should be made of the proposition that all value is subjective and that interpersonal comparisons of utility are out of bounds. Until I read Mack's article, I did not think that the belief in subjective value was incompatible with utilitarianism, given its concerns about the pleasures and pains, about the benefits and burdens of real persons. Quite the opposite, I think that the emphasis on "flourishing" as used by modem natural law writers such as Finnis invites a utilitarian (or consequentialist) reading, even if that reading is disavowed by the writers themselves. Once we accept some form of subjectivism, it must be asked how one can speak about consequences in the aggregate without treating "total utility" as some magical, well-nigh Platonic good that hovers over the individual members of the society. The answer lies I think in the choice of a measure of social welfare that allows judgments-to be made about (total) social states Without requiring interpersonal comparisons of utility. The standard accounts of Pareto superiority appear to me to satisfy both conditions. 4 When one says that state A of the world is better than state B, he means by this criterion that at least one person prefers (by his own subjective lights) state A to state B, while no persons (by his own subjective lights) prefers B to A. In that situation we can collectively prefer A to B without having to make any interpersonal comparisons of utility. Similarly, to say that a state is Pareto optimal means that no one can be made better off unless someone else is made worse off. It is therefore odd to want any social state that is not Pareto Optimal: why not make X better off by his own lights if no one else is hurt thereby. The use of the Pareto test has been attacked as too stringent 4. See, e.g., Coleman. Efficiency., Utiity and Wealth M1aximiation, 8 HoFsTRA L. REV. 509 (1980). HeinOnline -- 12 Harv. J. L. & Pub. Pol'y 770 1989

No. 3] Postscript: Subjective Utilitarianism 771 because it does not allow a movement to state A of the world from state B if any single person is made worse off, which seems highly likely when dealing with massive social programs. With heavy transaction cost barriers in place, we could not move from state B, the status quo, because the necessary side payments could not be made. In response to these pressures, the Kaldor-Hicks test allows the move to be made so long as there is some (hypothetical) transfer of money from X to Y that would leave both parties better off, again measured by their own subjective lights. Even this test, however, does not rely on interpersonal comparison of utility, only an effort to treat as social improvements states that would be achievable if transactions costs were low enough to permit bargaining to take place. 5 The problems with hypothetical compensation are heavily empirical, and perhaps insoluable, but they are not conceptual. Indeed the Kaldor-Hicks test has properties that Mack would applaud because, unlike a total utility test, it rules out any form of coercive redistribution. 6 The winners can only return the losers to their former state by giving back all that they have received, in which case the recipients can obtain no gain. To illustrate, if X starts with 100 and Y with 10, a coerced redistribution resulting in X with 90 and Y with 20 does not meet Kaldor-Hicks test for a social improvement because the only way that X's utility could be restored to the level that it had prior to the transfer is to give him back the 10 units that were taken. The conclusion holds even if each additional unit of wealth subjectively had diminishing marginal utility for X. There may be little lost per unit from the taking, but by the same token only small increments of utility are added as each unit of wealth is restored to its original owner. The principle of diminishing marginal utility holds in both directions, so every unit of wealth that is removed must be restored in order to bring A back to his original utility position. It cannot bed otherwise. Suppose X loses 10 units of wealth, and then 8 units are restored. If he enjoys the same utility -level as before, then we can repeat the process (if it costs less than two units) indefinitely and generate gains not obtainable simply by lowering X's 5. The transaction costs theme, neglected by Mack, was pursued in Epstein, supra note 1. at notes 25, 29, 65 and accompanying text. 6. See, e.g.. id. at notes 28 & 60 and accompanying text. HeinOnline -- 12 Harv. J. L. & Pub. Pol'y 771 1989

Harvard Journal of Law & Public Policy [Vol. 12 wealth 2 (or 10) units initially. Alchemy is no substitute for gainful production. There can be lots of debates as to whether Pareto tests should dominate Kaldor-Hicks tests and in what context. But whatever the relative methods of the two approaches, two points do seem to be clear. First, both approaches, associated with "efficiency" or "social welfare" analysis in economics, seem to fall within some ordinary layman's definition of utilitarian. Surely they are not deontological. Second, these tests do not require positing some Platonic pleasure independent of persons of the sort that Mack decries. The harder question is whether the use of Paretian criteria commits us to some version of "total utility" and "objective values" thought part of classical utilitarianism. Jules Coleman has written for example that "[t]he Pareto-superior standard is often thought of as normatively rooted in classical utilitarianism." 7 Thereafter he appears to take the position that the Pareto standard does require the use of objective comparisons of utility, but he acknowledges that others have disagreed with him. On this point, moreover, I think he is wrong for the reason mentioned above. So long as we know that each person advances by his own lights, then we are confident that total utility (to use that phrase) has advanced, even if we do not know (or care) by how much. We do not have to sum utilities across people to make the necessary comparative judgments. Those who try to make social judgments in a world where interpersonal comparisons are not possible, are, it seems, utilitarians who are skeptical about the belief of interpersonal comparisons of utility. They are certainly not deontologists. It is of course evident that these tests are often very difficult to apply in order to make even rough judgments between alternative legal rules. But what options are open to us? Mack relies upon an intuitive and absolute sense of autonomy that guarantees to each person his own unique preferences, purposes, goals and desires in life. But what should be done when they conflict, as they do, for example, when one person takes something out of the common that another person would like to have as his own? Do we have a realization of the purposes and goals of X or a frustration of the purposes and goals of Y? I 7. Coleman, supra note 4, at 515. HeinOnline -- 12 Harv. J. L. & Pub. Pol'y 772 1989

No. 3] Postscript: Subjective Utilitarianism 773 have tried to show why the first-possession rule is a reasonably good first approximation for the right rule to justify the acquisition of property,just as both Locke and Hume thought, albeit for somewhat different reasons. Autonomy need not be our intellectual primitive, but as a derived principle it is a powerful starting point to develop a system of rights that hopes to yield satisfactions that are Pareto superior to those obtainable in some alternative legal regime. Whether I am right or wrong, it is not enough to talk solely about goals, aims and purposes, and the uniqueness of different individuals. It is necessary to talk as well about the role that scarcity and self-interest have in organizing human affairs. We do not know, for example, whether Mack's view of autonomy is so strong and absolute that it invalidates all forms of taxation, or denies the state the power of eminent domain. Those have been regarded as the necessary consequences of an unlimited commitment to individual autonomy. We need to know whether Mack accepts that strong conclusion, or whether he qualifies it, and if so why. When reasons are given, in the end consequences will count, even for those who believe in subjective value. The large literature on prisoner's dilemma games, public goods, holdout problems and transactions costs makes it clear that autonomy can undermine subjective value in many settings, just as it advances it in most. Once the necessary link between autonomy principle and subjective value is broken, then the intuitive appeal of the deontological position is lost. The more troubled and vexed world of collective action has become inescapable. Today we know enough so that there is no philosophical safe harbor that spares us the pain of hard social choices. Any deontological, natural rights theory that ignores these hard questions of social coordination is a dead loser, today and forever more. HeinOnline -- 12 Harv. J. L. & Pub. Pol'y 773 1989

HeinOnline -- 12 Harv. J. L. & Pub. Pol'y 774 1989