How to approach legitimacy

Similar documents
Introduction: Legitimacy and International Courts

We the Stakeholders: The Power of Representation beyond Borders? Clara Brandi

Advisory Committee on Enforcement

POLITICAL AUTHORITY AND PERFECTIONISM: A RESPONSE TO QUONG

Law Beyond the State: A Reply to Liam Murphy

Miruna Barnoschi Northwestern University August 19, 2016

Sources of law in the WTO

The Relationship Between Constitutionalism and Pluralism

Introduction 478 U.S. 186 (1986) U.S. 558 (2003). 3

Researching the politics of gender: A new conceptual and methodological approach

Chapter 1 The Problem of Judicial Independence

PLURICOURTS. Centre for the Study of the Legitimacy of the International Judiciary

changes in the global environment, whether a shifting distribution of power (Zakaria

Democracy and Common Valuations

The Morality of Conflict

1100 Ethics July 2016

ANDREAS ZIMMERMANN & RAINER HOFMANN, ED., UNITY AND DIVERSITY IN INTERNATIONAL LAW (BERLIN: DUNCKER & HUMBLOT, 2006) By Mario Prost

PLATO s research objectives

Meeting Plato s challenge?

MA International Relations Module Catalogue (September 2017)

11 Legally binding versus nonlegally binding instruments

The Dickson Poon School of Law. King s LLM. International Dispute Resolution module descriptions for prospective students

Democracy, and the Evolution of International. to Eyal Benvenisti and George Downs. Tom Ginsburg* ... National Courts, Domestic

The Legitimacy of Humanitarian Intervention in International Society of The 21 st Century

(GLOBAL) GOVERNANCE. Yogi Suwarno The University of Birmingham

Global Public Goods amidst a Plurality of Legal Orders: A Symposium

Two Pictures of the Global-justice Debate: A Reply to Tan*

Boston University School of Law, Boston, MA Visiting Assistant Professor of Law, July 2015-June 2016

ABSTRACT. Electronic copy available at:

Global Capitalism & Law: An Interdisciplinary Seminar SYLLABUS Reading Materials Books

Summary. The Politics of Innovation in Public Transport Issues, Settings and Displacements

International tribunals: legalization and constitutionalization implications for national constitutional structures

Civil society in the EU: a strong player or a fig-leaf for the democratic deficit?

Part 1. Understanding Human Rights

Constitutional Democracy and World Politics: A Response to Gartzke and Naoi

Mehrdad Payandeh, Internationales Gemeinschaftsrecht Summary

From the veil of ignorance to the overlapping consensus: John Rawls as a theorist of communication

THE RIGHT TO HEALTH OF INDIGENOUS PEOPLES IN THE INDUSTRIALIZED WORLD: A Research Agenda

Identification of customary international law Statement of the Chair of the Drafting Committee Mr. Charles Chernor Jalloh.

Identifying the Enemy: Civilian Participation in Armed Conflict

POLI 111: INTRODUCTION TO THE STUDY OF POLITICAL SCIENCE

POST-2015: BUSINESS AS USUAL IS NOT AN OPTION Peacebuilding, statebuilding and sustainable development

Legitimacy in the European Union, what throughput got to do with it? Giulia Bistagnino WORKING PAPERS

Legal Reasoning, the Rule of Law, and Legal Theory: Comments on Gerald Postema, Positivism and the Separation of the Realists from their Skepticism

Steven Wheatley* Abstract. 1 Introduction. ... A Democratic Rule of International Law

NEW YORK UNIVERSITY Department of Politics. V COMPARATIVE POLITICS Spring Michael Laver Tel:

Penalizing Public Disobedience*

Power: A Radical View by Steven Lukes

Introduction[1] The obstacle

Response to Gianluigi Palombella, Wojciech Sadurski, and Neil Walker

ITUC 1 Contribution to the pre-conference negotiating text for the UNCTAD XII Conference in Accra, April

Libertarianism. Polycarp Ikuenobe A N I NTRODUCTION

Globalisation and Social Justice Group

T05P07 / International Administrative Governance: Studying the Policy Impact of International Public Administrations

Greening International Jurisprudence

GLOBAL DEMOCRACY THE PROBLEM OF A WRONG PERSPECTIVE

On Human Rights by James Griffin, Oxford University Press, 2008, 339 pp.

Is the Ideal of a Deliberative Democracy Coherent?

The Potential Role of the UN Guidelines and the new ILO Recommendation on the Promotion of Cooperatives

Ordering Power: Contentious Politics and Authoritarian Leviathans in Southeast Asia

Disagreement, Error and Two Senses of Incompatibility The Relational Function of Discursive Updating

Justice as fairness The social contract

Comment: Shaming the shameless? The constitutionalization of the European Union

The Human Security Paradigm and Cosmopolitan Democracy 1

Republicanism: Midway to Achieve Global Justice?

Samantha Besson* Abstract. 1 Introduction. ... Sovereignty, International Law and Democracy

A political theory of territory

Last time we discussed a stylized version of the realist view of global society.

Article 30. Exceptions to Rights Conferred

Constitutional Migration reviewed in light of Obedience Theory

1. Introduction. Jonathan Verschuuren

Constitutionalism in International Law: The Limits of Jus Cogens.

TRANSNATIONAL DEMOCRACY, LEGITIMACY AND THE EUROPEAN UNION

PUBLIC POLICY AND PUBLIC ADMINISTRATION (PPPA)

Law and Philosophy (2015) 34: Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2015 DOI /s ARIE ROSEN BOOK REVIEW

CYELP 12 [2016]

Political Norms and Moral Values

We recommend you cite the published version. The publisher s URL is:

Governing Body 328th Session, Geneva, 27 October 10 November 2016

The Legitimate Authority Of International Courts And Its Limits: A. Challenge To Raz s Service Conception? ANDREAS FOLLESDAL *

1 Introduction. Laura Werup Final Exam Fall 2013 IBP Pol. Sci.

Chapter 2 Treaty Interpretation as Opposed to Statutory, Constitutional and Contractual Interpretations

Summary of expert meeting: "Mediation and engaging with proscribed armed groups" 29 March 2012

Public justification in political liberalism: the deep view. Thomas M. Besch

NEW YORK UNIVERSITY Department of Politics V COMPARATIVE POLITICS Spring Michael Laver. Tel:

Social cohesion a post-crisis analysis

B.A. Study in English International Relations Global and Regional Perspective

The public vs. private value of health, and their relationship. (Review of Daniel Hausman s Valuing Health: Well-Being, Freedom, and Suffering)

The Legitimacy Deficits of Human Rights Supervisory Organs the Human Rights Judiciary: Elements and Implications of a Normative Theory 1

Chapter 7: CONTENPORARY MAINSTREAM APPROACHES: NEO-REALISM AND NEO-LIBERALISM. By Baylis 5 th edition

The turn to authority beyond states *

Exam Questions By Year IR 214. How important was soft power in ending the Cold War?

Legal normativity: Requirements, aims and limits. A view from legal philosophy. Elena Pariotti University of Padova

CORRUPTION IN INTERNATIONAL TRADE AND COMMERCIAL ARBITRATION

Comments by Nazanin Shahrokni on Erik Olin Wright s lecture, Emancipatory Social Sciences, Oct. 23 rd, 2007, with initial responses by Erik Wright

A Necessary Discussion About International Law

Ducking Dred Scott: A Response to Alexander and Schauer.

Ideology COLIN J. BECK

Codes of conduct at Canadian multinational enterprises (MNEs): at the confines of private regulation and public policy on labour

Department of Political Science Graduate Course Descriptions Fall 2014

Transcription:

How to approach legitimacy for the book project Empirical Perspectives on the Legitimacy of International Investment Tribunals Daniel Behn, 1 Ole Kristian Fauchald 2 and Malcolm Langford 3 January 2015 1. Introduction The purpose of this note is to provide a framework for how we approach legitimacy in our book project. We wish to provide a framework that is clear in the sense that it will be possible to trace and compare the various approaches to legitimacy of each individual author. At the same time the framework must be sufficiently flexible to let authors focus on the aspects of legitimacy that are most suitable to the topic in question or the author s choice of discipline/s. Our framework consists of questions that we would encourage you to consider when designing and carrying out research for your chapters. It is not necessary that you explicitly consider or respond to the questions in your contributions. 2. Subjects objects We ask you to consider the scope of subjects and objects of legitimacy for the purpose of your contribution. By subjects we refer to the entities that are in need or are seeking legitimacy. Given the focus of the book, the subjects of legitimacy will be the investment tribunals themselves. However, there may be differences in focus in the various contributions. Thus there may be: A focus on either specific categories of tribunals (e.g. ICSID tribunals) or all tribunals; Incorporation of the broader institutional and legal context in which the tribunals are operating, extending legitimacy considerations to: o institutions (e.g. ICSID, UNCITRAL, SCC); o procedural rules (e.g. ICSID Convention, UNCITRAL Arbitration Rules); o substantive rules (e.g. the ECT, BITs, model BITs, investment chapters in FTAs); or o enforcement mechanisms (e.g. the New York Convention). We ask that you distinguish where relevant between the institutional and non-institutional aspects of a regime. 4 1 Postdoctoral Researcher in International Investment Law, PluriCourts, University of Oslo. 2 Professor, PluriCourts, Department of Public and International Law, University of Oslo. 3 Postdoctoral Researcher, PluriCourts, University of Oslo. 1

By objects we refer to the entities that are targets of efforts to increase (or decrease) legitimacy. In the case of investment tribunals, there are multiple actors which are either required to comply with their rules and rulings or possess particular interests in their design and functioning. While core objects are those actors who must directly comply with the ruling of a tribunal (i.e. the case specific host state and investor), 5 we ask you to consider to whether your contribution also focuses on, for example: All potential host states; Home states; Specific institutions and entities within home states and/or host states (e.g. courts, the executive, the legislative, the public); Transnational actors such as specific groups of investors (e.g. big multinationals, SMEs, investors within certain sectors), intergovernmental political and adjudicative institutions (e.g. human rights bodies, the ILO, the World Bank), and non-governmental organizations and movements; or Entities that advise states and investors (e.g. law firms, business associations, the OECD, UNCTAD). If you decide to leave some relevant objects out of your legitimacy considerations, we encourage you to reflect on the implication this may have for your findings. 3. Purposes factors We further ask you to consider which purposes legitimacy may serve as well as the factors that contribute to or detract from legitimacy in the context of your contribution. Such a disaggregated approach is arguably relevant regardless of one s choice of analytical framework for legitimacy assessment normative, sociological or political (see further section 4.) 4 As Meyer and Sanklecha put it in the case of normative legitimacy analysis, between determining what the social ideal consists of as opposed to how institutions ought to be designed. L. Meyer and P. Sanklecha, 'Introduction: Legitimacy, Justice and Public International Law. Three Perspectives on the Debate' in L. Meyer (ed.) Justice, Legitimacy and Public International Law (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2009), pp. 1-28, at 21. 5 International courts and tribunals have much weaker coercive aspects than national courts. The coercive aspects of investment tribunals are a complex topic. The coerciveness of their decisions is dependent on the law and courts of host states as well as the possibility of achieving enforcement within other jurisdictions. While such coercion may be an element of establishing the peculiarity and force of investment tribunals, it may not primarily account for all of their influence on states behavior. However, this coercive view of law and courts has been strongly challenged. For instance, Hart argued that the role of law is primarily normative, providing reasons to act: rules provide the reason and justification for any use of coercive authority, Hart, The Concept of Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1961). Raz has claimed that law is essentially an authoritative social institution that affects the calculus of our practical reason and action, J. Raz, 'Law, Authority and Morality ', in J. Raz (ed.), Ethics in the Public Domain (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1994). Alternatively, and downplaying individual agency, legal norms may be simply acculturated: R. Goodman and D. Jinks, 'Incomplete Internalization and Compliance with Human Rights Law', European Journal of International Law, Vol. 19 No. 4 (2008), pp. 725-48. Thus, the legitimacy of investment tribunals may be relevant for or compel compliance even where important elements of coercion is available. 2

It may be useful first to reflect on the purposes that legitimacy could serve. Legitimacy analyses - whether normative, sociological or political are often guided by a particular understanding of the purpose of a regime, and this is especially critical in framing output legitimacy (see below). Viewed broadly, there is significant disagreement concerning the purposes of investment tribunals, and consequently also disagreement regarding the purposes that legitimacy could serve. Some argue that investment tribunals only serve to resolve disputes between investors and states (and in some instances between states). Others argue that investment tribunals contribute to building a coherent body of case law in the field of international investment law. Some also argue that such a body of case law contributes to establish customary rules of international law. Yet others argue that investment tribunals contribute to the effectiveness and status of international investment law when applied along with other rules of international law. From a broader perspective (than law), it can be argued that investment tribunals aim at promoting investment, increasing predictability for investors and provide stable investment climates. Against this background, we may take as a starting point that there would be agreement that the core purpose that legitimacy may serve for investment tribunals is to influence disputing parties to voluntarily comply with decisions. To many, the purpose could extend further. One aspect is the willingness of third parties affected by the conclusions of investment tribunals (e.g. local populations, employees, and the investors home states) to respect the conclusions of the tribunal. Another aspect is the extent to which other relevant actors (see the list of objects above) respect the analytical approach, the interpretations, and/or the conclusions of the investment tribunal as authoritative. We also ask you to consider which factors contribute to or detract from legitimacy. The chapters may differ significantly in their approach to relevant factors. While some authors may focus on specific factors, other contributions may seek to identify all factors of relevance to legitimacy. Factors may be closely interrelated and interdependent in terms of their effects on legitimacy. Examples of factors that may be relevant include: Selection of arbitrators; Transparency of proceedings and judgments; Participation of third parties in proceedings; Diversity in terms of investors bringing cases; Diversity in terms of host states being sued; The role of law firms in promoting disputes; The quality and consistency of the legal reasoning of tribunals; and Systemic bias towards particular states or investors. 4. Normative, sociological and political legitimacy There is no authoritative or generally accepted definition of legitimacy ; but there does seem to be general consensus on the differing types. The two principal ways of conceptualizing legitimacy 3

are normative and sociological. We ask you to consider which analytical approach(es) you take to legitimacy in light of the distinctions drawn up in the following. Buchanan and Keohane define normative legitimacy in the context of global governance institutions as: the right to rule, understood to mean both that institutional agents are morally justified in making rules and attempting to secure compliance with them and that people subject to those rules have moral, content-independent reasons to follow them and/or to not interfere with others compliances with them. 6 This normative conception of legitimacy concerns the rightness of an institutions exertion of power within a society: it is a set of moral standards by which an institution or regime is judged or justified. In the context of legal institutions, normative legitimacy may also carry claims about legal authority that according to some (i.e. exclusive positivists) are not based on moral justification. Normative legitimacy is closely related to legal legitimacy. The latter is grounded in an institution s observance of its legally constrained mandate. This notion is clear in Abi-Saab s attack on the use of normative legitimacy assessments: I would discard from the discourse of legitimacy any attempt to use it as a means to dodge or get around the law; as a passé-droit, a licence trumping legality or a justification of its violation. 7 While his assumption that normative legitimacy is usually more expansive than legal legitimacy is doubtful, the point is clear. Yet, positive law remains highly relevant to one constituent element of normative legitimacy: the fundamental role of consent in international law. Any application of normative legitimacy needs to take seriously the existence of legal mandates and jurisdictional constraints. In the field of investment treaty arbitration, part of the debate is precisely concerned with the scope of the legal mandate. Sociological legitimacy is a conception of legitimacy that is behavioral, empirical, or descriptive. It asks whether the governed believe and accept that an institution has, or maintains, the power to rule over them. In this Weberian sense, we ask whether individuals affirm a system of authority and lend it prestige, such that obedience may follow. 8 This type of legitimacy is descriptive in the sense that its purpose is to empirically catalogue belief systems of those subject to a particular legal system, institution or set of rules. It does not claim to evaluate whether those beliefs are normatively justified. International lawyers and international relations scholars sometimes conflate normative and sociological conceptions. Some may argue that the two go together in practice and that the former is a proxy for the latter (e.g. if an institution is normatively legitimate it is likely to be accepted as such). This is a questionable approach: actor beliefs may diverge significantly from the results of a principle-based analysis. This divergence is often apparent for judges and arbitrators: 6 A. Buchanen and R. Keohane, 'The Legitimacy of Global Governance Institutions' in R. Wolfrum and V. Röben (eds.), Legitimacy in International Law (Berlin: Springer, 2008), pp. 25-62, at 25. 7 G. Abi-Saab, 'Security Council as Legislator and as Executive in its Fight Against Terrorism and Against Proliferation of Weapons of Mass Destruction', in ibid., pp. 109-130, at 116. 8 M. Weber, The Theory of Social and Economic Organization (New York: Free Press, 1964), 382. 4

certain decisions or reasoning may build sociological legitimacy but weaken normative legitimacy, and vice-versa. Nonetheless, following Habermas and others, it is important to underline that sociological perspectives can sharpen normative theory. 9 If, contrary to normative expectations, an institution or regime is unable (or able) to maintain legitimacy in practice, those very expectations may require reconsideration. A sociological perspective can therefore heighten awareness of the real as opposed to imagined powers of institutions and provide alternative pathways to legitimate rule. 10 Likewise, the framing of sociological legitimacy is dependent or conceptually parasitic on some a priori conception of normative legitimacy. 11 To these two standard conceptions, we could add what could be crudely labelled political legitimacy. In political science we often find studies of the strategies of actors to legitimate themselves, particular institutions, or particular norms. The aim of such actors is often to strengthen normative or sociological legitimacy. The focus of research interest is how these actors behave. As this might be relevant to a number of the proposed empirical chapters, we would also encourage contributions that focus on the politics of building legitimacy. And, of course, such studies would provide indications of the grounded and contextual elements of normative and sociological legitimacy. 5. Elements of legitimacy The respective elements of normative legitimacy and their relevant weight are a matter of long debate in political theory as well as in political science and law. They can be framed and disaggregated in multiple ways within and across different disciplines and traditions. 12 It is not particularly controversial to disaggregate normative legitimacy into three elements: input, process ( throughput ), and output. 1. Input or consent legitimacy refers to the constitutive process for establishing and maintaining institutions or regimes. In relation to investment tribunals, this element can be evaluated against standards of consent and participation. 9 J. Habermas, Communication and the Evolution of Society (Boston: Beacon Press, 1979), 205. 10 B. Gilley, The Right to Rule (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2009), xiii cited in J. Kane and H. Patapan, 'Recovering Justice: Political Legitimacy Reconsidered', Politics & Policy, Vol. 38 No. 3 (2010), pp. 589-610, at 605. 11 D. Bodansky, 'Legitimacy in International Law and International Relations' in J. Dunoff and M. Pollack (eds.), Interdisciplinary Perspectives on International Law and International Relations (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2013), pp. 321-343, at 327. 12 For different perspectives on disaggregating normative legitimacy, see A. Føllesdal, 'Survey Article: The Legitimacy Deficits of the European Union', The Journal of Political Philosophy Vol. 14 No. 4 (2006), pp. 441 468, D. Bodansky, 'The Legitimacy of International Governance: A Coming Challenge for International. Environmental Law?', American Journal of International Law, Vol. 93 No. 3 (1999), pp. 596-624, G. Ulfstein, 'Do We Need a World Court of Human Rights?' in O. Engdahl and P. Wrange (eds.), The Law as it was and the Law as it Should Be (2008), pp. 261-272, M. Thatcher and A. Stone Sweet, 'Theory and Practice of Delegation to Non-Majoritarian Institutions', West European Politics, Vol. 25 No. 1 (2002), pp. 1-22. 5

2. Process (or throughput) legitimacy generally refers to the process by which rules, decisions, and actions are made, applied, or interpreted. Investment tribunals may be (or be viewed as) legitimate if they fulfil certain criteria such as transparency, accountability, and due process or contribute to more effective participation (commonly referred to as standards of procedural justice or fairness). 13 3. Output legitimacy generally refers to the instrumental or substantive justifications for an institution; and how outcomes from a tribunal s decision-making process are to be evaluated. Different aspects of output may be relevant, ranging from the negative (e.g. avoidance of extreme injustice ) 14 to the positive (e.g. the fulfilment of a moderate range of public goods) 15 through to thick optimal and just outcomes. 16 In addition, there may be positive and negative outputs and the definitions of each may be highly contested. There are questions over whether we can count output that is far-removed from the intended purpose of the tribunal as positive. 17 As to the elements of sociological legitimacy, more inductive approaches are necessary. While the elements of normative legitimacy can provide a starting point, these elements may not be relevant to a particular actor s view on an institution s legitimacy. For sociological legitimacy, it may be important to identify: Which actors or audiences are the subject of the legitimacy elements (see the subject object discussion above); Whether the assessment relates to general or specific aspects about the tribunal (e.g. a particular decision or aspects of its rules of procedure); The advantages and disadvantages of different methods in ascertaining the actors beliefs; Whether beliefs are stable or not; and Whether there are particular background conditions for the formation of beliefs. 18 6. Balancing elements of legitimacy One of the most critical questions in a legitimacy assessment concerns balancing: can one of the elements of legitimacy be traded-off against the other elements? Trade-offs between the different elements of legitimacy seem plausible but the degree of permissible balancing is arguably constrained and context-dependent. In this sense, legitimacy remains an overall binary measure (something is legitimate or not legitimate) but the weight or contribution of its elements may 13 Bodansky n. 8 above. 14 Buchanen and Keohane n. 3 above at 44. 15 Gilley n. 7 above at xiv, 220 as discussed in Kane and Patapan n. 7 above at 605. 16 F. Peter, 'Political Legitmacy' in E. N. Zalta (ed.) Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (2010), pp. 13-14. 17 Buchanen and Keohane n. 3 above at 47-49 discuss this institutional integrity dilemma although their case studies largely focus on harms. The dilemma is most acute when a tribunal produces overall or different benefits but not the targeted or intended benefit. 18 See, e.g., J. Gibson, G. Caldeira and V. Baird, 'On the Legitimacy of National High Courts', American Political Science Review, Vol. 92 No. 2 (1998), pp. 343-358, at 351 and updated results in J. Gibson, 'The Legitimacy of the U.S. Supreme Court in a Polarized Polity', Journal of Empirical Legal Studies, Vol. 4 No. 3 (2007), pp. 507-538. 6

operate on a scale. Importantly, this disaggregated approach allows one to assess the scope and size of the legitimacy gap and how one might address it in context. We might for example ask whether diminished input or process legitimacy can be offset by higher output legitimacy. And, is a procedurally cautious investment tribunal legitimate if it fails to fulfil its substantive mandate? 7