Journal of Public Economics

Similar documents
Centralized and decentralized of provision of public goods

Lecture 7: Decentralization. Political economy of decentralization is a hot topic. This is due to a variety of policiy initiatives all over the world

ECON 1000 Contemporary Economic Issues (Summer 2018) Government Failure

A Note on the Optimal Punishment for Repeat Offenders

Measuring Distributed Durations with Stable Errors

The political economy of publicly provided private goods

Inefficient Lobbying, Populism and Oligarchy

Inefficient lobbying, populism and oligarchy

Rethinking the Brain Drain

Diversionary Incentives and the Bargaining Approach to War

econstor Make Your Publications Visible.

Endogenous Political Institutions

COMMONWEALTH OF VIRGINIA STATE CORPORATION COMMISSION AT RICHMOND, FEBRUARY 25, 2019

Is Immigration Necessary and Sufficient? The Swiss Case on the Role of Immigrants on International Trade. Yener Kandogan

Corruption and Ideology in Autocracies

Enriqueta Aragones Harvard University and Universitat Pompeu Fabra Andrew Postlewaite University of Pennsylvania. March 9, 2000

Testing Export-Led Growth in Bangladesh: An ARDL Bounds Test Approach

DISCUSSION PAPER SERIES. Schooling Forsaken: Education and Migration. IZA DP No Ilhom Abdulloev Gil S. Epstein Ira N. Gang

Inequality and Employment in a Dual Economy: Enforcement of Labor Regulation in Brazil

Information Aggregation in Voting with Endogenous Timing

Spectrum: Retrieving Different Points of View from the Blogosphere

How do migrants care for their elderly parents? Time, money, and location #

Logrolling under Fragmented Authoritarianism: Theory and Evidence from China

Documento de Trabajo /13. On the Treatment of Foreigners and Foreign-Owned Firms in Cost Benefit Analysis

Two-stage electoral competition in two-party contests: persistent divergence of party positions

Political Economics II Spring Lectures 4-5 Part II Partisan Politics and Political Agency. Torsten Persson, IIES

Common Agency Lobbying over Coalitions and Policy

Wisdom of the Crowd? Information Aggregation and Electoral Incentives

Sincere Versus Sophisticated Voting When Legislators Vote Sequentially

Collective Decision with Costly Information: Theory and Experiments

Associated Students of Whitworth University

On Optimal Voting Rules under Homogeneous Preferences

THREATS TO SUE AND COST DIVISIBILITY UNDER ASYMMETRIC INFORMATION. Alon Klement. Discussion Paper No /2000

Sincere versus sophisticated voting when legislators vote sequentially

MIDTERM EXAM 1: Political Economy Winter 2017

A MODEL OF POLITICAL COMPETITION WITH CITIZEN-CANDIDATES. Martin J. Osborne and Al Slivinski. Abstract

Coalition Governments and Political Rents

Buying Supermajorities

Classical papers: Osborbe and Slivinski (1996) and Besley and Coate (1997)

ELECTIONS, GOVERNMENTS, AND PARLIAMENTS IN PROPORTIONAL REPRESENTATION SYSTEMS*

Reputation and Rhetoric in Elections

State of the World s Minorities and Indigenous Peoples 2012

Jelmer Kamstra a, Luuk Knippenberg a & Lau Schulpen a a Department of Cultural Anthropology and Development Studies,

Voluntary Voting: Costs and Benefits

SENIORITY AND INCUMBENCY IN LEGISLATURES

Sequential Voting with Externalities: Herding in Social Networks

The Provision of Public Goods Under Alternative. Electoral Incentives

COMPARATIVE VERSUS CONTRIBUTORY NEGLIGENCE: A COMPARISON OF THE LITIGATION EXPENDITURES

Organisation de Coopération et de Développement Économiques Organisation for Economic Co-operation and Development

Social Rankings in Human-Computer Committees

Approval Voting and Scoring Rules with Common Values

Should Straw Polls be Banned?

ONLINE APPENDIX: Why Do Voters Dismantle Checks and Balances? Extensions and Robustness

The Principle of Convergence in Wartime Negotiations. Branislav L. Slantchev Department of Political Science University of California, San Diego

Factions in Nondemocracies: Theory and Evidence from the Chinese Communist Party

Rhetoric in Legislative Bargaining with Asymmetric Information 1

Policy Reputation and Political Accountability

Anti-Poverty Election 2011 Poverty as an Election Tool Kit Table of Contents

Candidate Citizen Models

14.770: Introduction to Political Economy Lecture 11: Economic Policy under Representative Democracy

POLITICAL EQUILIBRIUM SOCIAL SECURITY WITH MIGRATION

CONTEXT ANALYSIS AND HUMANITARIAN RESPONSE

1 Electoral Competition under Certainty

Handcuffs for the Grabbing Hand? Media Capture and Government Accountability by Timothy Besley and Andrea Prat (2006)

Preferential votes and minority representation in open list proportional representation systems

RESEARCHING WOMEN S MOVEMENTS: AN INTRODUCTION TO FEMCIT AND SISTERHOOD AND AFTER

ON THE ORIGIN OF STATES: STATIONARY BANDITS AND TAXATION IN EASTERN CONGO

DISCUSSION PAPERS Department of Economics University of Copenhagen

In bureaucratic organizations, conflict over policy goals creates incentive problems

Corruption and Foreign Aid Nexus in the African Continent: An Empirical Analysis for Nigeria

ON IGNORANT VOTERS AND BUSY POLITICIANS

The Possibility of EU Lifting Arms Embargo on China. in the Context of the Eurozone Debt Crisis

Bureaucratic Corruption, Democracy and Judicial Independence

Economics Discussion Paper Series EDP-1502

HOTELLING-DOWNS MODEL OF ELECTORAL COMPETITION AND THE OPTION TO QUIT

TREATY FORMATION AND STRATEGIC CONSTELLATIONS

Ideology and Competence in Alternative Electoral Systems.

David Rosenblatt** Macroeconomic Policy, Credibility and Politics is meant to serve

The Swing Voter's Curse *

Good Politicians' Distorted Incentives

Supporting Information Political Quid Pro Quo Agreements: An Experimental Study

Law enforcement and false arrests with endogenously (in)competent officers

Helping Friends or Influencing Foes: Electoral and Policy Effects of Campaign Finance Contributions

Skilled Worker Migration and Trade: Inequality and Welfare

THE EFFECT OF OFFER-OF-SETTLEMENT RULES ON THE TERMS OF SETTLEMENT

International Cooperation, Parties and. Ideology - Very preliminary and incomplete

Comparative Politics and Public Finance 1

Compulsory versus Voluntary Voting Mechanisms: An Experimental Study

POLITICAL ACCOUNTABILITY UNDER ALTERNATIVE INSTITUTIONAL REGIMES

Political Economy: The Role of a Profit- Maxamizing Government

Compulsory versus Voluntary Voting An Experimental Study

Voting and Electoral Competition

Electoral Uncertainty and the Stability of Coalition Governments

Limited arbitrage is necessary and sufficient for the existence of an equilibrium

Legal Change: Integrating Selective Litigation, Judicial Preferences, and Precedent

Social Identity, Electoral Institutions, and the Number of Candidates

Veto Players, Policy Change and Institutional Design. Tiberiu Dragu and Hannah K. Simpson New York University

Corruption and Political Competition

University of Toronto Department of Economics. Influential Opinion Leaders

Prof. Panu Poutvaara University of Munich and Ifo Institute for Economic Research

Transcription:

Journal of Public Economics 92 (2008) 2225 2239 Contents lists available at ScienceDirect Journal of Public Economics journal homeage: www.elsevier.com/locate/econbase The informational role of suermajorities Emeric Henry London Business School, Sussex Place, Regent's Park, London NW4SA, United Kingdom article info abstract Article history: Received 9 August 2007 Received in revised form 2 March 2008 Acceted 7 Aril 2008 Available online 2 Aril 2008 JEL classification: D72 D82 D83 We study a collective decision making environment where an agenda setter makes strategic roosals to rivately informed voters who vote strategically. We show that, consistent with emirical evidence, it can be otimal for the agenda setter to roose suermajorities. Due to an informational role that we unveil, otimal suermajorities can be less costly than minimum winning coalitions, even though more voters are awarded a ositive share. We also examine consequences in terms of quality of decision making. We show that the introduction of a strategic agenda setter can lead to socially subotimal decisions. 2008 Elsevier B.V. All rights reserved. Keywords: Private information Aggregation of information in elections Legislative bargaining Suermajorities Debates. Introduction Grou decision making environments often share two imortant characteristics. First, the roosals submitted to a vote can be shaed strategically by an agenda setter. Second, voters often hold rivate information about the uncertain benefits of the roosals. Consider for instance a legislature deciding on the construction of major infrastructures such as a network of highways. The agenda setter rooses the recise location of the roads, in other words how the benefits are to be shared between legislators. The legislators vote based on rivate information they obtained, either from their constituents or from exerts they consulted, on the benefits and costs of the roject. Casual and emirical evidence suggests that in such legislative bargaining environments the roosed coalitions often involve more legislators than the simle majority needed for aroval. In the resent aer we show that the two characteristics reviously identified, the existence of a strategic agenda setter and rivately informed voters, can exlain the emergence of these larger coalitions. The agenda setter exloits the informational role of suermajorities. We unveil this mechanism in a theoretical model of legislative bargaining with rivately informed voters. The environment is one where an agenda setter submits a roosal that secifies how to share the benefits of a roject with uncertain returns. The legislators, who vote simultaneously, first obtain rivate signals about the roject's returns. Legislators vote strategically and thus consider only the case where their vote is ivotal. Our main result shows that, under conditions that we derive, the agenda setter rooses suermajorities. We define a suermajority roosal as one that attributes a strictly ositive share of the benefits to strictly more legislators than the number of votes in favor required for aroval. This result rests on the role of suermajorities as tools to aggregate information. The intuition Tel.: +44 20 7000 8428; fax: +44 20 7000 700. E-mail address: ehenry@london.edu. In an emirical analysis of roosal ower in the allocation of Congressionally earmarked transortation rojects, Knight (2005) shows that suermajorities are often the observed outcome. 0047-2727/$ see front matter 2008 Elsevier B.V. All rights reserved. doi:0.06/j.jubeco.2008.04.003

2226 E. Henry / Journal of Public Economics 92 (2008) 2225 2239 is that otimal suermajorities include some legislators voting informatively. All legislators, can thus obtain some information about other legislators' signals from considering the case where their vote is ivotal. If this information makes them confident that the returns of the roject are high, they need a smaller share of the benefits to vote in favor of the roosal. 2 Even though more legislators are included in the coalition, the overall cost can thus be decreased. However, such roosals also decrease the robability of accetance. We derive a condition such that the first effect dominates and thus rovide an exlanation for the emergence of suermajorities, based on strategic agenda setting and information aggregation. Our second result relates to the quality of decision making. We find that the introduction of a strategic agenda setter will sometimes lead to socially subotimal decision. We show that suermajorities can lead to mistaken rejections whereas minimum winning coalitions, where no information is aggregated, can lead to mistaken accetances. The conclusions of the literature on strategic voting, that redict that the socially otimal decision will be taken with robability one in sufficiently large legislatures, are therefore altered by the introduction of strategic agenda setting. In the last section we examine how a debate hase rior to the vote affects the roosals made by the agenda setter and changes the final outcome. A natural conjecture is that information will be revealed during the debate by the different legislators. We first show that roosals granting different strictly ositive shares to different grous of legislators cannot lead to full information revelation during the debate. More secifically, one grou at the most will be able to truthfully reveal their information. Second, we show that it can be otimal for the agenda setter to make such roosals, creating conflicts of interest, so as to limit the amount of information shared. We resent the informational role of suermajorities in the context of a legislature. There are numerous other situations where a rooser can strategically distribute benefits to rivately informed voters. A otential buyer of a firm can design tender offers that secify different rices for different shares. Shareholders often have rivate information about the otential benefits of the takeover. A firm in bankrutcy negotiations can grant different amounts to shareholders and creditors. One of the grous can thus be induced to vote informatively. Offers made by a firm to a union can treat different members differently. In all these alications it can be beneficial for the rooser to strategically use information aggregation, as emhasized in our model. The contribution of this aer can be viewed in different ways. The first is to introduce rivate information in a legislative bargaining context and in vote-buying models. 3 This leads us to rovide an informational justification for the emergence of suermajorities. The second contribution is to introduce strategic agenda setting in the literature on information aggregation in elections. We find that strategic agenda setting can lead to socially subotimal decisions even when information is aggregated. 4 We discuss the related literature, and in articular alternative exlanations for the emergence of suermajorities (Groseclose and Snyder, 996; Baron, 2006) and a related aer (Bond and Eraslan, 2007), later in the aer after having described our main results. Our aer is organized as follows. In Section 2 we describe the model and institutional environment. In Section 3 we resent an examle that introduces the main mechanisms. In Section 4 we exose our main result on suermajorities. In Section 5 we examine the introduction of a debate rior to the vote before discussing the related literature in the last section. Finally in Section 7 we discuss how these results could be tested emirically. 2. The model We study a legislature comosed of one agenda setter and N legislators. 5 The agenda setter submits a roosal which secifies how to slit the benefits from a roject between the different legislators. Secifically, the roosal is of the form (b,, b N ), where b i is the share of benefits allocated to legislator i. The agenda setter will kee the remaining share Σ N i =b i. The legislators cast their vote simultaneously and we suose, without loss of generality, that the agenda setter does not vote. If more than M legislators vote in favor of the roosal, the roject is undertaken and the benefits are distributed as secified by the roosal. If strictly less than M legislators vote in favor, the roject is abandoned and all layers obtain zero utility. Note that M, the majority needed for aroval, is a fixed characteristic of the legislature. We assume MbN, as the case of unanimity rule is of no interest in the resent study where we want to exlain the emergence of suermajorities. The roject has uncertain returns that can be either high s H or low s L (with s L b s H ). The agenda setter and the legislators initially share the same rior belief π that the state is high. Before voting, each legislator i,, N receives a rivate signal σ i {0,}. The signals are conditionally indeendent and satisfy P[σ i = s H ]=P[σ i =0 s L ]=, where N 2 measures the quality of the information. The roject also has a total cost c that will be incurred only if the roject is undertaken. We suose without loss of generality that the cost is equally divided between all legislators. The individual cost is therefore c N. The agenda setter and the legislators are risk neutral. The exected utility of legislator i faced with the roosal (b,, b N )is given by: b i ½P½ass \ s H Šs H þ P½ass \ s L Šs L Š c N, where ass refers to the event where the roosal is acceted. Legislators vote strategically and, when voting, consider only the case when their vote is ivotal. Secifically they will comare the exected utility of voting in favor if their vote is ivotal (event noted iυ) b i ½Ps ½ H jiυšs H þ Ps ½ L jiυšs L Š c N to zero (utility from voting against the roosal when your vote is ivotal). The agenda setter's utility is given by ½P½ass \ s H Šs H þ P½ass \ s L Šs L Šð P N b iþ. She will maximize her exected utility by choosing the shares (b,, b N ) aroriately, taking into account the voting behavior of the legislators. 2 We will show how the roortion of legislators voting informatively needs to be otimally adjusted to make legislators confident that the state is high. 3 We show in Section 6 that our model can be reexressed as a vote buying model. 4 This is in contrast with the literature on information aggregation in elections (Feddersen and Pesendorfer, 996, 997) that we discuss later on in the aer. 5 We refer throughout the main text to the grou of decision makers as a legislature, even though the analysis can be alied to other grous such as shareholders.

E. Henry / Journal of Public Economics 92 (2008) 2225 2239 2227 To summarize, the timing of the game is the following: () the agenda setter first makes a roosal (2) the legislators receive rivate signals (3) the legislators vote simultaneously on the roosal (4) the outcome of the vote is determined and if the roosal is acceted, the roject is undertaken and the benefits are slit accordingly. 3. A simle examle The following simle examle is useful to introduce some of the ideas of this aer. Suose that three neighbors are deciding whether to rehabilitate a wasteland situated between their resective roerties. The rules of the local community aoint an outside member as the agenda setter who rooses how to slit this common land if the rehabilitation roject is adoted and kees all the remaining share for herself. The rules also require two votes in favor to accet the roosal. The value of this wasteland after rehabilitation is unknown: one in the good state and zero otherwise, i.e. s H = and s L =0. All neighbors share a rior belief of one half that the state is high ¼ 2 and receive a rivate signal of recision ¼ 3 4. All three neighbors incur a cost of 0. if the roject is undertaken. We suose for simlicity that the agenda setter knows for sure that the state is high before making the roosal. The agenda setter can otentially make a large number of offers but we concentrate on two of them to convey the main insight. Offer rooses a minimum winning coalition: one neighbor receives a share of zero and the other two receive the minimal share such that they vote in favor regardless of their signal. 6 Offer 2 rooses a suermajority: all three neighbors are offered the minimal share such that they vote informatively. 7 We examine these offers searately. Offer is acceted for sure: the ositive shares offered are such that the two legislators who receive them vote in favor regardless of their message. We now determine the cost of the roosal. The shares offered are such that the neighbor is indifferent between voting in favor or against if he gets a signal of zero. When voting he considers only the case where his vote is ivotal, which for offer does not rovide any additional information since the other neighbors vote a certain way regardless of their signals. The neighbor will thus only consider his own signal when determining his voting behavior. After he receives a bad signal, his osterior robability that the state is high is 4. To be indifferent between voting in favor or against after a bad signal, he needs to be offered a share b i such that b i 4 ¼ c N (i.e. b i =0.4). The total cost of the roosal is then 0.8 and the utility of the agenda setter is 0.8=0.2. 8 On the contrary, offer 2 might be rejected. The neighbors in this case obtain some information from considering the ivotal case: one neighbor received a signal of one and voted in favor and the other received a signal of zero and voted against. After they. To be indifferent between voting in themselves receive a signal of one, their osterior robability that the state is high is therefore 3 4 3 favor or against after a good signal, they need to be offered a share b i such that b i 4 ¼ c N (i.e. b i ¼ 4 30 ). The total cost of the roosal is 0.4, which is smaller than in the case of offer even though more neighbors are offered ositive shares. However, the robability with which the roosal is acceted also decreases (it is now ( ) 3 =0.98). 9 The overall utility of the agenda setter is 0.59, which is greater than in the case of offer. We learned from this simle examle that offering ositive shares to more neighbors might decrease the overall cost of the roosal. Indeed, some neighbors can then be induced to vote informatively (all three neighbors in the case of offer 2). When voting, they can thus derive information about the other neighbor signals when they consider the case where their vote is ivotal and if this information raises their osterior belief that the state is high, they require a smaller share of benefits to vote in favor. Overall this reduces the cost of the roosal. However, given that some neighbors vote informatively, this roosal also has a lower robability of accetance. In this simle examle, the first ositive effect on costs dominates. We now examine, in the general model, under what conditions roosing suermajorities () decreases the overall cost of the roosal (2) increases the exected utility of the agenda setter. 0 4. Aggregation of information and suermajorities 4.. Proosals We start by describing the set of roosals the agenda setter makes in equilibrium. In general, she is not restricted to the two offers we comared in the revious examle. However, the following lemma indicates that individual shares offered will only be of three tyes, recisely those that we described in the examle. Lemma. In equilibrium, a legislator will be offered either: ) A zero share. 2) A share b j such that the legislator is indifferent between voting in favor or against when he gets a signal zero. 3) A share b k (b k b b j ) such that the legislator is indifferent between voting in favor or against when he gets a signal one. Lemma indicates that there are at most three tyes of legislators in equilibrium: those who are offered a zero share and always vote against the roosal, those who are offered b j and always vote in favor (denoted by j) and those who are offered b k and vote 6 In other words the share such that the neighbor is indifferent between voting in favor or against if he receives a signal of zero. We suose that they break the indifference in favor of the roosal. 7 In other words the share such that they are indifferent between voting in favor or against if they receive a signal of one. 8 We use the fact that the agenda setter knows for sure that the state is high. 9 This assumes as we did at the beginning of this section that the agenda setter knows that the state is high. 0 In other words, when the ositive effect on the cost of the roosal will dominate the negative effect on the robability of accetance.

2228 E. Henry / Journal of Public Economics 92 (2008) 2225 2239 informatively (denoted by k). Voting informatively means that they vote in favor if and only if they get a signal of one. The intuition of this result rests on the fact that any other offer leads to the same voting behavior as one of those three offers, but is more costly for the agenda setter. Consider for instance, a legislator who is offered a share b (b k, b j ). The share b is such that he votes in favor if he gets a signal of one but is not large enough to induce him to vote in favor if his signal is zero. His voting behavior is identical to that of tye b k, but he obtains a higher share of the rofits if the roosal is acceted. The agenda setter never in cludes such a legislator in her coalition. A consequence of Lemma is that, to maximize her exected benefits, the agenda setter can restrict herself to choosing the number of legislators who vote non-informatively (denoted by J) and the number of legislators who vote informatively (denoted by K). The following lemma establishes how the values of K and J affect the individual shares offered in equilibrium. Lemma 2. Given a choice of K and J, the roosal made in equilibrium is characterized by the shares: Share offered to one of the J legislators voting non-informatively: " b j ¼ c where N j ¼ = þ # Kþ2J 2Mþ : s H j þ s L j Share offered to one of the K legislators voting informatively: " b k ¼ c N s H k þ s L ð k Þ where k ¼ = þ # Kþ2J 2M : Proof. See Aendix A. The share b j,bydefinition, is such that the legislator is indifferent between voting in favor or against when he receives a signal of zero. The robability j is his osterior belief that the state is high when he receives a signal of zero and considers the case where his vote is ivotal. Therefore, the share b j is such that the exected benefits from the roject given beliefs j exactly equal the costs c N. The intuition for the share b k is identical. It is imortant to notice that, if K+2J is significantly different from 2M, the share the agenda setter needs to offer to a legislator voting informatively (b k ) is very close to the one she needs to offer a legislator who votes in favor regardless of his message (b j ). To understand why the comarison between K+2J and 2M is relevant, consider the situation where K+2J=2M in the secial case where all voters in the coalition vote informatively (i.e. J=0). 2 A legislator who considers the event where his vote is ivotal, knows that M legislatorsreceived a signal of one and voted in favor and the K M remaining legislators who were offered a ositive share, received a signal of zero and voted against. If K=2M, the number of signals in favor and against are equal, and the fact that a legislator's vote is ivotal does not affect his osterior belief. In this case, the only information he uses is his own signal and the difference between shares b j and b k is then large. 3 On the contrary, when K+2J is significantly different from 2M, most of the information legislators take into account does not come from their own signal but from the information aggregated and the shares b k and b j are very close. The fact that in general the shares offered to legislators voting informatively and the shares offered to those voting non-informatively are close will be an imortant element to exlain why suermajorities can be the cheaest otion for the agenda setter. 4.2. Aggregation of information in large legislatures We resent in this section the main result of our aer which shows that, under a condition that we derive, the agenda setter rooses a suermajority. This result is obtained in large legislatures, in other words when the size of the legislature N tends to infinity. In this context it is useful to reexress the main variables as a roortion of the legislature size N: k ¼ K N ; j ¼ J N and m ¼ M N.4 We also introduce the notation R ¼ ½ Š= ðs H þ s L ð ÞÞ= s H þ strictly smaller than one, will be useful in the main result that follows. þ s L þ Þ. This arameter R, which is Proosition. In large legislatures, if the total cost of the roject is relatively high comared to the benefits in the low state, mc [Rs L,s H ], the agenda setter rooses suermajorities in equilibrium. Proof. See Aendix A. Proosition gives a sufficient condition that guarantees that the agenda setter refers to roose a suermajority rather than a minimal coalition. We first oint out that if mcns H, the agenda setter cannot make a roosal that is acceted and leaves her with ositive utility (even in the best case scenario, where the state is known to be high, the costs cannot be covered by a simle We suose that if they are indifferent, they vote in favor of the roosal. 2 In other words the case where J=0 and K=2M. 3 A similar argument can be made when J N0: the votes in favor are then M J, the votes against K M+J and if K+2J =2M, these two numbers are equal. 4 Where m is not constrained to be equal to /2 but is different from by assumtion.

E. Henry / Journal of Public Economics 92 (2008) 2225 2239 2229 majority). We concentrate on the result relative to the lower bound: mc Rs L. The intuition follows closely that of the examle of Section 3. Well designed suermajorities decrease the total cost of the roosal but will also decrease the robability of accetance. The trade-off between these two effects leads to the condition mc Rs L given in Proosition. We now elaborate on the details of this intuition. Consider a suermajority roosal such that k+j=m. In a large legislature, the roortion of legislators voting in favor of the roosal among those voting informatively (tye k)isk if the state is high and ( )k if the state is low. Given that N 2,wehave mn( )k+j. The conditions k+j=mn( )k+j imly that the roosal is acceted if and only if the state is high. When a legislator determines his voting behavior and considers the case when his vote is ivotal, he will aggregate information and know for sure that the state is high and require a smaller share of the benefits to vote in favor of the roosal. Furthermore, following the intuition of Lemma 2, legislators voting informatively and those voting non-informatively will demand very similar shares. 5 The overall cost of the roosal will be low. If a minimum winning coalition is roosed, on the one hand it is acceted regardless of the state, but on the other hand, no information is aggregated and each legislator needs to be at least comensated for his exected cost after obtaining a signal zero. Both the cost of the roosal and the robability of accetance are higher. The balance between these two effects is reflected in the condition mc Rs L. If the total cost of buying a minimum coalition (which is aroximately mc 6 ) is high, decreasing the cost of the roosal becomes a riority and suermajorities become attractive. On the contrary, if the cost mc is low, guaranteeing accetance, becomes more imortant. The tye of roosals made in equilibrium will also have consequences in terms of the quality of the decision making. The following roosition addresses this question. Proosition 2. In large legislatures, if the total cost of the roject is relatively high comared to the benefits in the low state (mc [Rs L,s H ]), the roosal made in equilibrium is acceted if and only if the state is high. Furthermore if s L Nc, the equilibrium roosal leads to mistaken rejections. Proof. See Aendix A. The result of Proosition 2 follows closely that of Proosition. Under condition mc [Rs L,s H ], suermajorities are roosed in equilibrium and the roject is undertaken if and only if the state is high. The second art of the roosal highlights the fact that this will not always lead to socially otimal decisions. Consider the case where Rs L bmc (a suermajority is roosed) and s L Nc. If the state is low, the roosal is rejected when it should have been otimally acceted. Therefore, one imortant conclusion of this work is that, contrary to the conclusions of the literature on strategic voting, the socially otimal decision will not be taken with robability one when the agenda is set strategically. If the otimal choice of the agenda setter is a suermajority, we might observe mistaken rejections. Notice also that if the otimal choice is a minimal winning coalition, we might witness mistaken accetance. In the following result, we examine the effect of the quality of the information on roosals made by the agenda setter. Corollary. As the quality of the information held by the legislator increases: (a) the likelihood that the agenda setter rooses a suermajority increases. (b) if a suermajority is roosed, the size of the coalition j+k decreases. Proof. See Aendix A. The intuition for result (a) is the following. When the agenda setter rooses a minimum winning coalition, she has to offer legislators a share such that they are indifferent between voting for or against the roosal when they get signal zero. Therefore, if the quality of the signal is high ( high), the legislators demand a higher share to vote in favor of the roosal. On the contrary, the cost of otimal suermajorities decreases when the quality increases. However, result (b) states that in cases where the agenda setter does include more legislators than a simle minimum winning coalition, the size of the suermajority decreases with the quality of the signals. The intuition is that the agenda setter just needs enough legislators voting informatively so that others are confident that the state is high in the ivotal case. If the quality of the individual signals is high, fewer legislators are needed to aggregate the same amount of information. Therefore, as the quality of the information held by the legislators increases, fewer of them are included in the roosed coalition. If one of the concerns of the designer is to have benefits equally distributed among the different legislators and through them, their constituents, Corollary indicates that information of better quality is not necessarily beneficial. 4.3. Small legislature All the results of the revious sections were derived for large legislatures. For small legislatures, we cannot obtain a closed form solution to describe the otimal roosal. 7 However, we reort the results of some simulations. These simulations are erformed in the secial case where s L =0, s H = and m=0.5. According to Proosition, given that s L =0, in large legislatures suermajorities will always be roosed. Table in Aendix A shows that this is not necessarily the case in small legislatures for low values of 5 If k+j=m, given that N0.5, this means that K+2J is significantly different from 2M andthat b k and b j will be very similar. 6! The exact value of the total cost in the case of a minimum coalition is larger than mc: mc= s H 7 It is not ossible to find a closed form solution for the roosal that maximizes the utility of the agenda setter. In large legislatures we are able to use uniform convergence to first take the limit and then determine the maximum which greatly simlifies our roblem. Such a technique is not feasible in finite legislatures. þ þ sl þ

2230 E. Henry / Journal of Public Economics 92 (2008) 2225 2239 (Table in Aendix A, =0.6). For that value of, when the legislature is small, minimum winning coalitions are referable. However, when the legislature size N becomes larger, consistent with the results of Proosition, we observe that suermajorities are always referred. The second table shows that when is larger (Table 2 in Aendix A, =0.85), suermajorities are the otimal choice regardless of the size of the legislature. The comarison between Tables and 2 in Aendix A also confirms Corollary : once a suermajority is roosed, if the quality increases, the size of the coalition decreases. 8 5. How debates affect roosals The results of the revious sections rely on the fact that the agenda setter strategically uses information aggregation. It is natural to ask whether communication rior to the vote will affect the agenda setter's incentives and thus roosals made in equilibrium. In this section, we add a hase to the game reviously considered. Prior to the vote, legislators simultaneously exchange nonverifiable ublic messages m i {0,}. To be more recise, we consider the following timing: () the agenda setter makes a roosal (2) legislators receive rivate signals (3) legislators simultaneously send ublic messages (4) legislators vote simultaneously on the roosal (5) the outcome of the vote is determined and the benefits are distributed. The first oint we want to make is that there will always exist an equilibrium where no information is revealed truthfully. In that case the results of the revious sections are unaffected. We will study in this section the most informative equilibrium. 5.. Back to the examle Let us return to the examle of Section 3 to illustrate these questions. We concentrate on roosals where one neighbor is excluded from the coalition (he is offered a zero share). With the added debate hase more individual equilibrium offers can be made. In an equilibrium where some information is truthfully revealed, the offers can be conditioned on the number of ositive signals revealed. In equilibrium, a neighbor included in the coalition could be offered shares such that: He is indifferent between voting for or against at (0, 0) He is indifferent between voting for or against at (0, ) He is indifferent between voting for or against at (, 0) He is indifferent between voting for or against at (, ). The notation (u,υ) used is such that: u is the neighbor's own signal, υ is the message sent by the other neighbor during the debate. We denote b (u,υ) the share that leaves the neighbor indifferent between voting in favor or against the roosal when the information is (u,υ). Consider the case where one neighbor is offered b (0,) and the other b (,).Wefind that there cannot exist an equilibrium where both reort their signals truthfully. Suose tye b (,) is reorting truthfully in the debate and consider the decision tye b (0,) faces. He only has to consider the case where his message is ivotal, in other words if he sends message one, the roosal asses and if he sends message zero, it is defeated. In such a case, tye b (0,) knows that the other neighbor (tye b (,) ) must have obtained signal one (this tye only votes in favor if both his signal and the message received are one). This is sufficient information for tye b (0,) to want the roosal to ass regardless of his message. He will have an incentive to always send a mes sage of one. The same logic alies if b (0,) is reorting truthfully and tye b (,) obtains signal one. If they are offered different amounts, truthful reorting by both neighbors cannot occur in equilibrium. 5.2. Do all legislators reveal their information in debates? Can we generalize the result of this simle examle? We first need to determine the individual offers that can be made in equilibrium. The introduction of a debate increases the number of otential offers comared to those described in Lemma. In an equilibrium where information is truthfully revealed, the offers will deend on the number of signals revealed during the debate and will be different for legislators revealing truthfully and for the others. We denote T as the number of legislators revealing truthfully in equilibrium. The individual equilibrium offers are given by the following lemma. Lemma 3. In equilibrium, a legislator will be offered either: ) A zero share. 2) If he reveals truthfully, a share b k r such that he is indifferent between voting in favor or against if k signals of one were revealed during the debate, including otentially his own (k (0,, T)). 3) If he does not reveal truthfully, a share b k h such that he is indifferent between voting for or against if k signals of one were revealed truthfully and he obtained a signal of zero or if k signals of one were revealed truthfully and he obtained a signal of one (k (0,, T+)). As in the roof of Lemma, all other individual offer will lead to the same outcome of the vote but will be more costly and therefore subotimal for the agenda setter. We now study the communication strategy during the debate. The first thing to note is that legislators who are offered no share of the benefits cannot credibly reveal any information during the debate as they always 8 For instance for N=200, the coalition is of size 8 for =0.6 and size 09 for =0.85.

E. Henry / Journal of Public Economics 92 (2008) 2225 2239 223 want roosals to be defeated indeendently of their signal. It is also trivially true that when all legislators in the roosed coalition are offered the same share, an equilibrium where they truthfully reveal their information during the debate hase will always exist. 9 However, the following result confirms the simle examle: in equilibrium, truthful revelation will not always occur. Proosition 3. In the most informative equilibrium, if different grous of legislators are offered different amounts, only one grou will truthfully reveal their signal in equilibrium. Proof. See Aendix A. Proosition 3 indicates that two grous of legislators who are offered different amounts in equilibrium cannot both reveal their information truthfully. The intuition for this result has two arts. First, in equilibrium according to Lemma 3, if two grous are offered different amounts and truthfully reveal their information, legislators in one grou will need at least one extra ositive signal revealed during the debate than the other grou to vote in favor of the roosal. Second, the legislators when they decide whether to reort truthfully or not, consider only the case where their message is ivotal for the final vote. If the grou that needs more ositive signals is truthfully revealing, this means for a legislator of the other grou that, even without his message, the information is good enough for him to want to ass the roosal. He therefore has an incentive to always reort a signal of one. Proosition 3 therefore indicates that at most one grou of legislators will truthfully reveal their information during the debate. The following roosition characterizes this grou. We call the legislator who receives the Mth highest individual share, the ivotal legislator, where M is the number of votes in favor required to ass the roosal. Lemma 4. In equilibrium, if b r k is the offer made to legislators who reveal their signal truthfully, the ivotal legislator can only receive one of three offers: b r k,b h h h k or b k+ (with b k+ bb r k bb h k ). Proof. See Aendix A. Lemma 4 states that the incentives of the ivotal legislator and those of a legislator revealing truthfully his signal need to be closely aligned in equilibrium. 20 Consider the decision of a legislator to reort or not his signal. Suose that the ivotal legislator needs many more ositive signals than he does to vote in favor of the roosal. The legislator, to determine his communication strategy, examines the case where his message is ivotal, in other words changes the vote of the ivotal legislator. Because this ivotal legislator needs many more ositive signals to vote in favor, the information obtained from the ivotal case is sufficient to want the roosal to ass irresective of his signal. Such a legislator will not reort truthfully. The intuition is identical if the ivotal legislator needs less ositive evidence. The only legislators who can reort truthfully are therefore those who need a similar number of ositive signals as the ivotal legislator to vote in favor of the roosal. 5.3. Preventing information sharing in debates We have studied in the revious section the behavior of legislators in the deliberation hase. In this section we use these results to examine the agenda setter's otimal behavior and determine what roosals she will make in equilibrium? We show that it can be otimal for her to limit the amount of information shared during the debate by designing roosals where different grous have diverging interests. We first describe the different individual equilibrium roosals in the following lemma. Lemma 5. When a debate occurs rior to the vote, in equilibrium the agenda setter makes only two tyes of roosals: () Tye I: all legislators in the coalition 2 receive the same share b l such that they are indifferent between voting for or against if l ositive signals were revealed during the debate. Furthermore, they all reveal their information truthfully in the debate. (2) Tye II: involves two grou of legislators receiving different strictly ositive amounts in equilibrium. Tye b r k reveals truthfully. The other tye is either b h k or b h k+. Proof. See Aendix A. The revious lemma indicates that the agenda setter will otimally choose among a limited set of roosals. The first tye is one where all the information held by members of the coalition is revealed during the debate. The second tye of roosal involves two grous: one grou of legislators who truthfully reveal their information during the debate and the other grou who cannot communicate information. The roosals in that category are designed to create a conflict of interest between legislators and thus revent full information sharing. However, Lemma 5 leaves the question oen: can it be otimal for the agenda setter to make a roosal of tye II creating a conflict of interest between the different legislators? The following roosition addresses this question in large legislatures. 9 Indeed they have exactly aligned references and therefore in the case where their message is ivotal will always want to reveal it to avoid deceiving the other identical legislators. 20 Suose the legislators who reveal their signal truthfully need k signals of one to vote in favor. The ivotal legislator will either be the legislator who reveals truthfully or a legislator who does not reveal and needs either k or k+ signals of including otentially his own to vote in favor. 2 That is all legislators receiving a strictly ositive share.

2232 E. Henry / Journal of Public Economics 92 (2008) 2225 2239 Proosition 4. In large legislatures, it can be otimal for the decision maker to choose a roosal of tye II where only a finite amount of information is shared during the debate. Proof. See Aendix A. We rove this result by resenting an examle where, for a large legislature, a roosal of tye II rovides a higher exected utility than any roosal of tye I. In the case of large legislatures, all legislators included in the coalition reveal truthfully their information and the state is erfectly known after the debate. 22 There are therefore only two roosals of tye I. The first rooses to M legislators a share such that they are indifferent between voting for or against if the state is known to be high: therefore such a roosal has a low cost, 23 but it also has a low robability of accetance. We name this roosal high for sure. The other offer of tye I, that we name low for sure, comensates legislators when they know the state is low for sure, is always acceted but at a much higher cost. 24 Proosals of tye II in effect constitute intermediate solutions: they are acceted less often than the low for sure roosal but need to abandon a smaller share of the benefits to the legislators. They also are more costly than the high for sure roosal but are acceted more often. The roof of Proosition 4 is based on one of several secific examles where a roosal of tye II, where only a few signals are revealed during the debate, dominates all roosals of tye I. It is difficult to rovide a more general statement as there is no systematic way to comare the discrete utilities of the infinite number of roosals of tye II. 25 However, this initial result already shows that it can be otimal for the agenda setter to revent full information sharing during the debate. She can achieve this by making roosals that create conflicts of interests. 6. Related literature Our aer is linked to two main strands of the literature and makes contributions to both. First, it can be seen as introducing rivate information in the vote-buying literature. Reviewing this literature allows us to discuss two alternative exlanations for the emergence of suermajorities based on cometition between two lobbyists. Second, it can be seen as introducing strategic agenda setting in the literature on information aggregation. We show that, contrary to the results in that literature, strategic agenda setting will lead to mistaken decisions, even when information is aggregated. As Piketty (999) indicates in his survey aer, before the information aggregation aroach was introduced (Austen-Smith and Banks, 996; Feddersen and Pesendorfer, 996, 997) most of the ublic choice literature viewed olitics as a game where selfish rational actors seek to divide the ie roduced by economics. We can view our aer as combining these two aroaches. 6.. Vote-buying literature The main contribution of our aer is to give an exlanation for the observed occurrence of suermajorities, based on strategic agenda setting and information aggregation. Two main alternative exlanations exist in the literature on vote buying (Groseclose and Snyder, 996 and Baron, 2006) and are based on cometition between several lobbyists. Notice that our model can be relabeled as a vote-buying game with no agenda setter and a single lobbyist. The same tye of arguments as in our setu imly that it can be otimal for the single lobbyist to buy a suermajority to decrease the amount sent on vote buying. 26 Groseclose and Snyder (996) resent an interesting mechanism in a model with two cometing vote buyers, who have oosed interests and make sequential offers to legislators. They show that buying a minimum winning coalition might not be the cheaest solution for the first lobbyist. Indeed, if she makes such an offer, she will need to send large amounts to defend every single vote in her coalition, under the threat that the cometing lobbyist only needs to buy back one vote to guarantee a favorable outcome. 27 Several authors (Baron, 2006; Dekel et al., 2004) have ointed out that the existence of a final offer in the model of Groseclose and Snyder (996), is crucial for the result on suermajorities as it grants a substantial advantage to the second lobbyist. Dekel et al. (2004), in a model with two cometing lobbyists, who make sequential offers with a minimum increment and no final round, find that suermajorities will not be the observed outcome, as long as the winning lobbyist did not have a suermajority in his favor before the game started. Baron (2006) not only relaxes the assumtion of a final offer but also introduces several roles for the agenda setter: bargaining with the lobbyists, setting the agenda and voting on the roosal. In the model, at each round one legislator is randomly selected to set the agenda. Lobbyists not only buy votes but also send resources to influence the agenda setting activity. If the stakes of the 22 Due to the law of large numbers. 23 The legislators know the state is high for sure and therefore need a smaller share or vote in favor. 24 Note that for the legislator it is much more costly than without a debate because legislators will share information and will therefore know that the state is low for sure. 25 Tye II roosals, even in large legislatures can contain a finite number of signals truthfully revealed in equilibrium. The agenda's setter exected utility from making a Tye II roosal will contain comlex discrete robabilities. There does not seem to be a systematic way to obtain a closed form solution for the maximum. 26 The vote buyer can ay a high amount for a vote in favor to buy the vote for sure or ay an intermediate amount to induce the legislator to vote informatively as the agenda setter did in our model. 27 The intuition of their model is the following: suose that a first vote buyer has bought a minimum winning coalition, then the other vote buyer needs to win over only one member of that coalition. It therefore becomes very exensive for the first lobbyist to defend every single vote. If, on the other hand, she increases her coalition by one member, she might, even if she sends less er legislator, make it more exensive for the second mover to win over a majority that would now require him to buy two votes.

E. Henry / Journal of Public Economics 92 (2008) 2225 2239 2233 lobbyists are high or if legislators are imatient, suermajorities will be bought as they increase the robability that the randomly selected agenda setter will submit a favorable roosal to a vote. We rovide an alternative exlanation based on a comletely different mechanism involving rivate information and strategic agenda setting. In terms of broad differences the informational role of suermajorities can exlain their emergence in the absence of cometition between different vote buyers. 28 Furthermore the mechanism is general and does not rely on the articular institutional details of legislative bargaining. We describe in Section 7 how these alternative theories could be emirically tested. 6.2. Literature on strategic voting The second ersective on the aer is that it introduces rivate information in a legislative bargaining context, similar to the model in the seminal work by Baron and Ferejohn (989). The introduction of rivate information in elections naturally ties our aer to the literature on information aggregation (Austen-Smith and Banks (996), Feddersen and Pesendorfer (996, 997), Duggan and Martinelli (200) and others). In these aers the agenda is set exogenously. We effectively introduce strategic agenda setting in these environments. We show that the introduction of strategic agenda setting has imortant consequences in terms of the quality of decision making. One of the messages of the literature on information aggregation is that in large legislatures, information will be efficiently aggregated and the socially otimal decision taken with robability one. For instance, Feddersen and Pesendorfer (997) show that even if the fraction of informed voters is arbitrarily small, the socially referred olicy wins with robability one with a large enough electorate. On the contrary, we show in Proosition 2, that the existence of a strategic agenda setter can lead to mistaken rejections if suermajorities are roosed or mistaken accetances if minimum winning coalitions are the otimal choice. Strategic agenda setting leads to otential mistakes. As was ointed out in the introduction, an indeendent work by Bond and Eraslan (2007), considers a related question. They also examine situations where the agenda is set endogenously by an agenda setter and voters hold rivate information. However, they focus on roosals where all legislators are treated equally (they are not interested in legislative bargaining situations) and consider a different set of questions. They reexamine the classical comarison between unanimity and majority rules. 29 Finally, we want to oint that our work is also linked to a aer on vote trading by Piketty (994). When voters do not hold information, vote trading enhances social welfare as voters with stronger references can voice them in the market for votes. However, Piketty shows that this result can be overturned when information is introduced. If there exists a roortion of uncertain voters who hold rivate information on the state of the world and if their signal is sufficiently imrecise, there exists an equilibrium where all uncertain voters sell their vote. In such circumstances voting does not aggregate any information. As is the case in our aer, the author combines two strands of the literature (vote-buying and information aggregation aroaches) and uncovers as we do in Proosition 2 deviations from the socially otimal outcome. 30 6.3. Literature on debates Finally we oint out the links with the literature on debates, relevant to our analysis in Section 5. There is a relatively large literature on debates (for instance Sector, 2000). A few recent aers have examined more secifically the imact of debates on the outcome of a vote in a game-theoretic framework. An imortant result was obtained by Gerardi and Yariv (2003): under general conditions, the set of sequential equilibria outcomes achievable by augmenting a voting game by a deliberation hase is constant in the voting rule m. The central observation leading to that result is that all individuals voting unanimously can be art of a sequential voting equilibrium. Therefore, individuals behave as if the final voting hase did not matter. In contrast, Austen-Smith and Feddersen (2002), examine equilibria where agents always condition their vote on being ivotal. They show that majority rule induces more information sharing than unanimity. Two other aers are articularly relevant to our study. Meirowitz (2007) studies a case where voters have otentially oosed references. In a model where the roortion of the different tyes of voters is not known with certainty, he finds that truthful equilibria exist only if the agents are confident enough that the other articiants have references similar to theirs. In a related aer, Meirowitz (2006) determines a necessary condition for an equilibrium with full revelation: either all articiants believe they have the majority oinion or no individual signal can change the outcome. The result emhasizes the fact that articiants who have minority interests generally have incentives to misreresent their information. The result we obtain in Lemma 4 follows a similar logic: only the legislators who have closely aligned references to those of the ivotal voter can reveal their information truthfully. 7. Emirical validation The theory we develo in this aer makes recise testable redictions regarding the size of coalitions and the emergence of suermajorities. We therefore believe it is imortant to outline how our results could be tested and to relate our work to the existing emirical literature. 28 The model can involve either a strategic agenda setter and no lobbyist or a single vote buyer. 29 Contrary to revious results, that found that unanimity just led to less information aggregation and therefore worse decisions, they find that with an endogenous agenda, it can become a Pareto dominant voting rule. The agenda setter is forced to make more attractive roosals as under unanimity, low offers will lead to mistaken rejections. 30 Note that our model is a secial case of a market for votes where votes can only be traded with the agenda setter who is essentially setting the rice through the roosal she makes.