Is Lawrence Still Good Law?

Similar documents
Patterson, Chapter 14. The Federal Judicial System Applying the Law. Chapter Quiz

CHAPTER 9. The Judiciary

The Federal Courts. Chapter 16

NEW YORK COUNTY LAWYERS ASSOCIATION


SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES

AP Gov Chapter 15 Outline

Chapter 8 - Judiciary. AP Government

The full speech, as prepared for delivery, is below:

1. Which Article of the Constitution created the federal judiciary?

The Courts. Chapter 15

The Federal Courts. Chapter 16

Unit V: Institutions The Federal Courts

Chapter 14 AP GOVERNMENT

Judiciary and Political Parties. Court Rulings on Parties. Presidential Nomination Rules. Presidential Nomination Rules

III. OBAMA & THE COURTS

7) For a case to be heard in the Supreme Court, a minimum of how many judges must vote to hear the case? A) none B) one C) nine D) five E) four

Court Hierarchy. Part One: The Court Structure. Federal Court Hierarchy 9/1/17. United States Supreme Court. United States Court of Appeals

The Judicial Branch INTRODUCTION TO THE FEDERAL COURTS

Citation: John Harrison, The Unitary Executive and the Scope of Executive Power, 126 Yale L.J. F. 374 ( )

Courts, Judges, and the Law

AGENCY/PHOTOGRAPHER. An Obama Supreme Court Versus a Romney High Court. Ian Millhiser September 2012

AP Government Chapter 15 Reading Guide: The Judiciary

Jurisdiction. Appointed by the President with the Advice and Consent of the Senate according to Article II, Section 2

Of Inkblots and Originalism: Historical Ambiguity and the Case of the Ninth Amendment

Understanding the U.S. Supreme Court

Warm Up: Review Activity Declare your Powers

The Federalist, No. 78

SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES

Unit 4C STUDY GUIDE. The Judiciary. Use the Constitution to answer questions #1-9. Unless noted, all questions are based on Article III.

Judicial Review of Unilateral Treaty Terminations

The Supreme Court The Judicial Branch

The United States Supreme Court

America s Federal Court System

Follow this and additional works at: Part of the Law Commons

The Six Basic Principles

The Federal Judiciary (HAA)

In 2008, the en banc Fifth Circuit granted mandamus relief in the

THE JUDICIAL BRANCH: THE FEDERAL COURTS

By: Mariana Gaxiola-Viss 1. Before the year 2002 corporations were free to sponsor any

AP US GOVERNMENT: CHAPER 7: POLITICAL PARTIES: ESSENTIAL TO DEMOCRACY

a. Exceptions: Australia, Canada, Germany, India, and a few others B. Debate is over how the Constitution should be interpreted

Congress Can Curb the Courts

Running head: SUPREME COURTS NOMINATION IN THE UNITED STATES 1. Supreme Courts Nomination in the United States Name Institution

2007 Annenberg Public Policy Center Judicial Survey Exact Question Wording, By Category

The Federal Courts. Warm-Up. Warm-Up. Chapter 16. The Weberian model views bureaucracies as. The Weberian model views bureaucracies as

SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES

Magruder s American Government

Chapter 14: The Judiciary Multiple Choice

The Judiciary AP Government Spring 2016

COMMENTS DISTRICT OF COLUMBIA V. HELLER: THE INDIVIDUAL RIGHT TO BEAR ARMS

The Judicial System (cont d)

INTRO TO POLI SCI 11/30/15

The Federalist Papers

Chapter 18 The Judicial Branch

Topic 7 The Judicial Branch. Section One The National Judiciary

DESIGNATION OF ACTING SOLICITOR OF LABOR MEMORANDUM OPINION FOR THE DEPUTY COUNSEL TO THE PRESIDENT

Friends of Democracy Corps and Greenberg Quinlan Rosner 1994=2010. Report on the Democracy Corps and Resurgent Republic bipartisan post election poll

June 27, 2008 JUSTICES, RULING 5-4, ENDORSE PERSONAL RIGHT TO OWN GUN

Democracy and Statutory Interpretation: New Empirical Work and Positive Theory ABA Administrative Law, Fall Conference 2013

Lesson Plan Title Here

Campaign Finance Law and the Constitutionality of the Millionaire s Amendment : An Analysis of Davis v. Federal Election Commission

THE SPECIAL COUNSEL IS AN INFERIOR OFFICER

10. The courts which regularly employ grand juries are a. district courts. b. courts of appeal. c. military tribunals. d. bankruptcy courts.

Explain the key arguments of the Federalists and the process by which the Constitution was finally ratified.

The House of Representatives shall be composed of Members chosen every second Year by the People of the several States.

Ch.9: The Judicial Branch

laws created by legislative bodies.

The Courts and The Judiciary Part III

TUSHNET-----Introduction THE IDEA OF A CONSTITUTIONAL ORDER

Campaigning in General Elections (HAA)

Judicial Recess Appointments: A Survey of the Arguments

INTRODUCTION THE NATURE OF THE JUDICIAL SYSTEM

Supreme Court of the United States

STUDENT GOVERNMENT ASSOCIATION OF THE JOHNS HOPKINS UNIVERSITY

Class Period THE US CONSTITUTION. 2. Compare Article I with Article II. Which article is longer and more detailed? WHY do you suppose it s longer?

Separation of Powers: History and Theory

SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES

RECENT DECISION I. FACTS

By Jane Lynch and Jared Wagner

Lilly v. Virginia Glimmers of Hope for the Confrontation Clause?

4) Once every decade, the Constitution requires that the population be counted. This is called the 4)

Supreme Court Declines to Overrule or Modify Basic, But Allows Rebuttal of "Price Impact" in Opposing Class Certification

Foreign Aid for Antitrust Litigants: Impact of the Intel Decision By Richard Liebeskind, Bryan Dunlap and William DeVinney

Network Derived Domain Maps of the United States Supreme Court:

THE NATURE OF THE JUDICIAL SYSTEM

Unit 4 Test Bank Congress

Flag Protection: A Brief History and Summary of Supreme Court Decisions and Proposed Constitutional Amendments

UNITED STATES AIR FORCE COURT OF CRIMINAL APPEALS

Global Macro Strategy: Special Election Report

BEST STAFF COMPETITION PIECE

American Government & Civics Final Exam Review Guide

PARTISAN GERRYMANDERING

Civil vs Criminal Cases

TOP TWO PRIMARY By Harry Kresky, openprimaries.org INTRODUCTION

THE MYTH OF THE CONSTITUTIONALLY REQUIRED UP OR DOWN VOTE The True History of Checks and Balances, Advice and Consent in the Senate

3 BRANCHES OF GOVERNMENT

HUMAN RIGHTS AND THE AMERICAN CONSTITUTION

From: John Halpin, Center for American Progress Karl Agne, GBA Strategies

A Proposal to Reform the Process for Confirming Justices of the United States Supreme Court

Transcription:

Is Lawrence Still Good Law? EDWARD B. FOLEY* Whether Lawrence is overruled by a future Court, as Bowers was in Lawrence, depends on whether President Bush is successful in appointing to the Court justices who share Justice Scalia's jurisprudence. It would be preferable to have a more robust doctrine of stare decisis, which would require all justices to abide by precedents that they consider incorrect. Otherwise, constitutional law will lose its ability to serve as a check against a tyranny of the majority, because the public will perceive constitutional law as dependent on the identity of the justices who sit on the Court and will insist that the justices share the public's prevailing sentiments. Is Lawrence v. Texas 1 still good law? In a sense, what an odd question to ask. Lawrence is the most recent pronouncement by the U.S. Supreme Court on one of the most basic principles of American constitutional law, as that case was decided the very last day of the October 2002 Term. Yet, in a much more important and fundamental sense, none of us today has any idea whether Lawrence is still good law because that decision-like any decision in which Justices Scalia and Thomas dissented-is inherently unstable (and thus unreliable as precedent), pending the outcome of the presidential election. If President Bush is reelected and true to his word about his intent to appoint more Scalias and Thomases to the Supreme Court, then-pending the outcome of the intense confirmation battles that inevitably will follow-all could change. 2 Lawrence overruled Bowers v. Hardwick, 3 but there is no doubt that Scalia and Thomas, if given the opportunity, would quickly overrule Lawrence and reinstate Bowers. And there is no doubt that Scalia and Thomas will get this opportunity if three justices who share their jurisprudential views join the Court, as replacements for Justices O'Connor and Stevens and Chief Justice Rehnquist. They may not get this opportunity in another sodomy case right away. Rather, the opportunity could come in a gay adoption case, 4 or a military case, 5 or some other fact pattem. But in any such event, a five-member majority comprised of Scalia, * Robert M. Duncan/Jones Day Designated Professor of Law, Moritz College of Law at The Ohio State University. I Lawrence v. Texas, 39 U.S. 558 (2003). 2 This essay, written before the election, goes to press shortly after President Bush's victory. Its contemplation of a five-member majority of the Court sharing a Scalia/Thomas jurisprudence is even more appropriate now that the Republicans have secured 55 seats in the Senate, and the difficulty of a Democratic filibuster even greater. 3 Lawrence, 539 U.S. at 578 (overruling Bowers v. Hardwick, 478 U.S. 186 (1986)). 4 See, e.g., Lofton v. Sec'y of the Dep't of Children & Family Services, 358 F.3d 804 (1 th Cir. 2004). 5 See, e.g., United States v. Marcum, 60 M.J. 198 (C.A.A.F. 2004).

1134 OHIO STATE LA WJOURNAL [Vol. 65:!1133 Thomas, and like-minded justices would eviscerate Lawrence and, most probably, even overrule it explicitly. Thus, the only way to protect Lawrence from being overruled the way Bowers was-apart from making sure that Senator John Kerry defeats Bush-is for the Democrats in the Senate to be successful in using the filibuster, or the threat of a filibuster, to stop a reelected President Bush from appointing more Scalias and Thomases to the Supreme Court. But even if such a filibuster strategy is successful in the short term, it is an unpalatable prospect to think that the future of American constitutional law depends on the exercise of an inherently obstructionist device. There are several reasons for this: First, filibusters are inherently contentious, with the expectation that they are reserved for, as Thomas Mann has put it, "extreme" situations. 6 As a result, whichever party is using the filibuster is necessarily on the defensive. Contrast this situation with one in which the Constitution clearly specifies that the President needs two-thirds vote of the Senate in order to get his way (as with a treaty). 7 In that situation, there is nothing wrong with the Senators insisting that the President get the requisite supramajority support: in doing so, the Senate is exercising its expected constitutional function. By contrast, when the Constitution calls for advice and consent by a basic majority vote of the Senate, 8 then the use of the filibuster-even if constitutionally permissible as part of the Senate's intemal deliberative process-is out of step with the Constitution's expectations and thus is an inherently defensive and precarious posture, to be reserved for exceptional circumstances. Second, and somewhat related, it will be difficult for Democrats to sustain a successful filibuster strategy over the long term. The Democrats, after all, did not filibuster the nomination of Justice Thomas, and he made it to the Court. The public may not tolerate the Senate's refusal to vote up or down on the President's nominees to the Supreme Court. The Democrats' successful use of the filibuster over circuit court nominees, 9 which has proceeded below the public's radar 6 Thomas E. Mann, Estrada Caught in 'Poisonous' War Based on Ideology, ROLL CALL, Mar. 5, 2003, at 8. 7 U.S. CONST. art. II, 2 ("He shall have Power, by and with the Advice and Consent of the Senate, to make Treaties, provided two thirds of the Senators present concur.. "); see also U.S. CONST. art. I, 3 ("The Senate shall have the sole Power to try all Impeachments... And no Person shall be convicted without the Concurrence of two thirds of the Members present."). 8 U.S. CONST. art. II, 2 ("[H]e shall nominate, and by and with the Advice and Consent of the Senate, shall appoint... Judges of the supreme Court, and all other Officers of the United States, whose Appointments are not herein otherwise provided for, and which shall be established by Law."). 9 The ability to block the President's nomination of Miguel Estrada to the D.C. Circuit, despite his exemplary background (former Assistant to the Solicitor General, etc.), was the most muscle-flexing use of the filibuster so far. Compare Editorial, Victory for a Smear, WASH.

2004] IS LAWRENCE STILL GOOD LA W? 1135 screen by and large, does not necessarily mean that the Democrats will be equally successful in blocking Bush's nominations to the Supreme Court. And, of course, the Democrats might simply make a mistake in letting slip through a nominee who turns out to be-contrary to their predictions-another Scalia rather than another Kennedy. Thus, the odds of sustaining a successful filibuster strategy diminish over time, and if Bush (or a similarly conservative Republican President) gets to appoint Ginsburg's replacement, as well as the replacements of the three others I mentioned, the odds of Lawrence remaining good law grow ever slimmer. Third, and much more fundamentally, depending on the filibuster to protect the future of Lawrence exposes American constitutional law-at least its current form-as entirely dependent on the identity of the individuals who happen to sit on the Supreme Court. If we get our folks on the bench, then we get constitutional law to be the way we want it, but if we do not-and the other side gets to put its people on the Court-then constitutional law looks altogether different. Ultimately, the complete personification of constitutional law is not a sustainable vision, certainly not if constitutional law is supposed to perform its high-perhaps highest-function of protecting the rights of individuals and minorities against tyrannies of the majority.' 0 This is true because one of two things will occur to prevent the Court fiom exercising its crucial countermajoritarian function. One possibility is that the People simply will not tolerate the continued exercise of a countermajoritian judicial review on the ground that the outcome of this review is altogether subjective and dependent on the identity of the particular judges doing the reviewing. (If the justices disagree about the outcome of constitutional cases simply because of their differing personal views, then the personal views of the People themselves are just as valid and are entitled to prevail.) Alternatively, judicial review will lose its countermajoritarian character by virtue of the fact that the selection process for appointing new justices will have devolved into an intensely majoritarian political dynamic. The fight between the President and the Senate-as a result of the polarizing forces within each party canceling each other out-will end up in the confirmation of middle-of-the-road consensus nominees who reflect majoritarian sentiment about the content of individual and minority rights. A bench full of centrists who accurately reflect the median voter's vision of constitutional rights is not necessarily a bad form of democracy, but it is not the kind of republic our Constitution, with its written Bill of Rights, was designed to secure. The whole point of putting the Bill of Rights into the Constitution was so POST, Sept. 5, 2003, at A20; with Editorial, Miguel Estrada Bows Out, N.Y. TIMES, Sept. 5, 2003, at A 18. 10 The literature on the countermajoritarian function of the Court is large. Jim Fleming's thoughtful essay on "deliberate autonomy" would be as good as any place to begin. See James E. Fleming, Securing Deliberative Autonomy, 48 STAN. L. REV. 1 (1995).

1136 OHIO STATE LA WJOURNAL [Vol. 65:1133 that it would be enforced, by honest judges immune from political pressure and exercising the relatively objective craft of legal interpretation, against majoritarian sentiment that might conflict with those rights." A bunch of centrist judges who simply enforce the prevailing majority view does not conform to the animating vision of our Bill of Rights. How then do we get out of this situation and, instead, secure for the Bill of Rights-and for Lawrence as an interpretation of the Bill of Rights writ large-a firmer footing? (This fi-mer footing would not require use of the filibuster to prevent a President from repealing a Supreme Court decision that interprets the Bill of Rights in a way with which he disagrees.) The only way out that I see is to strengthen considerably the doctrine of stare decisis in constitutional cases. If there could develop a norm that justices are not permitted to overrule previous interpretations of the Bill of Rights simply because they disagree with those interpretations-no matter how strongly they disagree with those interpretations-and the justices themselves feel compelled to abide by this norm, then the norm would thwart the ability of a President to appoint a justice with the view of overturning a decision the President and his party dislikes. Ironically, Lawrence itself does not look so good from the perspective of a robust doctrine of stare decisis in constitutional cases. After all, Lawrence overruled Bowers essentially for the simple reason that Bowers was wrong. Really, really wrong, to be sure. But, essentially, for no other reason than that it was a serious misinterpretation of the Bill of Rights, properly understood. Given more time, I could offer several arguments about why overruling Bowers in Lawrence was actually consistent with a robust doctrine of stare decisis, in much the same way that overruling Gobitis 12 in Barnette 13 was. 14 But I know that my arguments would not convince the likes of Justices Scalia and Thomas, who saw Lawrence as a wholly unprincipled and inconsistent manipulation of the doctrine of stare decisis. If stare decisis is to work as a norm that truly prevents justices from overruling cases with which they strongly Congress: 11 James Madison himself made this point when he introduced the Bill of Rights in If they are incorporated into the Constitution, independent tribunals ofjustice will consider themselves in a peculiar manner the guardians of those rights; they will be an impenetrable bulwark against every assumption of power in the Legislative or Executive; they will be naturally led to resist every encroachment upon rights expressly stipulated for in the Constitution by the declaration of rights. 1 ANNALS OF CONG. 457 (1789). 12 Minersville School Dist. v. Gobbitis, 310 U.S. 586 (1940). 13 West Virginia State Bd. of Educ. v. Barnette, 319 U.S. 624 (1943). 14 Those were the two flag salute cases from the 1940s, and Barnette is the single most important case for setting forth the vision of judicial protection of individual and minority rights, as enshrined in the Bill of Rights, from tyrannies of the majority.

2004] IS LAWRENCE STILL GOOD LAW? disagree, then these justices must perceive their ideological opponents on the Court as being equally bound by precedents they find abhorrent. Thus, the only hope for securing Lawrence as a fixed feature of American constitutional law in the same way that Barnette is-so that Scalia and Thomas cannot overrule it no matter how strongly they might disagree with it-is for Lawrence to become woven into the fabric of constitutional law so tightly that it cannot be pulled out. A cluster of decisions needs to be built up around Lawrence, relying upon Lawrence, so that it is unassailable-like the incorporation doctrine is today. If that happens, and it also happens that the norm of a robust doctrine of stare decisis develops, then it is possible that future constitutional precedents interpreting the Bill of Rights will become protected against presidential assaults by virtue of this norm of stare decisis. Judicial interpretation of the Bill of Rights could then return to its intended countermajoritarian character, protecting individuals and minorities from tyrannies of the majority. To be sure, the body of precedent protected by stare decisis would have started with a majoritarian pedigree; it would have been put in place initially by centrist justices, like Kennedy and Breyer. But the written Bill of Rights itself had an initial majoritarian pedigree, as a result of the ratifying conventions. The whole point is to install a body of constitutional law that protects individual rights from future majorities that might become tyrannical, and that is a function a robust doctrine of stare decisis could perform with respect to a body of constitutional law that develops over time and includes Lawrence. However, and this is the essential point, for the norm of stare decisis to protect the countermajoritarian character of judicial review, then in the future liberal justices as well as conservative justices need to abide by-and be perceived as abiding by-this norm. In this sense, there can be no more decisions like Lawrence, overruling a precedent (like Bowers) that the liberals dislike. Otherwise, the gloves will come off again, so to speak, and constitutional law will be up for grabs, depending entirely on who wins the presidency and whether liberals in the Senate can block a conservative president's nominations. And then, any judicial decision that interprets the Bill of Rights to protect individuals or minorities from majoritarian tyranny will become precarious once more, and the Bill of Rights will not be able to serve the function it was designed to serve. And it may not get another chance.