MORALITY - evolutionary foundations and policy implications

Similar documents
Economics Marshall High School Mr. Cline Unit One BC

"Efficient and Durable Decision Rules with Incomplete Information", by Bengt Holmström and Roger B. Myerson

VOTING ON INCOME REDISTRIBUTION: HOW A LITTLE BIT OF ALTRUISM CREATES TRANSITIVITY DONALD WITTMAN ECONOMICS DEPARTMENT UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA

What is Fairness? Allan Drazen Sandridge Lecture Virginia Association of Economists March 16, 2017

Learning and Belief Based Trade 1

Compulsory versus Voluntary Voting Mechanisms: An Experimental Study

Supporting Information Political Quid Pro Quo Agreements: An Experimental Study

Norms of Distributive Justice in Rural Malawi

Introduction to Political Economy Problem Set 3

LEARNING FROM SCHELLING'S STRATEGY OF CONFLICT by Roger Myerson 9/29/2006

Self-Organization and Cooperation in Social Systems

Nordic Journal of Political Economy

Economic philosophy of Amartya Sen Social choice as public reasoning and the capability approach. Reiko Gotoh

REVIEW OF FOUNDATIONS OF HUMAN SOCIALITY: ECONOMIC EXPERIMENTS AND ETHNOGRAPHIC EVIDENCE FROM FIFTEEN SMALL-SCALE SOCIETIES

Are Dictators Averse to Inequality? *

ON IGNORANT VOTERS AND BUSY POLITICIANS

Some reflections on the role of moral reasoning in economics

An example of public goods

PARTIAL COMPLIANCE: SUNDAY SCHOOL MORALITY MEETS GAME THEORY.

Enriqueta Aragones Harvard University and Universitat Pompeu Fabra Andrew Postlewaite University of Pennsylvania. March 9, 2000

Reputation and Rhetoric in Elections

The Provision of Public Goods, and the Matter of the Revelation of True Preferences: Two Views

The Provision of Public Goods Under Alternative. Electoral Incentives

On the Irrelevance of Formal General Equilibrium Analysis

On Preferences for Fairness in Non-Cooperative Game Theory

the social dilemma?» Emmanuel SOL, Sylvie THORON, Marc WILLINGER

Chapter 4: Voting and Social Choice.

Goods, Games, and Institutions : A Reply

GAME THEORY. Analysis of Conflict ROGER B. MYERSON. HARVARD UNIVERSITY PRESS Cambridge, Massachusetts London, England

On Optimal Voting Rules under Homogeneous Preferences

International Cooperation, Parties and. Ideology - Very preliminary and incomplete

When users of congested roads may view tolls as unjust

Electing the President. Chapter 12 Mathematical Modeling

Cooperation, punishment, emergence of government and the tragedy of authorities

The Evolution of Preferences in Political Institutions

The Social Choice Theory: Can it be considered a Complete Political Theory?

policy-making. footnote We adopt a simple parametric specification which allows us to go between the two polar cases studied in this literature.

UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA, SAN DIEGO DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS

(67686) Mathematical Foundations of AI June 18, Lecture 6

Morals by Convention The rationality of moral behaviour

Course Title. Professor. Contact Information

Who is Homo Economicus and What is Wrong with Her?

Voter Participation with Collusive Parties. David K. Levine and Andrea Mattozzi

Topics on the Border of Economics and Computation December 18, Lecture 8

Lecture 16: Voting systems

Sampling Equilibrium, with an Application to Strategic Voting Martin J. Osborne 1 and Ariel Rubinstein 2 September 12th, 2002.

Political Science 200A Week 8. Social Dilemmas

Social Rankings in Human-Computer Committees

Jan Theodor Schikora: Bringing good and bad Whistle-blowers to the Lab

Final Exam. Thursday, December hour, 30 minutes

INSTITUTIONS AND THE PATH TO THE MODERN ECONOMY: LESSONS FROM MEDIEVAL TRADE, Avner Greif, 2006, Cambridge University Press, New York, 503 p.

DISCUSSION PAPERS Department of Economics University of Copenhagen

Political Economics II Spring Lectures 4-5 Part II Partisan Politics and Political Agency. Torsten Persson, IIES

Game Theory and the Law: The Legal-Rules-Acceptability Theorem (A rationale for non-compliance with legal rules)

Definition: Institution public system of rules which defines offices and positions with their rights and duties, powers and immunities p.

Electing the President. Chapter 17 Mathematical Modeling

INFORMATION AGGREGATION BY MAJORITY RULE: THEORY AND EXPERIMENTS 1. Krishna Ladha, Gary Miller and Joe Oppenheimer

Experimental Computational Philosophy: shedding new lights on (old) philosophical debates

1 Aggregating Preferences

Mohammad Hossein Manshaei 1393

Collective Decision with Costly Information: Theory and Experiments

Arrow s Impossibility Theorem on Social Choice Systems

Choosing Among Signalling Equilibria in Lobbying Games

I assume familiarity with multivariate calculus and intermediate microeconomics.

Property Rights and the Rule of Law

The Restoration of Welfare Economics

Handcuffs for the Grabbing Hand? Media Capture and Government Accountability by Timothy Besley and Andrea Prat (2006)

14.770: Introduction to Political Economy Lecture 11: Economic Policy under Representative Democracy

An Experimental Investigation of Delegation, Voting and the Provision of Public Goods

Information Acquisition and Voting Mechanisms: Theory and Evidence

Incentives and Social Norms in Household Behavior

Notes for an inaugeral lecture on May 23, 2002, in the Social Sciences division of the University of Chicago, by Roger Myerson.

Utilitarianism, Game Theory and the Social Contract

Coalitional Game Theory

Classical papers: Osborbe and Slivinski (1996) and Besley and Coate (1997)

Decision Making Procedures for Committees of Careerist Experts. The call for "more transparency" is voiced nowadays by politicians and pundits

Compulsory versus Voluntary Voting An Experimental Study

Rational Choice. Pba Dab. Imbalance (read Pab is greater than Pba and Dba is greater than Dab) V V

Voting with hands and feet: the requirements for optimal group formation

Compulsory versus Voluntary Voting An Experimental Study

Social Choice & Mechanism Design

A Public Philosophical Critique of Modern Economics

How much benevolence is benevolent enough?

Sequential Voting with Externalities: Herding in Social Networks

Jury Voting without Objective Probability

NBER WORKING PAPER SERIES PUBLIC GOODS AGREEMENTS WITH OTHER-REGARDING PREFERENCES. Charles D. Kolstad

Approval Voting and Scoring Rules with Common Values

In Defense of Liberal Equality

On Some Problems to Apply the Economic Model of Behaviour in Political Science

Policy Reputation and Political Accountability

Conditional Clauses in GHG Abatement Legislation

Individualism. Marquette University. John B. Davis Marquette University,

Voting rules: (Dixit and Skeath, ch 14) Recall parkland provision decision:

Lecture 7 A Special Class of TU games: Voting Games

The Political Economy of Trade Policy

THE TRUSTLAB PROJECT:

RESPONSE TO JAMES GORDLEY'S "GOOD FAITH IN CONTRACT LAW: The Problem of Profit Maximization"

A joint initiative of Ludwig-Maximilians University s Center for Economic Studies and the Ifo Institute for Economic Research

I. Identify and or Define. III. Games and Puzzles

Brown University Economics 2160 Risk, Uncertainty and Information Fall 2008 Professor: Roberto Serrano. General References

Transcription:

MORALITY - evolutionary foundations and policy implications Ingela Alger & Jörgen Weibull The State of Economics, The State of the World Conference 8-9 June 2016 at the World Bank

1 Introduction The discipline of economics has had a huge impact on policy all over the world Probably due to its methodological strength and unity goal-oriented individual behavior equilibrium The goal functions (utility, profit) are key ingredients

Since the days of Adam Smith s On the Wealth of Nations, economists usually assume selfishness, Homo oeconomicus, an opportunistic creature without morality, who takes any opportunity to enrich him- or herself As every individual [...] intends only his own gain [...] Why this premise of pure self-interest?

Does the assumption have empirical support? markets? In smaller groups? In large anonymous Behavioral and experimental economics say no in the second case

The evolutionary approach: preferences or moral values that lead to behaviors that give their carriers on average better material outcomes will spread (by biological or cultural mechanisms) Aim of this talk: discuss some recent theoretical results concerning the evolutionary foundations of human motivation examine implications for economics and policy

1.1 Background Milton Friedman (1953): unless the behavior of businessmen in some way or other approximated behavior consistent with the maximization of returns, it seems unlikely that they would remain in business for long More recently, game theorists have shown that Homo oeconomicus will prevail in strategic interactions if: the population is large individuals do not know each other s utility functions players are uniformly randomly matched

By contrast: in small populations, spitefulness arises [Schaffer (1988)] if individuals know each others preferences, Homo oeconomicus will not prevail [Schelling (1960), Fershtman & Judd (1987), Banerjee & Weibull (1995), Heifetz, Shannon & Spiegel (2007)] likewise, if the random matching is not uniform (think of geographic location, language, culture and religion) Homo oeconomicus will not prevail [Alger & Weibull (2016)]

1.2 The rest of the talk Describe a new class of preferences, which we call Homo moralis, and their evolutionary foundation Discuss implications of such preferences for canonical economic policy issues Compare with other social preferences suggested in behavioral economics Conclude and sum up

2 Evolution and morality 1. Individuals in a large population are now and then randomly matched into groups to interact with each other 2. The group interaction may involve elements of cooperation and/or conflict, asymmetric information, repetition, reciprocation, etc. 3. Material payoffs from the interaction are symmetric and aggregative in the sense that a participant s payoff depends only on own action and some aggregate of other group members actions 4. Each individual has a utility function, the expected value of which he or she seeks to maximize 5. Each individual s utility function is his or her private information

2.1 Definitions Stability: Generalizing Maynard-Smith s & Price s (1973) notion of an evolutionarily stable strategy (ESS), we analyze which utility functions, if any, are evolutionarily stable in the sense that, if almost all individuals in the population have such preferences the incumbents or residents these individuals would materially outperform individuals with other behaviorally distinct preferences the mutants in all equilibria Instability: A utility function is evolutionarily unstable if there exists another utility function such that, no matter how small its population share, there is some equilibrium in which the latter utility function materially outperforms the former Assortativity: The assortativity profile of the matching process is the probability vector, a, for the events that none, some, or all the individuals in a (vanishingly rare) mutant s group also are mutants

2.2 Results Evolution favors a particular class of utility functions that we call Homo moralis Such individuals attach some weight to their own material payoff but also to what can be interpreted as a generalized version of Kantian morality A Homo moralis maximizes a weighted average of many terms; each term being the material payoff that she would obtain if hypothetically the strategies of none, some, or all the other individuals in her group were replaced by her strategy We call the vector of these probability weights the individual s morality profile and denote it µ

Homo oeconomicus is one extreme member of this class, who pays attention only to his own material payoff Homo kantiensis is at the opposite extreme, who pays attention only to her hypothetical material payoff if everybody were to use her strategy A whole range of Homo moralis preferences lie between these extremes Act only according to that maxim whereby you can, at the same time, will that it should become a universal law. [Immanuel Kant, Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals, 1785]

Theorem 2.1 (Alger & Weibull, 2016) Homo moralis with morality profile µ = a is evolutionarily stable. Any preferences that are behaviorally distinct from those of Homo moralis with morality profile µ = a are evolutionarily unstable. The Homo moralis utility function is simple for pairwise interactions, and, in larger groups, under conditional independence of types; the morality profile then collapses to a single number, the degree of morality, 0 κ 1

2.3 Discussion Morality has been discussed by many economists, including Adam Smith, Francis Edgeworth, John Harsanyi, John Rawls, Ken Arrow, Amartya Sen,... However, to the best of our knowledge, Homo moralis preferences have not been discussed, or even known, before So how do individuals of this new species behave? What are the policy implications if economists models are populated not by Homo oeconomicus but by Homo moralis?

3 Morality and economics 3.1 Trust Trust varies across countries and over time, and trust is positively correlated with economic prosperity and growth [Algan and Cahuc (2010)] A tool for experimental study: the trust game [Berg et al. (1995), Cesarini et al. (2008)] One individual, the investor, can send some money to another individual, the trustee The sent amount is multiplied by some factor, usually three The trustee decides how much of the gross return to send back to the investor

If both are Homo oeconomicus, the trustee sends back no money and the investor therefore sends nothing Yet, in experiments the average investor sends a significant share of her endowment, and most trustees send back part of the gross return

What will Homo moralis do in such an interaction? If both are Homo kantiensis, the investor will invest all his endowment and the trustee will return half the gross return from investment For Homo moralis of intermediate degree of morality, 0 < κ < 1: Full investment obtains for sufficiently high degrees of morality κ As κ falls, investment begins to fall Less is paid back, and eventually, at some low κ, investment ceases

3.2 Environmental economics Arguably, the effectiveness of environmental policy depends to a large extent on human motivation Let s analyze the behavior of Homo moralis in an otherwise standard model of consumption with external effects [Musgrave (1959), Arrow (1970)] A continuum of consumers, two consumption goods, one environmentally neutral and one harmful The quality of the environment depends on average consumption of the second good, and hence each individual s impact on the environment is nil

Each consumer derives utility from own consumption and from the quality of the environment: u (x 1, x 2, x 2 ) What happens if all individuals are identical Homo moralis with u as their material payoff function?

Necessary first-order condition on each individual s consumption: ) ( u 2 x κ 1, x κ 2, ( xκ 2 ( u 1 x κ 1, x κ 2, ) = p κ u3 x κ 1, x κ 2, 2) ( xκ xκ 2 u 1 x κ 1, x κ 2, ). xκ 2 κ = 0 : Homo oeconomicus (no concern for the environment) κ = 1 : Homo kantiensis (socially optimal concern for the environment) 0 < κ < 1: Homo moralis refrains somewhat from consuming the environmentally harmful good (u 3 < 0) Policy if κ > 0: combine environmental taxes with public information about effects on the environment

3.3 Other examples 1. Democracy (a) Homo oeconomicus participates in general elections only if his expected benefit from participation exceeds his cost, and since the probability for being pivotal is small, the participation rate of Homo oeconomicus is low [Krishna & Morgan (2009)], and yet the actual participation rate in general elections is quite high in many countries (b) In committees where members have private information, Homo oeconomicus will typically not vote informatively even when all members have the same preferences, and thus judgment aggregation may fail [Condorcet (1785), Austen-Smith & Banks (1996)]

2. Public goods provision: free-riding and group size [Nosenzo, Quercia & Sefton (2015)] 3. Tax evasion: In some countries less evasion than would be rational for Homo oeconomicus, given the low conviction probability and relatively mild penalties [Sandmo (2005)]

4 Behavioral economics Many forms of human motivation have been proposed, and some tested: altruism [Becker (1974)] warm glow [Andreoni (1990)] conformity [Bernheim (1994)] conditional altruism [Levine (1998)] inequity aversion [Fehr and Schmidt (1999)] identity [Akerlof and Kranton (2000)] honesty [Alger & Ma (2003), Alger & Renault (2007), Demichelis & Weibull (2008)] norm adherence [Lindbeck, Nyberg & Weibull (1999), Brekke, Kverndokk & Nyborg (2003), Huck, Kübler & Weibull (2012)] image concern [Bénabou & Tirole (2006), Ellingsen & Johannesson (2008), Falk & Tirole (2016)]

All these models presume that individuals have a concern for something else than their pure material self-interest. By contrast, evolutionary theory may explain if and why, and may bring these many varieties to a common root. An avenue for future research!

5 Conclusion 1. Behavioral and experimental economics, other social and behavioral sciences, everyday observation, and introspection suggest that human motivation is more complex than narrow self-interest 2. The powerful analytical machinery of economics should not be abandoned because of this, but on the contrary be brought to use for agents with more complex motivations 3. Evolutionary stability theory suggests that evolution favors humans motivated by a combination of self-interest and a form of morality

4. By applying the powerful analytical tools of economics, new predictions and policy recommendations will follow, arguably leading to less emphasis on pecuniary incentives and more on information and education about the consequences of our actions for ourselves and others 5. Our results being purely theoretical, empirical and experimental work will be necessary to determine the empirical validity of Homo moralis

Final point: the status of economics in the eyes of the general public and in other social and behavioral sciences Economics textbooks may give the false impression that selfishness is part of economic rationality [Rubinstein (2006)] This misreading of economics probably hurts the reputation of economics If economists would instead use partly morally motivated agents, such as Homo moralis, then such misunderstandings could be avoided and the critique would fall flat to the ground Economic analysis would then not be prejudiced in favor of neither selfishness nor morality, but would allow for the whole spectrum of intermediate degrees

6 Post-presentation section Q: Are different social preferences distinguishable from each other and from morality? A stark contrast between altruism and morality is seen in the following simple coordination game: A B A 2, 2 0, 0 B 0, 0 1, 1 Suppose a society is trapped in equilibrium (B, B). Consider a small group of mutants who are altruists, then a small group of mutants who are Homo kantiensis